Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Large cardinal
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Other uses of|Cardinal}} {{Short description|Set theory concept}} In the mathematical field of [[set theory]], a '''large cardinal property''' is a certain kind of property of [[Transfinite number|transfinite]] [[cardinal number]]s. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, bigger than the least α such that α=ω<sub>α</sub>). The proposition that such cardinals exist cannot be proved in the most common [[axiomatization]] of set theory, namely [[ZFC]], and such propositions can be viewed as ways of measuring how "much", beyond ZFC, one needs to assume to be able to prove certain desired results. In other words, they can be seen, in [[Dana Scott]]'s phrase, as quantifying the fact "that if you want more you have to assume more".<ref>{{cite book|last=Bell|first=J. L.|title=Boolean-Valued Models and Independence Proofs in Set Theory|url=https://archive.org/details/booleanvaluedmod0000bell|url-access=registration|pages=viii|publisher=Oxford University Press|year=1985|isbn=0-19-853241-5|no-pp=true}}</ref> There is a rough convention that results provable from ZFC alone may be stated without hypotheses, but that if the proof requires other assumptions (such as the existence of large cardinals), these should be stated. Whether this is simply a linguistic convention, or something more, is a controversial point among distinct philosophical schools (see [[#Motivations and epistemic status|Motivations and epistemic status]] below). A '''{{vanchor|large cardinal axiom}}''' is an axiom stating that there exists a cardinal (or perhaps many of them) with some specified large cardinal property. Most working set theorists believe that the large cardinal axioms that are currently being considered are [[consistent]] with ZFC.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Joel |first=Hamkins |date=2022-12-24 |title=Does anyone still seriously doubt the consistency of ZFC? |url=https://mathoverflow.net/questions/437195/does-anyone-still-seriously-doubt-the-consistency-of-zfc |publisher=[[MathOverflow]]}}</ref> These axioms are strong enough to imply the consistency of ZFC. This has the consequence (via [[Gödel's incompleteness theorem|Gödel's second incompleteness theorem]]) that their consistency with ZFC cannot be proven in ZFC (assuming ZFC is consistent). There is no generally agreed precise definition of what a large cardinal property is, though essentially everyone agrees that those in the [[list of large cardinal properties]] are large cardinal properties. ==Partial definition== A necessary condition for a property of cardinal numbers to be a ''large cardinal property'' is that the existence of such a cardinal is not known to be inconsistent with [[ZFC|ZF]] and that such a cardinal ''Κ''<!--Kappa--> would be an uncountable initial ordinal for which [[constructible universe|''L''<sub>''Κ''</sub>]]<!--Kappa--> is a model of ZFC. If ZFC is [[consistent]], then ZFC does ''not'' imply that any such large cardinals exist. ==Hierarchy of consistency strength== A remarkable observation about large cardinal axioms is that they appear to occur in strict [[linear order]] by [[consistency strength]]. That is, no exception is known to the following: Given two large cardinal axioms ''A''<sub>1</sub> and ''A''<sub>2</sub>, exactly one of three things happens: #Unless ZFC is inconsistent, ZFC+''A''<sub>1</sub> is consistent if and only if ZFC+''A''<sub>2</sub> is consistent; #ZFC+''A''<sub>1</sub> proves that ZFC+''A''<sub>2</sub> is consistent; or #ZFC+''A''<sub>2</sub> proves that ZFC+''A''<sub>1</sub> is consistent. These are mutually exclusive, unless one of the theories in question is actually inconsistent. In case 1, we say that ''A''<sub>1</sub> and ''A''<sub>2</sub> are [[Equiconsistency|equiconsistent]]. In case 2, we say that ''A''<sub>1</sub> is consistency-wise stronger than ''A''<sub>2</sub> (vice versa for case 3). If ''A''<sub>2</sub> is stronger than ''A''<sub>1</sub>, then ZFC+''A''<sub>1</sub> cannot prove ZFC+''A''<sub>2</sub> is consistent, even with the additional hypothesis that ZFC+''A''<sub>1</sub> is itself consistent (provided of course that it really is). This follows from [[Gödel's second incompleteness theorem]]. The observation that large cardinal axioms are linearly ordered by consistency strength is just that, an observation, not a theorem. (Without an accepted definition of large cardinal property, it is not subject to proof in the ordinary sense.) Also, it is not known in every case which of the three cases holds. [[Saharon Shelah]] has asked, "[i]s there some theorem explaining this, or is our vision just more uniform than we realize?" [[W. Hugh Woodin|Woodin]], however, deduces this from the [[Ω-conjecture]], the main unsolved problem of his [[Ω-logic]]. It is also noteworthy that many combinatorial statements are exactly equiconsistent with some large cardinal rather than, say, being intermediate between them. The order of consistency strength is not necessarily the same as the order of the size of the smallest witness to a large cardinal axiom. For example, the existence of a [[huge cardinal]] is much stronger, in terms of consistency strength, than the existence of a [[supercompact cardinal]], but assuming both exist, the first huge is smaller than the first supercompact. ==Motivations and epistemic status== Large cardinals are understood in the context of the [[von Neumann universe]] V, which is built up by [[transfinite induction|transfinitely iterating]] the [[powerset]] operation, which collects together all [[subset]]s of a given set. Typically, [[Model theory|models]] in which large cardinal axioms ''fail'' can be seen in some natural way as submodels of those in which the axioms hold. For example, if there is an [[inaccessible cardinal]], then "cutting the universe off" at the height of the first such cardinal yields a [[universe (mathematics)|universe]] in which there is no inaccessible cardinal. Or if there is a [[measurable cardinal]], then iterating the ''definable'' powerset operation rather than the full one yields [[Gödel's constructible universe]], L, which does not satisfy the statement "there is a measurable cardinal" (even though it contains the measurable cardinal as an ordinal). Thus, from a certain point of view held by many set theorists (especially those inspired by the tradition of the [[Cabal (set theory)|Cabal]]), large cardinal axioms "say" that we are considering all the sets we're "supposed" to be considering, whereas their negations are "restrictive" and say that we're considering only some of those sets. Moreover the consequences of large cardinal axioms seem to fall into natural patterns (see Maddy, "Believing the Axioms, II"). For these reasons, such set theorists tend to consider large cardinal axioms to have a preferred status among extensions of ZFC, one not shared by axioms of less clear motivation (such as [[Martin's axiom]]) or others that they consider intuitively unlikely (such as [[V=L|V = L]]). The hardcore [[Philosophy of mathematics#Mathematical realism|realists]] in this group would state, more simply, that large cardinal axioms are ''true''. This point of view is by no means universal among set theorists. Some [[Philosophy of mathematics#Formalism|formalists]] would assert that standard set theory is by definition the study of the consequences of ZFC, and while they might not be opposed in principle to studying the consequences of other systems, they see no reason to single out large cardinals as preferred. There are also realists who deny that [[ontological maximalism]] is a proper motivation, and even believe that large cardinal axioms are false. And finally, there are some who deny that the negations of large cardinal axioms ''are'' restrictive, pointing out that (for example) there can be a [[transitive set]] model in L that believes there exists a measurable cardinal, even though L itself does not satisfy that proposition. ==See also== * [[List of large cardinal properties]] ==Notes== {{Reflist}} ==References== * {{cite book|author=Drake, F. R.|title=Set Theory: An Introduction to Large Cardinals (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics; V. 76)|publisher=Elsevier Science Ltd|year=1974|isbn=0-444-10535-2}} * {{cite book|author=Jech, Thomas|title=Set theory, third millennium edition (revised and expanded)|publisher=Springer|year=2002|isbn=3-540-44085-2|author-link=Thomas Jech}} * {{cite book|last=Kanamori|first=Akihiro|year=2003|author-link=Akihiro Kanamori|publisher=Springer|title=The Higher Infinite : Large Cardinals in Set Theory from Their Beginnings|title-link=The Higher Infinite|edition=2nd|isbn=3-540-00384-3}} *{{citation|last1=Kanamori|first1=Akihiro|first2=M. |last2=Magidor |chapter=The evolution of large cardinal axioms in set theory |series=Lecture Notes in Mathematics |publisher =Springer Berlin / Heidelberg |volume =669 |chapter-url=http://math.bu.edu/people/aki/e.pdf | access-date=September 25, 2022 |title=Higher Set Theory |year=1978 |isbn =978-3-540-08926-1 |doi =10.1007/BFb0103104 |doi-access= |pages=99–275 }} * {{cite journal|last=Maddy|first=Penelope|title=Believing the Axioms, I|journal=Journal of Symbolic Logic|volume=53|issue=2|year=1988|pages=481–511|author-link=Penelope Maddy|doi=10.2307/2274520|jstor=2274520}} * {{cite journal|last=Maddy|first=Penelope|title=Believing the Axioms, II|journal=Journal of Symbolic Logic|volume=53|issue=3|year=1988|pages=736–764|doi=10.2307/2274569|jstor=2274569|s2cid=16544090 }} * {{cite arXiv|last=Shelah|first=Saharon|title=The Future of Set Theory|year=2002|eprint=math/0211397|author-link=Saharon Shelah}} * {{cite journal|last=Solovay|first=Robert M. |author2=William N. Reinhardt |author3-link=Akihiro Kanamori |author3=Akihiro Kanamori|year=1978|title=Strong axioms of infinity and elementary embeddings|journal=Annals of Mathematical Logic|volume=13|issue=1|pages=73–116|author-link=Robert M. Solovay|url=http://math.bu.edu/people/aki/d.pdf|doi=10.1016/0003-4843(78)90031-1|author2-link=William Nelson Reinhardt |doi-access=free}} * {{cite journal|last=Woodin|first=W. Hugh|title=The continuum hypothesis, part II|journal=Notices of the American Mathematical Society|volume=48|issue=7|year=2001|pages=681–690}} ==External links== * [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/large-cardinals-determinacy/ "Large Cardinals and Determinacy"] at the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] {{Set theory}} {{Mathematical logic}} [[Category:Axioms of set theory]] [[Category:Large cardinals| ]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:Cite arXiv
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Mathematical logic
(
edit
)
Template:Other uses of
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Set theory
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Vanchor
(
edit
)