Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Form of the Good
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Superlative concept in the philosophy of Plato}} {{redirect|The Good|other uses|Good (disambiguation)}} {{Platonism}} The '''Form of the Good''', or more literally translated "the Idea of the Good" ({{lang|grc|ἡ τοῦ ἀγαθοῦ ἰδέα}}{{efn|[[Romanization of Greek|Transliteration]]: {{transliteration|grc|{{#Invoke:Ancient Greek|translit|ἡ τοῦ ἀγαθοῦ ἰδέα}}}}}}), is a concept in the philosophy of [[Plato]]. In Plato's [[Theory of Forms]], in which Forms are defined as perfect, eternal, and changeless concepts existing outside space and time, the Form of the Good is the mysterious highest Form and the source of all the other Forms. ==Uses in ''The Republic''== The first references that are seen in ''The Republic'' to the Form of the Good are within the conversation between [[Glaucon]] and [[Socrates]] (454 c–d). When he is trying to answer such difficult questions pertaining to the definition of [[justice]], Plato identifies that we should not "introduce every form of difference and sameness in nature" instead we must focus on "the one form of sameness and difference that was relevant to the particular ways of life themselves" which is the form of the Good. This form is the basis for understanding all other forms; it is what allows us to understand everything else. Through the conversation between Socrates and Glaucon (508 a–c), Plato analogizes the form of the Good with the sun as it is what allows us to see things. Here, Plato describes how the sun allows for sight. But he makes a very important distinction, "sun is not sight" but it is "the cause of sight itself." As the sun is in the visible realm, the form of Good is in the [[Intelligibility (philosophy)|intelligible]] realm. It is "what gives truth to the things known and the power to know to the knower". It is not only the "cause of knowledge and truth, it is also an object of knowledge". Plato identifies how the form of the Good allows for the cognizance to understand such difficult concepts as [[justice]]. He identifies [[knowledge]] and [[truth]] as important, but through Socrates (508d–e) says, "good is yet more prized". He then proceeds to explain "although the good is not being" it is "superior to it in rank and power", it is what "provides for knowledge and truth" (508e).<ref name=Reeve>{{cite book|last=Reeve|first=Plato; revised by C.D.C.|title=Republic|date=1992|publisher=Hackett Publ. Co|location=Indianapolis, Ind.|isbn=978-0-87220-136-1|edition=[2nd ed.].}}</ref> ==Scholarly analysis== Plato writes that the Form (or Idea) of the Good is the origin of knowledge although it is not knowledge itself, and from the Good, things that are just and true, gain their usefulness and value. Humans are compelled to pursue the good, but no one can hope to do this successfully without philosophical reasoning. According to Plato, true [[epistemology|knowledge]] is conversant, not about those material objects and imperfect intelligences which we meet within our daily interactions with all mankind, but rather it investigates the nature of those purer and more perfect patterns which are the models after which all created beings are formed. Plato supposes these perfect types to exist from all eternity and calls them the ''Forms'' or ''Ideas''.<ref>"Idea" from the Greek ἰδέα, often transliterated in the past but now typically translated as "character". The archaic sense must be distinguished from the modern sense meaning "thought". Cf. Russell: "It must not be supposed that 'ideas', in his sense, exist in minds, though they may be apprehended by minds.... The word 'idea' has acquired, in the course of time, many associations which are quite misleading when applied to Plato's 'ideas'. (''The Problems of Philosophy'', chapter 9).</ref> As these Forms cannot be perceived by human senses, whatever [[knowledge]] we attain of the Forms must be seen through the mind's eye (cf. ''[[Parmenides dialogue|Parmenides]]'' 132a), while ideas derived from the concrete world of flux are ultimately unsatisfactory and uncertain (see the ''[[Theaetetus (dialogue)|Theaetetus]]''). He maintains that degree of skepticism which denies all permanent authority to the evidence of sense. In essence, Plato suggests that justice, truth, equality, beauty, and many others ultimately derive from the Form of the Good. ===Aristotle's criticism=== [[Aristotle]] discusses the Forms of Good in critical terms several times in both of his major surviving ethical works, the ''[[Eudemian Ethics|Eudemian]]'' and ''[[Nicomachean Ethics]]''. Aristotle argues that Plato's Form of the Good does not apply to the physical world, for Plato does not assign "goodness" to anything in the existing world. Because Plato's Form of the Good does not explain events in the physical world, humans have no reason to believe that the Form of the Good exists and the Form of the Good is thereby irrelevant to human ethics.<ref name=plat>{{cite book|last=Fine|first=Gail|title=Plato on Knowledge and Forms|date=2003|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=New York|isbn=0-19-924559-2|page=350}}</ref> ===Other criticisms=== Plato's Form of the Good is often criticized as too general.<ref name=BAR>{{cite book|last=Reeve|first=C.D.C.|title=Blindness and reorientation : problems in Plato's Republic|date=2013|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=Oxford|isbn=978-0-19-993443-0|pages=165, 166|edition=1.}}</ref> Plato's Form of the Good does not define things in the physical world that are good, and therefore lacks connectedness to reality.<ref>{{cite book|last=Herman|first=Arthur|title=The cave and the light : Plato versus Aristotle, and the struggle for the soul of Western civilization|date=2013|publisher=Bantam Books|location=New York|isbn=978-0-553-80730-1|page=46|edition=First}}</ref> Because Plato's Form of the Good lacks instruction, or ways for the individual to be good, Plato's Form of the Good is not applicable to human ethics since there is no defined method for which goodness can be pursued. Through Socrates in ''The Republic'', Plato acknowledges the Form of the Good as an elusive concept and proposes that the Form of the Good be accepted as a hypothesis, rather than criticized for its weaknesses. According to Socrates in ''The Republic'', the only alternative to accepting a hypothesis is to refute all the objections against it, which is counterproductive in the process of contemplation.<ref name=BAR /> Aristotle along with other scholars sees the Form of the Good as synonymous with the idea of One.<ref name=Rev>{{cite journal|last=Jordan|first=R.W.|title=Platos Idee des Guten by Rafael Ferber Review|journal=The Classical Review|date=1986|volume=36|pages=65–67|jstor=3064234|doi=10.1017/s0009840x00105001|s2cid=170977273 }}</ref> Plato claims that Good is the highest Form, and that all objects aspire to be good.<ref>{{cite web|last=Banach|first=David|title=Plato's Theory of Forms|url=http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/platform.htm|access-date=2 May 2014|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20140803230257/http://www.anselm.edu/homepage/dbanach/platform.htm|archive-date=3 August 2014|url-status=dead}}</ref> Since Plato does not define good things, interpreting Plato's Form of the Good through the idea of One allows scholars to explain how Plato's Form of the Good relates to the physical world. According to this philosophy, in order for an object to belong to the Form of the Good, it must be One and have the proper harmony, uniformity, and order to be in its proper form.<ref name=Rev /> Philosopher Rafael Ferber dismissed Aristotle's view that the 'Good' is 'One' and wrote that the Form of the Good is self-contradictory. Ferber claimed that Plato's Form of the Good could be simultaneously defined and unknown, and be in a state of both "being" and "not being".<ref name=Rev /> Plato's Forms are also critiqued for being treated as the reason for all things, as opposed to being an essence in itself. Some scholars also believe that Plato intended the Form to be the essence of which things come into existence. These different interpretations of Plato's intention for the Form may be attributed to the idea that Plato did not have a systematic definition of the Form itself.<ref name=plat /> ==Influence== Plato's writings on the meaning of virtue and justice permeate through the [[Western philosophy|Western philosophical]] tradition.<ref name="The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2013 Edition)">{{cite web|last=Frede|first=Dorothy|title=Plato's Ethics: An Overview|date=16 September 2003|url=http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2013/entries/plato-ethics/|access-date=28 April 2014}}</ref> [[Plotinus]], the founder of [[neoplatonism]], had principles that were heavily influenced by the Good. His concept of 'the One' is equivalent to 'the Good' because it describes an ultimate [[ontological]] truth. 'The One' is both 'uncaused' and the cause of being for everything else in the universe. Plotinus compared his principle of 'the One' to an illuminating light, as Plato did with the Form of the Good. As a result of Plotinus' school of [[neoplatonism]], the bulk of understanding of [[Platonic philosophy]] until the 19th century came through Plotinus' interpretation of it. Many theologians and philosophers of Judaism, Christianity and Islam looked to the ideas of [[Platonism]] through the lens of Plotinus.<ref name="Stanford1">Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plotinus/ ''Plotinus''].</ref> Amphis, a comic playwright of Athens, has one of his characters say: "And as for the good that you are likely to get on her account, I know no more about it, master, than I do of the good of Plato."<ref>[[Diogenes Laërtius]] 3.27</ref> There is an ancient anecdotal tradition that Plato gave a public lecture entitled "On the Good" which so confused the audience that most walked out. At the end of the lecture Plato said to those hearers who remained: 'The Good is the One".<ref>Aristoxenus, ''Harmonics'' 30–31; see A. S. Riginos, ''Platonica'' (1976), pp. 124 ff., for further testimony.</ref> ==See also== *[[Aletheia|Aletheia (truth)]] *[[Plotinus#Influence|Influence of Plotinus]] *[[Seventh Letter]] *[[Summum bonum]] *[[The Allegory of the Cave]] *[[The divided line|The Divided Line]] *[[The One (Neoplatonism)|The One]] *[[Theory of forms]] *[[Transcendentals]] *[[Value (ethics)]] *[[Virtue]] ==Notes== {{Notelist}} ==References== {{Reflist}} {{Socrates navbox}} {{Plato navbox}} {{Good and evil}} [[Category:Republic (Plato)]] [[Category:Concepts in ancient Greek ethics]] [[Category:Concepts in ancient Greek epistemology]] [[Category:Concepts in ancient Greek metaphysics]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Efn
(
edit
)
Template:Good and evil
(
edit
)
Template:Lang
(
edit
)
Template:Notelist
(
edit
)
Template:Plato navbox
(
edit
)
Template:Platonism
(
edit
)
Template:Redirect
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Socrates navbox
(
edit
)