Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Infimum and supremum
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{short description|Greatest lower bound and least upper bound}} [[Image:Infimum illustration.svg|thumb|upright=1.2|A set <math>P</math> of real numbers (hollow and filled circles), a subset <math>S</math> of <math>P</math> (filled circles), and the infimum of <math>S.</math> Note that for [[Total order|totally ordered]] finite sets, the infimum and the [[Maximum_and_minimum#In_relation_to_sets|minimum]] are equal.]] [[Image:Supremum illustration.svg|thumb|upright=1.2|A set <math>A</math> of real numbers (blue circles), a set of upper bounds of <math>A</math> (red diamond and circles), and the smallest such upper bound, that is, the supremum of <math>A</math> (red diamond).]] In mathematics, the '''infimum''' (abbreviated '''inf'''; {{plural form}}: '''infima''') of a [[subset]] <math>S</math> of a [[partially ordered set]] <math>P</math> is the [[greatest element]] in <math>P</math> that is less than or equal to each element of <math>S,</math> if such an element exists.<ref name="BabyRudin">{{cite book|first=Walter|last=Rudin|author-link=Walter Rudin|title=Principles of Mathematical Analysis|publisher=McGraw-Hill|edition=3rd|year=1976|isbn=0-07-054235-X|chapter=Chapter 1 The Real and Complex Number Systems|format=print|page=[https://archive.org/details/principlesofmath00rudi/page/n15 4]|url=https://archive.org/details/principlesofmath00rudi|url-access=registration}}</ref> If the infimum of <math>S</math> exists, it is unique, and if ''b'' is a [[Upper and lower bounds|lower bound]] of <math>S</math>, then ''b'' is less than or equal to the infimum of <math>S</math>. Consequently, the term ''greatest lower bound'' (abbreviated as {{em|GLB}}) is also commonly used.<ref name="BabyRudin" /> The '''supremum''' (abbreviated '''sup'''; {{plural form}}: '''suprema''') of a subset <math>S</math> of a partially ordered set <math>P</math> is the [[least element]] in <math>P</math> that is greater than or equal to each element of <math>S,</math> if such an element exists.<ref name=BabyRudin /> If the supremum of <math>S</math> exists, it is unique, and if ''b'' is an [[Upper and lower bounds|upper bound]] of <math>S</math>, then the supremum of <math>S</math> is less than or equal to ''b''. Consequently, the supremum is also referred to as the ''least upper bound'' (or {{em|LUB}}).<ref name=BabyRudin /> The infimum is, in a precise sense, [[Duality (order theory)|dual]] to the concept of a supremum. Infima and suprema of [[real number]]s are common special cases that are important in [[Mathematical analysis|analysis]], and especially in [[Lebesgue integration]]. However, the general definitions remain valid in the more abstract setting of [[order theory]] where arbitrary partially ordered sets are considered. The concepts of infimum and supremum are close to [[minimum]] and [[maximum]], but are more useful in analysis because they better characterize special sets which may have {{em|no minimum or maximum}}. For instance, the set of [[positive real numbers]] <math>\R^+</math> (not including <math>0</math>) does not have a minimum, because any given element of <math>\R^+</math> could simply be divided in half resulting in a smaller number that is still in <math>\R^+.</math> There is, however, exactly one infimum of the positive real numbers relative to the real numbers: <math>0,</math> which is smaller than all the positive real numbers and greater than any other real number which could be used as a lower bound. An infimum of a set is always and only defined relative to a superset of the set in question. For example, there is no infimum of the positive real numbers inside the positive real numbers (as their own superset), nor any infimum of the positive real numbers inside the complex numbers with positive real part. == Formal definition == [[File:Illustration of supremum.svg|thumb|upright=1.2|supremum = least upper bound]] A {{em|lower bound}} of a subset <math>S</math> of a [[partially ordered set]] <math>(P, \leq)</math> is an element <math>y</math> of <math>P</math> such that * <math>y \leq x</math> for all <math>x \in S.</math> A lower bound <math>a</math> of <math>S</math> is called an {{em|infimum}} (or {{em|greatest lower bound}}, or [[Join and meet|{{em|meet}}]]) of <math>S</math> if * for all lower bounds <math>y</math> of <math>S</math> in <math>P,</math> <math>y \leq a</math> (<math>a</math> is larger than any other lower bound). Similarly, an {{em|upper bound}} of a subset <math>S</math> of a partially ordered set <math>(P, \leq)</math> is an element <math>z</math> of <math>P</math> such that * <math>z \geq x</math> for all <math>x \in S.</math> An upper bound <math>b</math> of <math>S</math> is called a {{em|supremum}} (or {{em|least upper bound}}, or [[Join and meet|{{em|join}}]]) of <math>S</math> if * for all upper bounds <math>z</math> of <math>S</math> in <math>P,</math> <math>z \geq b</math> (<math>b</math> is less than any other upper bound). == Existence and uniqueness == Infima and suprema do not necessarily exist. Existence of an infimum of a subset <math>S</math> of <math>P</math> can fail if <math>S</math> has no lower bound at all, or if the set of lower bounds does not contain a greatest element. (An example of this is the subset <math>\{ x \in \mathbb{Q} : x^2 < 2 \}</math> of <math>\mathbb{Q}</math>. It has upper bounds, such as 1.5, but no supremum in <math>\mathbb{Q}</math>.) Consequently, partially ordered sets for which certain infima are known to exist become especially interesting. For instance, a [[Lattice (order)|lattice]] is a partially ordered set in which all {{em|nonempty finite}} subsets have both a supremum and an infimum, and a [[complete lattice]] is a partially ordered set in which {{em|all}} subsets have both a supremum and an infimum. More information on the various classes of partially ordered sets that arise from such considerations are found in the article on [[Completeness (order theory)|completeness properties]]. If the supremum of a subset <math>S</math> exists, it is unique. If <math>S</math> contains a greatest element, then that element is the supremum; otherwise, the supremum does not belong to <math>S</math> (or does not exist). Likewise, if the infimum exists, it is unique. If <math>S</math> contains a least element, then that element is the infimum; otherwise, the infimum does not belong to <math>S</math> (or does not exist). == Relation to maximum and minimum elements == The infimum of a subset <math>S</math> of a partially ordered set <math>P,</math> assuming it exists, does not necessarily belong to <math>S.</math> If it does, it is a [[Minimal element|minimum or least element]] of <math>S.</math> Similarly, if the supremum of <math>S</math> belongs to <math>S,</math> it is a [[Maximal element|maximum or greatest element]] of <math>S.</math> For example, consider the set of negative real numbers (excluding zero). This set has no greatest element, since for every element of the set, there is another, larger, element. For instance, for any negative real number <math>x,</math> there is another negative real number <math>\tfrac{x}{2},</math> which is greater. On the other hand, every real number greater than or equal to zero is certainly an upper bound on this set. Hence, <math>0</math> is the least upper bound of the negative reals, so the supremum is 0. This set has a supremum but no greatest element. However, the definition of [[Maximal element|maximal and minimal elements]] is more general. In particular, a set can have many maximal and minimal elements, whereas infima and suprema are unique. Whereas maxima and minima must be members of the subset that is under consideration, the infimum and supremum of a subset need not be members of that subset themselves. === Minimal upper bounds === Finally, a partially ordered set may have many minimal upper bounds without having a least upper bound. Minimal upper bounds are those upper bounds for which there is no strictly smaller element that also is an upper bound. This does not say that each minimal upper bound is smaller than all other upper bounds, it merely is not greater. The distinction between "minimal" and "least" is only possible when the given order is not a [[Totally ordered set|total]] one. In a totally ordered set, like the real numbers, the concepts are the same. As an example, let <math>S</math> be the set of all finite subsets of natural numbers and consider the partially ordered set obtained by taking all sets from <math>S</math> together with the set of [[integer]]s <math>\Z</math> and the set of positive real numbers <math>\R^+,</math> ordered by subset inclusion as above. Then clearly both <math>\Z</math> and <math>\R^+</math> are greater than all finite sets of natural numbers. Yet, neither is <math>\R^+</math> smaller than <math>\Z</math> nor is the converse true: both sets are minimal upper bounds but none is a supremum. === Least-upper-bound property === {{main|Least-upper-bound property}} The {{em|least-upper-bound property}} is an example of the aforementioned [[Completeness (order theory)|completeness properties]] which is typical for the set of real numbers. This property is sometimes called {{em|Dedekind completeness}}. If an ordered set <math>S</math> has the property that every nonempty subset of <math>S</math> having an upper bound also has a least upper bound, then <math>S</math> is said to have the least-upper-bound property. As noted above, the set <math>\R</math> of all real numbers has the least-upper-bound property. Similarly, the set <math>\Z</math> of integers has the least-upper-bound property; if <math>S</math> is a nonempty subset of <math>\Z</math> and there is some number <math>n</math> such that every element <math>s</math> of <math>S</math> is less than or equal to <math>n,</math> then there is a least upper bound <math>u</math> for <math>S,</math> an integer that is an upper bound for <math>S</math> and is less than or equal to every other upper bound for <math>S.</math> A [[well-order]]ed set also has the least-upper-bound property, and the empty subset has also a least upper bound: the minimum of the whole set. An example of a set that {{em|lacks}} the least-upper-bound property is <math>\Q,</math> the set of rational numbers. Let <math>S</math> be the set of all rational numbers <math>q</math> such that <math>q^2 < 2.</math> Then <math>S</math> has an upper bound (<math>1000,</math> for example, or <math>6</math>) but no least upper bound in <math>\Q</math>: If we suppose <math>p \in \Q</math> is the least upper bound, a contradiction is immediately deduced because between any two reals <math>x</math> and <math>y</math> (including [[square root of 2|<math>\sqrt{2}</math>]] and <math>p</math>) there exists some rational <math>r,</math> which itself would have to be the least upper bound (if <math>p > \sqrt{2}</math>) or a member of <math>S</math> greater than <math>p</math> (if <math>p < \sqrt{2}</math>). Another example is the [[hyperreals]]; there is no least upper bound of the set of positive infinitesimals. There is a corresponding {{em|greatest-lower-bound property}}; an ordered set possesses the greatest-lower-bound property if and only if it also possesses the least-upper-bound property; the least-upper-bound of the set of lower bounds of a set is the greatest-lower-bound, and the greatest-lower-bound of the set of upper bounds of a set is the least-upper-bound of the set. If in a partially ordered set <math>P</math> every bounded subset has a supremum, this applies also, for any set <math>X,</math> in the function space containing all functions from <math>X</math> to <math>P,</math> where <math>f \leq g</math> if and only if <math>f(x) \leq g(x)</math> for all <math>x \in X.</math> For example, it applies for real functions, and, since these can be considered special cases of functions, for real <math>n</math>-tuples and sequences of real numbers. The [[least-upper-bound property]] is an indicator of the suprema. == Infima and suprema of real numbers == In [[Mathematical analysis|analysis]], infima and suprema of subsets <math>S</math> of the [[real numbers]] are particularly important. For instance, the negative [[real number]]s do not have a greatest element, and their supremum is <math>0</math> (which is not a negative real number).<ref name=BabyRudin /> The [[completeness of the real numbers]] implies (and is equivalent to) that any bounded nonempty subset <math>S</math> of the real numbers has an infimum and a supremum. If <math>S</math> is not bounded below, one often formally writes <math>\inf_{} S = -\infty.</math> If <math>S</math> is [[Empty set|empty]], one writes <math>\inf_{} S = +\infty.</math> ===Properties=== If <math>A</math> is any set of real numbers then <math>A \neq \varnothing</math> if and only if <math>\sup A \geq \inf A,</math> and otherwise <math>-\infty = \sup \varnothing < \inf \varnothing = \infty.</math>{{sfn|Rockafellar|Wets|2009|pp=1-2}} '''Set inclusion''' If <math>A \subseteq B</math> are sets of real numbers then <math>\inf A \geq \inf B</math> (if <math>A = \varnothing</math> this reads as <math>\inf B \le \infty</math>) and <math>\sup A \leq \sup B.</math> '''Image under functions''' If <math>f \colon \mathbb{R} \to \mathbb{R}</math> is a nonincreasing function, then <math>f (\inf(S)) \le \inf (f (S))</math> and <math>\sup(f(S))</math>, where the image is defined as <math>f(S) \,\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}\, \{f(s) : s \in S\}.</math> '''Identifying infima and suprema''' If the infimum of <math>A</math> exists (that is, <math>\inf A</math> is a real number) and if <math>p</math> is any real number then <math>p = \inf A</math> if and only if <math>p</math> is a lower bound and for every <math>\epsilon > 0</math> there is an <math>a_\epsilon \in A</math> with <math>a_\epsilon < p + \epsilon.</math> Similarly, if <math>\sup A</math> is a real number and if <math>p</math> is any real number then <math>p = \sup A</math> if and only if <math>p</math> is an upper bound and if for every <math>\epsilon > 0</math> there is an <math>a_\epsilon \in A</math> with <math>a_\epsilon > p - \epsilon.</math> '''Relation to limits of sequences''' If <math>S \neq \varnothing</math> is any non-empty set of real numbers then there always exists a non-decreasing sequence <math>s_1 \leq s_2 \leq \cdots</math> in <math>S</math> such that <math>\lim_{n \to \infty} s_n = \sup S.</math> Similarly, there will exist a (possibly different) non-increasing sequence <math>s_1 \geq s_2 \geq \cdots</math> in <math>S</math> such that <math>\lim_{n \to \infty} s_n = \inf S.</math> In particular, the infimum and supremum of a set belong to its [[Closure (topology)|closure]] if <math>\inf S \in \mathbb{R}</math> then <math>\inf S \in \bar{S}</math> and if <math>\sup S \in \mathbb{R}</math> then <math>\sup S \in \bar{S}</math> Expressing the infimum and supremum as a limit of a such a sequence allows theorems from various branches of mathematics to be applied. Consider for example the well-known fact from [[topology]] that if <math>f</math> is a [[Continuous function (topology)|continuous function]] and <math>s_1, s_2, \ldots</math> is a sequence of points in its domain that converges to a point <math>p,</math> then <math>f\left(s_1\right), f\left(s_2\right), \ldots</math> necessarily converges to <math>f(p).</math> It implies that if <math>\lim_{n \to \infty} s_n = \sup S</math> is a real number (where all <math>s_1, s_2, \ldots</math> are in <math>S</math>) and if <math>f</math> is a continuous function whose domain contains <math>S</math> and <math>\sup S,</math> then <math display=block>f(\sup S) = f\left(\lim_{n \to \infty} s_n\right) = \lim_{n \to \infty} f\left(s_n\right),</math> which (for instance) guarantees<ref group=note>Since <math>f\left(s_1\right), f\left(s_2\right), \ldots</math> is a sequence in <math>f(S)</math> that converges to <math>f(\sup S),</math> this guarantees that <math>f(\sup S)</math> belongs to the [[Closure (topology)|closure]] of <math>f(S).</math></ref> that <math>f(\sup S)</math> is an [[adherent point]] of the set <math>f(S) \,\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}\, \{f(s) : s \in S\}.</math> If in addition to what has been assumed, the continuous function <math>f</math> is also an increasing or [[non-decreasing function]], then it is even possible to conclude that <math>\sup f(S) = f(\sup S).</math> This may be applied, for instance, to conclude that whenever <math>g</math> is a real (or [[Complex number|complex]]) valued function with domain <math>\Omega \neq \varnothing</math> whose [[sup norm]] <math>\|g\|_\infty \,\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}\, \sup_{x \in \Omega} |g(x)|</math> is finite, then for every non-negative real number <math>q,</math> <math display=block>\|g\|_\infty^q ~\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}~ \left(\sup_{x \in \Omega} |g(x)|\right)^q = \sup_{x \in \Omega} \left(|g(x)|^q\right)</math> since the map <math>f : [0, \infty) \to \R</math> defined by <math>f(x) = x^q</math> is a continuous non-decreasing function whose domain <math>[0, \infty)</math> always contains <math>S := \{|g(x)| : x \in \Omega\}</math> and <math>\sup S \,\stackrel{\scriptscriptstyle\text{def}}{=}\, \|g\|_\infty.</math> Although this discussion focused on <math>\sup,</math> similar conclusions can be reached for <math>\inf</math> with appropriate changes (such as requiring that <math>f</math> be non-increasing rather than non-decreasing). Other [[Norm (mathematics)|norms]] defined in terms of <math>\sup</math> or <math>\inf</math> include the [[weak Lp space|weak <math>L^{p,w}</math> space]] norms (for <math>1 \leq p < \infty</math>), the norm on [[Lp space|Lebesgue space]] <math>L^\infty(\Omega, \mu),</math> and [[operator norm]]s. Monotone sequences in <math>S</math> that converge to <math>\sup S</math> (or to <math>\inf S</math>) can also be used to help prove many of the formula given below, since addition and multiplication of real numbers are continuous operations. ===Arithmetic operations on sets=== The following formulas depend on a notation that conveniently generalizes arithmetic operations on sets. Throughout, <math>A, B \subseteq \R</math> are sets of real numbers. '''Sum of sets''' The [[Minkowski sum]] of two sets <math>A</math> and <math>B</math> of real numbers is the set <math display=block>A + B ~:=~ \{a + b : a \in A, b \in B\}</math> consisting of all possible arithmetic sums of pairs of numbers, one from each set. The infimum and supremum of the Minkowski sum satisfy, if <math>A \ne \varnothing \ne B</math> <math display=block>\inf (A + B) = (\inf A) + (\inf B)</math> and <math display=block>\sup (A + B) = (\sup A) + (\sup B).</math> '''Product of sets''' The multiplication of two sets <math>A</math> and <math>B</math> of real numbers is defined similarly to their Minkowski sum: <math display=block>A \cdot B ~:=~ \{a \cdot b : a \in A, b \in B\}.</math> If <math>A</math> and <math>B</math> are nonempty sets of positive real numbers then <math>\inf (A \cdot B) = (\inf A) \cdot (\inf B)</math> and similarly for suprema <math>\sup (A \cdot B) = (\sup A) \cdot (\sup B).</math><ref name="zakon">{{cite book|title=Mathematical Analysis I|first=Elias|last=Zakon|pages=39β42|publisher=Trillia Group|date=2004|url=http://www.trillia.com/zakon-analysisI.html}}</ref> '''Scalar product of a set''' The product of a real number <math>r</math> and a set <math>B</math> of real numbers is the set <math display=block>r B ~:=~ \{r \cdot b : b \in B\}.</math> If <math>r > 0</math> then <math display=block>\inf (r \cdot A) = r (\inf A) \quad \text{ and } \quad \sup (r \cdot A) = r (\sup A),</math> while if <math>r < 0</math> then <math display=block>\inf (r \cdot A) = r (\sup A) \quad \text{ and } \quad \sup (r \cdot A) = r (\inf A).</math> In the case <math>r = 0</math>, one has, if <math>A \ne \varnothing</math> <math display=block> \inf (0 \cdot A) = 0 \quad \text{ and } \quad \sup (0 \cdot A) = 0 </math> Using <math>r = -1</math> and the notation <math display=inline>-A := (-1) A = \{- a : a \in A\},</math> it follows that, <math display=block>\inf (- A) = - \sup A \quad \text{ and } \quad \sup (- A) = - \inf A.</math> '''Multiplicative inverse of a set''' For any set <math>S</math> that does not contain <math>0,</math> let <math display=block>\frac{1}{S} ~:=\; \left\{\tfrac{1}{s} : s \in S\right\}.</math> If <math>S \subseteq (0, \infty)</math> is non-empty then <math display=block>\frac{1}{\sup_{} S} ~=~ \inf_{} \frac{1}{S}</math> where this equation also holds when <math>\sup_{} S = \infty</math> if the definition <math>\frac{1}{\infty} := 0</math> is used.<ref group="note" name="DivisionByInfinityOr0">The definition <math>\tfrac{1}{\infty} := 0</math> is commonly used with the [[extended real number]]s; in fact, with this definition the equality <math>\tfrac{1}{\sup_{} S} = \inf_{} \tfrac{1}{S}</math> will also hold for any non-empty subset <math>S \subseteq (0, \infty].</math> However, the notation <math>\tfrac{1}{0}</math> is usually left undefined, which is why the equality <math>\tfrac{1}{\inf_{} S} = \sup_{} \tfrac{1}{S}</math> is given only for when <math>\inf_{} S > 0.</math></ref> This equality may alternatively be written as <math>\frac{1}{\displaystyle\sup_{s \in S} s} = \inf_{s \in S} \tfrac{1}{s}.</math> Moreover, <math>\inf_{} S = 0</math> if and only if <math>\sup_{} \tfrac{1}{S} = \infty,</math> where if<ref group=note name="DivisionByInfinityOr0" /> <math>\inf_{} S > 0,</math> then <math>\tfrac{1}{\inf_{} S} = \sup_{} \tfrac{1}{S}.</math> == Duality == If one denotes by <math>P^{\operatorname{op}}</math> the partially-ordered set <math>P</math> with the [[Converse relation|opposite order relation]]; that is, for all <math>x \text{ and } y,</math> declare: <math display=block>x \leq y \text{ in } P^{\operatorname{op}} \quad \text{ if and only if } \quad x \geq y \text{ in } P,</math> then infimum of a subset <math>S</math> in <math>P</math> equals the supremum of <math>S</math> in <math>P^{\operatorname{op}}</math> and vice versa. For subsets of the real numbers, another kind of duality holds: <math>\inf S = - \sup (- S),</math> where <math>-S := \{ -s ~:~ s \in S \}.</math> == Examples == === Infima === * The infimum of the set of numbers <math>\{2, 3, 4\}</math> is <math>2.</math> The number <math>1</math> is a lower bound, but not the greatest lower bound, and hence not the infimum. * More generally, if a set has a smallest element, then the smallest element is the infimum for the set. In this case, it is also called the [[minimum]] of the set. * <math>\inf \{ 1, 2, 3, \ldots \} = 1.</math> * <math>\inf \{ x \in \R : 0 < x < 1 \} = 0.</math> * <math>\inf \left\{ x \in \Q : x^3 > 2 \right\} = \sqrt[3]{2}.</math> * <math>\inf \left\{ (-1)^n + \tfrac{1}{n} : n = 1, 2, 3, \ldots \right\} = -1.</math> * If <math>\left(x_n\right)_{n=1}^{\infty}</math> is a decreasing sequence with limit <math>x,</math> then <math>\inf x_n = x.</math> === Suprema === * The supremum of the set of numbers <math>\{1, 2, 3\}</math> is <math>3.</math> The number <math>4</math> is an upper bound, but it is not the least upper bound, and hence is not the supremum. * <math>\sup \{ x \in \R : 0 < x < 1\} = \sup \{ x \in \R : 0 \leq x \leq 1\} = 1.</math> * <math>\sup \left\{ (-1)^n - \tfrac{1}{n} : n = 1, 2, 3, \ldots \right\} = 1.</math> * <math>\sup \{ a + b : a \in A, b \in B \} = \sup A + \sup B.</math> * <math>\sup \left\{ x \in \Q : x^2 < 2 \right\} = \sqrt{2}.</math> In the last example, the supremum of a set of [[Rational number|rationals]] is [[Irrational number|irrational]], which means that the rationals are [[Complete space|incomplete]]. One basic property of the supremum is <math display=block>\sup \{ f(t) + g(t) : t \in A \} ~\leq~ \sup \{ f(t) : t \in A \} + \sup \{ g(t) : t \in A \}</math> for any [[Functional (mathematics)|functionals]] <math>f</math> and <math>g.</math> The supremum of a subset <math>S</math> of <math>(\N, \mid\,)</math> where <math>\,\mid\,</math> denotes "[[Divisor|divides]]", is the [[lowest common multiple]] of the elements of <math>S.</math> The supremum of a set <math>S</math> containing subsets of some set <math>X</math> is the [[Union (set theory)|union]] of the subsets when considering the partially ordered set <math>(P(X), \subseteq)</math>, where <math>P</math> is the [[power set]] of <math>X</math> and <math>\,\subseteq\,</math> is [[subset]]. == See also == {{Commons category}} * {{annotated link|Essential supremum and essential infimum}} * {{annotated link|Greatest element and least element}} * {{annotated link|Maximal and minimal elements}} * {{annotated link|Limit superior and limit inferior}} (infimum limit) * {{annotated link|Upper and lower bounds}} == Notes == {{reflist|group=note}} == References == {{reflist}} * {{Rockafellar Wets Variational Analysis 2009 Springer}} <!-- {{sfn|Rockafellar|Wets|2009|p=}} --> ==External links== * {{springer|title=Upper and lower bounds|id=p/u095810}} * {{MathWorld|Supremum|author=Breitenbach, Jerome R.|author2=Weisstein, Eric W.|name-list-style=amp}} {{Lp spaces}} [[Category:Order theory]] [[Category:Superlatives]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Annotated link
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Commons category
(
edit
)
Template:Em
(
edit
)
Template:Lp spaces
(
edit
)
Template:Main
(
edit
)
Template:MathWorld
(
edit
)
Template:PAGENAMEBASE
(
edit
)
Template:Plural form
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Rockafellar Wets Variational Analysis 2009 Springer
(
edit
)
Template:Sfn
(
edit
)
Template:SfnRef
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Sister project
(
edit
)
Template:Springer
(
edit
)