Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Gluing axiom
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Axiom specifying the requisites of a sheaf on a topological space}} In [[mathematics]], the '''gluing axiom''' is introduced to define what a [[sheaf (mathematics)|sheaf]] <math>\mathcal F</math> on a [[topological space]] <math>X</math> must satisfy, given that it is a [[presheaf]], which is by definition a [[contravariant functor]] :<math>{\mathcal F}:{\mathcal O}(X) \rightarrow C</math> to a category <math>C</math> which initially one takes to be the [[category of sets]]. Here <math>{\mathcal O}(X)</math> is the [[partial order]] of [[open set]]s of <math>X</math> ordered by [[inclusion map]]s; and considered as a category in the standard way, with a unique [[morphism]] :<math>U \rightarrow V</math> if <math>U</math> is a [[subset]] of <math>V</math>, and none otherwise. As phrased in the [[Sheaf (mathematics)|sheaf]] article, there is a certain axiom that <math>F</math> must satisfy, for any [[open cover]] of an open set of <math>X</math>. For example, given open sets <math>U</math> and <math>V</math> with [[union (set theory)|union]] <math>X</math> and [[intersection (set theory)|intersection]] <math>W</math>, the required condition is that :<math>{\mathcal F}(X)</math> is the subset of <math>{\mathcal F}(U) \times {\mathcal F}(V)</math> With equal image in <math>{\mathcal F}(W)</math> In less formal language, a [[Section (category theory)|section]] <math>s</math> of <math>F</math> over <math>X</math> is equally well given by a pair of sections :<math>(s', s'')</math> on <math>U</math> and <math>V</math> respectively, which 'agree' in the sense that <math>s'</math> and <math>s''</math> have a common image in <math>{\mathcal F}(W)</math> under the respective restriction maps :<math>{\mathcal F}(U) \rightarrow {\mathcal F}(W)</math> and :<math>{\mathcal F}(V) \rightarrow {\mathcal F}(W)</math>. The first major hurdle in sheaf theory is to see that this ''gluing'' or ''patching'' axiom is a correct abstraction from the usual idea in geometric situations. For example, a [[vector field]] is a section of a [[tangent bundle]] on a [[smooth manifold]]; this says that a vector field on the union of two open sets is (no more and no less than) vector fields on the two sets that agree where they overlap. Given this basic understanding, there are further issues in the theory, and some will be addressed here. A different direction is that of the [[Grothendieck topology]], and yet another is the logical status of 'local existence' (see [[Kripke–Joyal semantics]]). ==Removing restrictions on ''C''== To rephrase this definition in a way that will work in any category <math>C</math> that has sufficient structure, we note that we can write the objects and morphisms involved in the definition above in a diagram which we will call (G), for "gluing": :<math>{\mathcal F}(U)\rightarrow\prod_i{\mathcal F}(U_i){{{} \atop \longrightarrow}\atop{\longrightarrow \atop {}}}\prod_{i,j}{\mathcal F}(U_i\cap U_j)</math> Here the first map is the product of the restriction maps :<math>{res}_{U,U_{i}}:{\mathcal F}(U)\rightarrow{\mathcal F}(U_{i})</math> and each pair of arrows represents the two restrictions :<math>res_{U_i,U_i\cap U_j}:{\mathcal F}(U_i)\rightarrow{\mathcal F}(U_i\cap U_j)</math> and :<math>res_{U_j,U_i\cap U_j}:{\mathcal F}(U_j)\rightarrow{\mathcal F}(U_i\cap U_j)</math>. It is worthwhile to note that these maps exhaust all of the possible restriction maps among <math>U</math>, the <math>U_i</math>, and the <math>U_i\cap U_j</math>. The condition for <math>\mathcal F</math> to be a sheaf is that for any open set <math>U</math> and any collection of open sets <math>\{U_i\}_{i\in I}</math> whose union is <math>U</math>, the diagram (G) above is an [[Equaliser (mathematics)|equalizer]]. One way of understanding the gluing axiom is to notice that <math>U</math> is the [[colimit]] of the following diagram: :<math>\coprod_{i,j}U_i\cap U_j{{{} \atop \longrightarrow}\atop{\longrightarrow \atop {}}}\coprod_iU_i</math> The gluing axiom says that <math>\mathcal F</math> turns colimits of such diagrams into limits. ==Sheaves on a basis of open sets== In some categories, it is possible to construct a sheaf by specifying only some of its sections. Specifically, let <math>X</math> be a topological space with [[basis of a topological space|basis]] <math>\{ B_i \}_{i \in I}</math>. We can define a category <math>\mathcal{O}'(X)</math> to be the full subcategory of <math>{\mathcal O}(X)</math> whose objects are the <math>\{ B_i \}</math>. A '''B-sheaf''' on <math>X</math> with values in <math>C</math> is a contravariant functor :<math>{\mathcal F}:{\mathcal O}'(X) \rightarrow C</math> which satisfies the gluing axiom for sets in <math>{\mathcal O}'(X)</math>. That is, on a selection of open sets of <math>X</math>, <math>\mathcal F</math> specifies all of the sections of a sheaf, and on the other open sets, it is undetermined. B-sheaves are equivalent to sheaves (that is, the category of sheaves is equivalent to the category of B-sheaves).<ref>Vakil, [http://math.stanford.edu/~vakil/216blog/FOAGjun1113public.pdf Math 216: Foundations of algebraic geometry], 2.7.</ref> Clearly a sheaf on <math>X</math> can be restricted to a B-sheaf. In the other direction, given a B-sheaf <math>\mathcal F</math> we must determine the sections of <math>\mathcal F</math> on the other objects of <math>{\mathcal O}(X)</math>. To do this, note that for each open set <math>U</math>, we can find a collection <math>\{ B_j \}_{j \in J}</math> whose union is <math>U</math>. Categorically speaking, this choice makes <math>U</math> the colimit of the full subcategory of <math>{\mathcal O}'(X)</math> whose objects are <math>\{ B_j \}_{j \in J}</math>. Since <math>\mathcal F</math> is contravariant, we define <math>{\mathcal F}'(U)</math> to be the [[projective limit|limit]] of the <math>\{ {\mathcal F}(B_j) \}_{j \in J}</math> with respect to the restriction maps. (Here we must assume that this limit exists in <math>C</math>.) If <math>U</math> is a basic open set, then <math>U</math> is a terminal object of the above subcategory of <math>{\mathcal O}'(X)</math>, and hence <math>{\mathcal F}'(U) = {\mathcal F}(U)</math>. Therefore, <math>{\mathcal F}'</math> extends <math>\mathcal F</math> to a presheaf on <math>X</math>. It can be verified that <math>{\mathcal F}'</math> is a sheaf, essentially because every element of every open cover of <math>X</math> is a union of basis elements (by the definition of a basis), and every pairwise intersection of elements in an open cover of <math>X</math> is a union of basis elements (again by the definition of a basis). ==The logic of ''C''== The first needs of sheaf theory were for sheaves of [[abelian group]]s; so taking the category <math>C</math> as the [[category of abelian groups]] was only natural. In applications to geometry, for example [[complex manifold]]s and [[algebraic geometry]], the idea of a ''sheaf of [[local ring]]s'' is central. This, however, is not quite the same thing; one speaks instead of a [[locally ringed space]], because it is not true, except in trite cases, that such a sheaf is a functor into a [[category of local rings]]. It is the ''stalks'' of the sheaf that are local rings, not the collections of ''sections'' (which are [[ring (mathematics)|rings]], but in general are not close to being ''local''). We can think of a locally ringed space <math>X</math> as a parametrised family of local rings, depending on <math>x</math> in <math>X</math>. A more careful discussion dispels any mystery here. One can speak freely of a sheaf of abelian groups, or rings, because those are [[algebraic structure]]s (defined, if one insists, by an explicit [[signature (logic)|signature]]). Any category <math>C</math> having [[product (category theory)|finite product]]s supports the idea of a [[group object]], which some prefer just to call a group ''in'' <math>C</math>. In the case of this kind of purely algebraic structure, we can talk ''either'' of a sheaf having values in the category of abelian groups, or an ''abelian group in the category of sheaves of sets''; it really doesn't matter. In the local ring case, it does matter. At a foundational level we must use the second style of definition, to describe what a local ring means in a category. This is a logical matter: axioms for a local ring require use of [[existential quantification]], in the form that for any <math>r</math> in the ring, one of <math>r</math> and <math>1-r</math> is [[invertible]]. This allows one to specify what a 'local ring in a category' should be, in the case that the category supports enough structure. ==Sheafification== {{See also|Categorification}} {{See also|Sheaf (mathematics)#Turning a presheaf into a sheaf}} To turn a given presheaf <math>\mathcal P</math> into a sheaf <math>\mathcal F</math>, there is a standard device called '''''sheafification''''' or '''''sheaving'''''. The rough intuition of what one should do, at least for a presheaf of sets, is to introduce an equivalence relation, which makes equivalent data given by different covers on the overlaps by refining the covers. One approach is therefore to go to the [[Stalk of a sheaf#Stalks of a sheaf|stalk]]s and recover the [[sheaf space]] of the ''best possible'' sheaf <math>\mathcal F</math> produced from <math>\mathcal P</math>. This use of language strongly suggests that we are dealing here with [[adjoint functors]]. Therefore, it makes sense to observe that the sheaves on <math>X</math> form a [[full subcategory]] of the presheaves on <math>X</math>. Implicit in that is the statement that a [[morphism of sheaves]] is nothing more than a [[natural transformation]] of the sheaves, considered as functors. Therefore, we get an abstract characterisation of sheafification as [[left adjoint]] to the inclusion. In some applications, naturally, one does need a description. In more abstract language, the sheaves on <math>X</math> form a [[reflective subcategory]] of the presheaves (Mac Lane–[[Ieke Moerdijk|Moerdijk]] ''Sheaves in Geometry and Logic'' p. 86). In [[topos theory]], for a [[Lawvere–Tierney topology]] and its sheaves, there is an analogous result (ibid. p. 227). ==Other gluing axioms== The gluing axiom of sheaf theory is rather general. One can note that the [[Mayer–Vietoris axiom]] of [[homotopy theory]], for example, is a special case. == See also == *[[Gluing schemes]] == Notes == {{reflist}} == References == *{{EGA | book=I}} {{DEFAULTSORT:Gluing Axiom}} [[Category:General topology]] [[Category:Limits (category theory)]] [[Category:Homological algebra]] [[Category:Mathematical axioms]] [[Category:Differential topology]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:EGA
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:See also
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)