Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Level of measurement
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{short description|Distinction between nominal, ordinal, interval and ratio variables}} {{Distinguish|Units of measurement|Level sensor|Level (logarithmic quantity)}} {{Redirect|Nominal variable|the economics usage|Real versus nominal value (economics)}} '''Level of measurement''' or '''scale of measure''' is a classification that describes the nature of information within the values assigned to [[dependent and independent variables|variables]].<ref name="Koch 2008">{{cite encyclopedia |editor-last=Kirch |editor-first=Wilhelm |encyclopedia=Encyclopedia of Public Health |volume=2 |pages=851–852 |publisher=Springer |date=2008 |isbn=978-1-4020-5613-0 |doi=10.1007/978-1-4020-5614-7_1971|chapter=Level of Measurement }}</ref> Psychologist [[Stanley Smith Stevens]] developed the best-known classification with four levels, or scales, of measurement: [[#Nominal level|nominal]], [[#Ordinal scale|ordinal]], [[#Interval scale|interval]], and [[#Ratio scale|ratio]].<ref name = "Koch 2008" /><ref name = "Stevens 1946">{{cite journal |last=Stevens |first=S. S. |s2cid=4667599 |author-link=Stanley Smith Stevens |title=On the Theory of Scales of Measurement |journal=[[Science (journal)|Science]] |volume=103 |issue=2684 |pages=677–680 |date=7 June 1946 |pmid=17750512 |doi=10.1126/science.103.2684.677 |bibcode=1946Sci...103..677S }}</ref> This framework of distinguishing levels of measurement originated in psychology and has since had a complex history, being adopted and extended in some disciplines and by some scholars, and criticized or rejected by others.<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Michell | first1 = J. | year = 1986 | title = Measurement scales and statistics: a clash of paradigms | doi = 10.1037/0033-2909.100.3.398| journal = Psychological Bulletin | volume = 100 | issue = 3| pages = 398–407 }}</ref> Other classifications include those by Mosteller and [[John Tukey|Tukey]],<ref name = "Mosteller">{{cite book | last1 = Mosteller | first1 = Frederick | last2=Tukey | first2=John W.| title = Data analysis and regression : a second course in statistics | url = https://archive.org/details/dataanalysisregr0000most | publisher = Addison-Wesley Pub. Co | location = Reading, Mass | year = 1977 | isbn = 978-0201048544 }}</ref> and by Chrisman.<ref name="Chrisman">{{cite journal |last=Chrisman |first=Nicholas R. |title=Rethinking Levels of Measurement for Cartography |journal=Cartography and Geographic Information Science |volume=25 |issue=4 |date=1998 |pages=231–242 |issn=1523-0406 |doi=10.1559/152304098782383043 |bibcode=1998CGISy..25..231C }}{{subscription required|via=[[Taylor & Francis]]}}</ref> == Stevens's typology == === Overview === Stevens proposed his typology in a 1946 ''[[Science (journal)|Science]]'' article titled "On the theory of scales of measurement".<ref name="Stevens 1946"/> In that article, Stevens claimed that all [[measurement]] in science was conducted using four different types of scales that he called "nominal", "ordinal", "interval", and "ratio", unifying both "[[Qualitative property|qualitative]]" (which are described by his "nominal" type) and "[[Quantitative property|quantitative]]" (to a different degree, all the rest of his scales). The concept of scale types later received the mathematical rigour that it lacked at its inception with the work of mathematical psychologists Theodore Alper (1985, 1987), Louis Narens (1981a, b), and [[R. Duncan Luce]] (1986, 1987, 2001). As Luce (1997, p. 395) wrote: {{blockquote|S. S. Stevens (1946, 1951, 1975) claimed that what counted was having an interval or ratio scale. Subsequent research has given meaning to this assertion, but given his attempts to invoke scale type ideas it is doubtful if he understood it himself ... '''no measurement theorist I know accepts Stevens's broad definition of measurement ...''' in our view, the only sensible meaning for 'rule' is empirically testable laws about the attribute.}} ==== Comparison ==== {| class="wikitable" ! Incremental<br/> progress ! Measure property ! Mathematical<br/> operators ! Advanced<br/> operations ! Central<br/> tendency ! Variability |- | Nominal | Classification, membership | =, ≠ | [[aggregate data|Grouping]] | [[Mode (statistics)|Mode]] | [[Qualitative variation]] |- | Ordinal | Comparison, level | >, < | [[Sorting]] | [[Median]] | [[Range (statistics)|Range]],<br/> [[interquartile range]] |- | Interval | Difference, affinity | +, − | [[Measurement#Methodology|Comparison to a standard]] | [[Arithmetic mean]] | [[Deviation (statistics)|Deviation]] |- | Ratio | Magnitude, amount | ×, / | [[Ratio]] | [[Geometric mean]],<br/> [[harmonic mean]] | [[Coefficient of variation]],<br/> [[studentized range]] |} === Nominal level === <!--Do not change this name. It is pointed to by other Wikipedia articles.--> A nominal scale consists only of a number of distinct classes or categories, for example: [Cat, Dog, Rabbit]. Unlike the other scales, no kind of relationship between the classes can be relied upon. Thus measuring with the nominal scale is equivalent to [[classifying]]. Nominal measurement may differentiate between items or subjects based only on their names or (meta-)categories and other qualitative classifications they belong to. Thus it has been argued that even [[dichotomy|dichotomous]] data relies on a [[constructivist epistemology]]. In this case, discovery of an exception to a classification can be viewed as progress. Numbers may be used to represent the variables but the numbers do not have numerical value or relationship: for example, a [[globally unique identifier]]. Examples of these classifications include gender, nationality, ethnicity, language, genre, style, biological species, and form.<ref>Nominal measures are based on sets and depend on categories, a la Aristotle: {{cite web |url=http://www4.uwsp.edu/geo/faculty/gmartin/geog476/Lecture/BeySt.htm |title=Beyond Stevens: A revised approach to measurement for geographic information |first=Nicholas |last=Chrisman |date=March 1995 |access-date=2014-08-25}}</ref><ref>"Invariably one came up against fundamental physical limits to the accuracy of measurement. ... The art of physical measurement seemed to be a matter of compromise, of choosing between reciprocally related uncertainties. ... Multiplying together the conjugate pairs of uncertainty limits mentioned, however, I found that they formed invariant products of not one but two distinct kinds. ... The first group of limits were calculable ''a priori'' from a specification of the instrument. The second group could be calculated only ''a posteriori'' from a specification of what was ''done'' with the instrument. ... In the first case each unit [of information] would add one additional ''dimension'' (conceptual category), whereas in the second each unit would add one additional ''atomic fact''.", – pp. 1–4: MacKay, Donald M. (1969), ''Information, Mechanism, and Meaning'', Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, {{ISBN|0-262-63-032-X}}</ref> In a university one could also use residence hall or department affiliation as examples. Other concrete examples are * in [[grammar]], the [[parts of speech]]: noun, verb, preposition, article, pronoun, etc. * in politics, [[power projection]]: hard power, soft power, etc. * in biology, the [[taxonomic rank]]s below domains: kingdom, phylum, class, etc. * in [[software engineering]], type of [[Trap (computing)|fault]]: specification faults, design faults, and code faults Nominal scales were often called qualitative scales, and measurements made on qualitative scales were called qualitative data. However, the rise of qualitative research has made this usage confusing. If numbers are assigned as labels in nominal measurement, they have no specific numerical value or meaning. No form of arithmetic computation (+, −, ×, etc.) may be performed on nominal measures. The nominal level is the lowest measurement level used from a statistical point of view. ====Mathematical operations==== [[Equality (mathematics)|Equality]] and other operations that can be defined in terms of equality, such as [[inequality (mathematics)|inequality]] and [[set membership]], are the only [[non-trivial]] [[operation (mathematics)|operation]]s that generically apply to objects of the nominal type. ====Central tendency==== The [[mode (statistics)|mode]], i.e. the ''most common'' item, is allowed as the measure of [[central tendency]] for the nominal type. On the other hand, the [[median]], i.e. the ''middle-ranked'' item, makes no sense for the nominal type of data since ranking is meaningless for the nominal type.<ref>{{cite journal|last1=Manikandan|first1=S.|title=Measures of central tendency: Median and mode|journal=Journal of Pharmacology and Pharmacotherapeutics|date=2011|volume=2|issue=3|pages=214–5|doi=10.4103/0976-500X.83300|pmc=3157145|pmid=21897729 |doi-access=free }}</ref> ===Ordinal scale=== {{anchor |Ordinal scale}}<!-- This section is linked from [[IQ classification]] and other articles --> {{further|Ordinal data}} The ordinal type allows for [[rank order]] (1st, 2nd, 3rd, etc.) by which data can be sorted but still does not allow for a relative ''degree of difference'' between them. Examples include, on one hand, '''dichotomous''' data with dichotomous (or dichotomized) values such as "sick" vs. "healthy" when measuring health, "guilty" vs. "not-guilty" when making judgments in courts, "wrong/false" vs. "right/true" when measuring [[truth value]], and, on the other hand, '''non-dichotomous''' data consisting of a spectrum of values, such as "completely agree", "mostly agree", "mostly disagree", "completely disagree" when measuring [[opinion]]. The ordinal scale places events in order, but there is no attempt to make the intervals of the scale equal in terms of some rule. Rank orders represent ordinal scales and are frequently used in research relating to qualitative phenomena. A student's rank in his graduation class involves the use of an ordinal scale. One has to be very careful in making a statement about scores based on ordinal scales. For instance, if Devi's position in his class is 10th and Ganga's position is 40th, it cannot be said that Devi's position is four times as good as that of Ganga. Ordinal scales only permit the ranking of items from highest to lowest. Ordinal measures have no absolute values, and the real differences between adjacent ranks may not be equal. All that can be said is that one person is higher or lower on the scale than another, but more precise comparisons cannot be made. Thus, the use of an ordinal scale implies a statement of "greater than" or "less than" (an equality statement is also acceptable) without our being able to state how much greater or less. The real difference between ranks 1 and 2, for instance, may be more or less than the difference between ranks 5 and 6. Since the numbers of this scale have only a rank meaning, the appropriate measure of central tendency is the median. A percentile or quartile measure is used for measuring dispersion. Correlations are restricted to various rank order methods. Measures of statistical significance are restricted to the non-parametric methods (R. M. Kothari, 2004). ==== Central tendency ==== The [[median]], i.e. ''middle-ranked'', item is allowed as the measure of [[central tendency]]; however, the mean (or average) as the measure of [[central tendency]] is not allowed. The [[mode (statistics)|mode]] is allowed. In 1946, Stevens observed that psychological measurement, such as measurement of opinions, usually operates on ordinal scales; thus means and standard deviations have no [[Validity (logic)|validity]], but they can be used to get ideas for how to improve [[operationalization]] of variables used in [[questionnaire]]s. Most [[psychological]] data collected by [[psychometric]] instruments and tests, measuring [[cognitive]] and other abilities, are ordinal, although some theoreticians have argued they can be treated as interval or ratio scales. However, there is little [[prima facie]] evidence to suggest that such attributes are anything more than ordinal (Cliff, 1996; Cliff & Keats, 2003; Michell, 2008).<ref>*{{Cite book |title=Statistical Theories of Mental Test Scores |last1=Lord |first1=Frederic M. |last2=Novick |first2=Melvin R. |last3=Birnbaum |first3=Allan |year=1968 |publisher=Addison-Wesley |location=Reading, MA |lccn=68011394 |page=21 |quote=Although, formally speaking, interval measurement can always be obtained by specification, such specification is theoretically meaningful only if it is implied by the theory and model relevant to the measurement procedure.}} *{{cite journal |author=William W. Rozeboom |title=Reviewed Work: ''Statistical Theories of Mental Test Scores'' |journal=American Educational Research Journal |volume=6 |issue=1 |date=January 1969 |pages=112–116 |jstor=1162101}}</ref> In particular,<ref>{{cite book |title=Handbook of Parametric and Nonparametric Statistical Procedures |last=Sheskin |first=David J. |year=2007 |edition=Fourth |publisher=Chapman & Hall/CRC |location=Boca Raton |isbn=978-1-58488-814-7 |page=3 |quote=Although in practice IQ and most other human characteristics measured by psychological tests (such as anxiety, introversion, self esteem, etc.) are treated as interval scales, many researchers would argue that they are more appropriately categorized as ordinal scales. Such arguments would be based on the fact that such measures do not really meet the requirements of an interval scale, because it cannot be demonstrated that equal numerical differences at different points on the scale are comparable. }}</ref> IQ scores reflect an ordinal scale, in which all scores are meaningful for comparison only.<ref>{{cite book |title=Psychology: An Introduction |last=Mussen |first=Paul Henry |year=1973 |publisher=Heath |location=Lexington (MA) |isbn=978-0-669-61382-7 |page=[https://archive.org/details/psychologyintrod00muss/page/363 363] |quote=The I.Q. is essentially a rank; there are no true "units" of intellectual ability. |url=https://archive.org/details/psychologyintrod00muss/page/363 }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |title=The WISC-III Companion: A Guide to Interpretation and Educational Intervention |last=Truch |first=Steve |year=1993 |publisher=Pro-Ed |location=Austin (TX) |isbn=978-0-89079-585-9 |page=35 |quote=An IQ score is not an equal-interval score, as is evident in Table A.4 in the WISC-III manual. }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |title=Measuring Intelligence: Facts and Fallacies |url=https://archive.org/details/measuringintelli00bart |url-access=registration |last=Bartholomew |first=David J. |author-link=D.J. Bartholomew |year=2004 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |location=Cambridge |isbn=978-0-521-54478-8 |quote=When we come to quantities like IQ or g, as we are presently able to measure them, we shall see later that we have an even lower level of measurement—an ordinal level. This means that the numbers we assign to individuals can only be used to rank them—the number tells us where the individual comes in the rank order and nothing else. |page=[https://archive.org/details/measuringintelli00bart/page/n65 50] }}</ref> There is no absolute zero, and a 10-point difference may carry different meanings at different points of the scale.<ref>{{cite book |author=Eysenck, Hans |title=Intelligence: A New Look |location=New Brunswick (NJ) |publisher=[[Transaction Publishers]] |isbn=978-1-56000-360-1 |year=1998 |pages=24–25 |quote=Ideally, a scale of measurement should have a true zero-point and identical intervals. . . . Scales of hardness lack these advantages, and so does IQ. There is no absolute zero, and a 10-point difference may carry different meanings at different points of the scale. }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |title=IQ and Human Intelligence |last=Mackintosh |first=N. J. |author-link=Nicholas Mackintosh |year=1998 |publisher=Oxford University Press |location=Oxford |isbn=978-0-19-852367-3 |pages=[https://archive.org/details/iqhumanintellige00mack/page/30 30–31] |quote=In the jargon of psychological measurement theory, IQ is an ordinal scale, where we are simply rank-ordering people. ... It is not even appropriate to claim that the 10-point difference between IQ scores of 110 and 100 is the same as the 10-point difference between IQs of 160 and 150 |url=https://archive.org/details/iqhumanintellige00mack/page/30 }}</ref> ===Interval scale=== The interval type allows for defining the ''degree of difference'' between measurements, but not the ratio between measurements. Examples include ''[[temperature scale]]s'' with the [[degree Celsius|Celsius scale]], which has two defined points (the freezing and boiling point of water at specific conditions) and then separated into 100 intervals, ''date'' when measured from an arbitrary epoch (such as AD), ''location'' in Cartesian coordinates, and ''direction'' measured in degrees from true or magnetic north. Ratios are not meaningful since 20 °C cannot be said to be "twice as hot" as 10 °C (unlike temperature in [[kelvin]]s), nor can multiplication/division be carried out between any two dates directly. However, ''ratios of differences'' can be expressed; for example, one difference can be twice another; for example, the ten-degree difference between 15 °C and 25 °C is twice the five-degree difference between 17 °C and 22 °C. Interval type variables are sometimes also called "scaled variables", but the formal mathematical term is an [[affine space]] (in this case an [[affine line]]). ====Central tendency and statistical dispersion==== The [[mode (statistics)|mode]], [[median]], and [[arithmetic mean]] are allowed to measure central tendency of interval variables, while measures of statistical dispersion include [[range (statistics)|range]] and [[standard deviation]]. Since one can only divide by ''differences'', one cannot define measures that require some ratios, such as <!--- the studentized range or. --- Error: studentized range is a ratio of a difference (range) to a root-mean-square difference (standard DEVIATION from the mean ---> the [[coefficient of variation]]. More subtly, while one can define [[Moment (mathematics)|moments]] about the [[Origin (mathematics)|origin]], only central moments are meaningful, since the choice of origin is arbitrary. One can define [[standardized moment]]s, since ratios of differences are meaningful, but one cannot define the coefficient of variation, since the mean is a moment about the origin, unlike the standard deviation, which is (the square root of) a central moment. === Ratio scale === :''See also'': {{section link|Positive real numbers#Ratio scale}} The ratio type takes its name from the fact that measurement is the estimation of the ratio between a magnitude of a continuous quantity and a [[unit of measurement]] of the same kind (Michell, 1997, 1999). Most measurement in the physical sciences and engineering is done on ratio scales. Examples include [[mass]], [[length]], [[Time|duration]], [[plane angle]], [[energy]] and [[electric charge]]. In contrast to interval scales, ratios can be compared using [[division (mathematics)|division]]. Very informally, many ratio scales can be described as specifying "how much" of something (i.e. an amount or magnitude). Ratio scales are often used to express an [[order of magnitude]] such as for temperature in [[Orders of magnitude (temperature)]]. ==== Central tendency and statistical dispersion ==== The [[geometric mean]] and the [[harmonic mean]] are allowed to measure the central tendency, in addition to the mode, median, and arithmetic mean. The [[studentized range]] and the [[coefficient of variation]] are allowed to measure statistical dispersion. All statistical measures are allowed because all necessary mathematical operations are defined for the ratio scale. == Debate on Stevens's typology == While Stevens's typology is widely adopted, it is still being challenged by other theoreticians, particularly in the cases of the nominal and ordinal types (Michell, 1986).<ref name = "Velleman and Wilkinson 1993">{{cite journal |last1=Velleman |first1=Paul F. |last2=Wilkinson |first2=Leland |journal=The American Statistician | title=Nominal, ordinal, interval, and ratio typologies are misleading |volume=47 | number=1 | year = 1993 |pages=65–72 |doi=10.2307/2684788 | jstor=2684788 }}</ref> Duncan (1986), for example, objected to the use of the word ''measurement'' in relation to the nominal type and Luce (1997) disagreed with Stevens's definition of measurement. On the other hand, Stevens (1975) said of his own definition of measurement that "the assignment can be any consistent rule. The only rule not allowed would be random assignment, for randomness amounts in effect to a nonrule". Hand says, "Basic psychology texts often begin with Stevens's framework and the ideas are ubiquitous. Indeed, the essential soundness of his hierarchy has been established for representational measurement by mathematicians, determining the invariance properties of mappings from empirical systems to real number continua. Certainly the ideas have been revised, extended, and elaborated, but the remarkable thing is his insight given the relatively limited formal apparatus available to him and how many decades have passed since he coined them."<ref name = "Hand 2017">{{cite journal |last1=Hand |first1=David J.|journal=Measurement: Interdisciplinary Research and Perspectives | title=Measurement: A Very Short Introduction—Rejoinder to discussion |volume=15 | number=1 | year = 2017 |pages=37–50 |doi=10.1080/15366367.2017.1360022|hdl=10044/1/50223 |s2cid=148934577 |hdl-access=free }}</ref> The use of the mean as a measure of the central tendency for the ordinal type is still debatable among those who accept Stevens's typology. Many behavioural scientists use the mean for ordinal data anyway. This is often justified on the basis that the ordinal type in behavioural science is in fact somewhere between the true ordinal and interval types; although the interval difference between two ordinal ranks is not constant, it is often of the same order of magnitude. For example, applications of measurement models in educational contexts often indicate that total scores have a fairly linear relationship with measurements across the range of an assessment. Thus, some argue that so long as the unknown interval difference between ordinal scale ranks is not too variable, interval scale statistics such as means can meaningfully be used on ordinal scale variables. Statistical analysis software such as [[SPSS]] requires the user to select the appropriate measurement class for each variable. This ensures that subsequent user errors cannot inadvertently perform meaningless analyses (for example correlation analysis with a variable on a nominal level). [[L. L. Thurstone]] made progress toward developing a justification for obtaining the interval type, based on the [[law of comparative judgment]]. A common application of the law is the [[analytic hierarchy process]]. Further progress was made by [[Georg Rasch]] (1960), who developed the probabilistic [[Rasch model]] that provides a theoretical basis and justification for obtaining interval-level measurements from counts of observations such as total scores on assessments. ===Other proposed typologies=== Typologies aside from Stevens's typology have been proposed. For instance, [[Frederick Mosteller|Mosteller]] and [[John Tukey|Tukey]] (1977) and Nelder (1990)<ref>Nelder, J. A. (1990). The knowledge needed to computerise the analysis and interpretation of statistical information. In ''Expert systems and artificial intelligence: the need for information about data''. Library Association Report, London, March, 23–27.</ref> described continuous counts, continuous ratios, count ratios, and categorical modes of data. See also Chrisman (1998), van den Berg (1991).<ref>van den Berg, G. (1991). ''Choosing an analysis method''. Leiden: DSWO Press</ref> ==== Mosteller and Tukey's typology (1977) ==== Mosteller and Tukey<ref name="Mosteller"/> noted that the four levels are not exhaustive and proposed seven instead: # Names # Grades (ordered labels like beginner, intermediate, advanced) # Ranks (orders with 1 being the smallest or largest, 2 the next smallest or largest, and so on) # Counted fractions (bound by 0 and 1) # Counts (non-negative integers) # Amounts (non-negative real numbers) # Balances (any real number) For example, percentages (a variation on fractions in the Mosteller–Tukey framework) do not fit well into Stevens's framework: No transformation is fully admissible.<ref name = "Velleman and Wilkinson 1993" /> ==== Chrisman's typology (1998) ==== Nicholas R. Chrisman<ref name="Chrisman"/> introduced an expanded list of levels of measurement to account for various measurements that do not necessarily fit with the traditional notions of levels of measurement. Measurements bound to a range and repeating (like degrees in a circle, clock time, etc.), graded membership categories, and other types of measurement do not fit to Stevens's original work, leading to the introduction of six new levels of measurement, for a total of ten: # Nominal # Gradation of membership # Ordinal # Interval # Log-interval # Extensive ratio # Cyclical ratio # Derived ratio # Counts # Absolute While some claim that the extended levels of measurement are rarely used outside of academic geography,<ref name = "Wolman 2006">{{cite journal |title=Measurement and meaningfulness in conservation science |journal=Conservation Biology |volume=20 |issue=6 |pages=1626–1634 |year=2006 |last=Wolman |first=Abel G |s2cid=21372776 |doi=10.1111/j.1523-1739.2006.00531.x|pmid=17181798 |bibcode=2006ConBi..20.1626W }}</ref> graded membership is central to [[fuzzy set theory]], while absolute measurements include probabilities and the plausibility and ignorance in [[Dempster–Shafer theory]]. Cyclical ratio measurements include angles and times. Counts appear to be ratio measurements, but the scale is not arbitrary and fractional counts are commonly meaningless. Log-interval measurements are commonly displayed in stock market graphics. All these types of measurements are commonly used outside academic geography, and do not fit well to Stevens's original work. === Scale types and Stevens's "operational theory of measurement" === The theory of scale types is the intellectual handmaiden to Stevens's "operational theory of measurement", which was to become definitive within psychology and the [[behavioral sciences]],{{citation needed|date=July 2012}} despite Michell's characterization as its being quite at odds with measurement in the natural sciences (Michell, 1999). Essentially, the operational theory of measurement was a reaction to the conclusions of a committee established in 1932 by the [[British Association for the Advancement of Science]] to investigate the possibility of genuine scientific measurement in the psychological and behavioral sciences. This committee, which became known as the ''Ferguson committee'', published a Final Report (Ferguson, et al., 1940, p. 245) in which Stevens's [[sone]] scale (Stevens & Davis, 1938) was an object of criticism: {{blockquote | …any law purporting to express a quantitative relation between sensation intensity and stimulus intensity is not merely false but is in fact meaningless unless and until a meaning can be given to the concept of addition as applied to sensation.}} That is, if Stevens's ''[[sone]]'' scale genuinely measured the intensity of auditory sensations, then evidence for such sensations as being quantitative attributes needed to be produced. The evidence needed was the presence of ''additive structure''—a concept comprehensively treated by the German mathematician [[Otto Hölder]] (Hölder, 1901). Given that the physicist and measurement theorist [[Norman Robert Campbell]] dominated the Ferguson committee's deliberations, the committee concluded that measurement in the social sciences was impossible due to the lack of [[concatenation (mathematics)|concatenation]] operations. This conclusion was later rendered false by the discovery of the [[theory of conjoint measurement]] by Debreu (1960) and independently by Luce & Tukey (1964). However, Stevens's reaction was not to conduct experiments to test for the presence of additive structure in sensations, but instead to render the conclusions of the Ferguson committee null and void by proposing a new theory of measurement: {{blockquote|Paraphrasing N. R. Campbell (Final Report, p. 340), we may say that measurement, in the broadest sense, is defined as the assignment of numerals to objects and events according to rules (Stevens, 1946, p. 677).}} Stevens was greatly influenced by the ideas of another Harvard academic,<ref>[[Percy Bridgman]] (1957) ''[[The Logic of Modern Physics]]''</ref> the [[Nobel Prize|Nobel laureate]] physicist [[Percy Bridgman]] (1927), whose doctrine of [[operationalism]] Stevens used to define measurement. In Stevens's definition, for example, it is the use of a tape measure that defines length (the object of measurement) as being measurable (and so by implication quantitative). Critics of operationalism object that it confuses the relations between two objects or events for properties of one of those of objects or events (Moyer, 1981a, b; Rogers, 1989).<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Hardcastle | first1 = G. L. | year = 1995 | title = S. S. Stevens and the origins of operationism | journal = Philosophy of Science | volume = 62 | issue = 3| pages = 404–424 | doi=10.1086/289875| s2cid = 170941474 }}</ref><ref> Michell, J. (1999). ''Measurement in Psychology – A critical history of a methodological concept''. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.</ref> The Canadian measurement theorist William Rozeboom was an early and trenchant critic of Stevens's theory of scale types.<ref>{{cite journal | last1 = Rozeboom | first1 = W. W. | year = 1966 | title = Scaling theory and the nature of measurement | journal = Synthese | volume = 16 | issue = 2| pages = 170–233 | doi=10.1007/bf00485356| s2cid = 46970420 }}</ref> ==== Same variable may be different scale type depending on context ==== Another issue is that the same variable may be a different scale type depending on how it is measured and on the goals of the analysis. For example, hair color is usually thought of as a nominal variable, since it has no apparent ordering.<ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.ats.ucla.edu/stat/mult_pkg/whatstat/nominal_ordinal_interval.htm|title=What is the difference between categorical, ordinal and interval variables?|work=Institute for Digital Research and Education|publisher=University of California, Los Angeles|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20160125165359/http://www.ats.ucla.edu/stat/mult_pkg/whatstat/nominal_ordinal_interval.htm|access-date=7 February 2016|archive-date=2016-01-25}}</ref> However, it is possible to order colors (including hair colors) in various ways, including by hue; this is known as [[colorimetry]]. Hue is an interval level variable. == See also == * [[Cohen's kappa]] * [[Coherence (units of measurement)]] * [[Hume's principle]] * [[Inter-rater reliability]] * [[Logarithmic scale]] * [[Ramsey–Lewis method]] * [[Set theory]] * [[Statistical data type]] * [[Transition (linguistics)]] == References == {{Reflist}} == Further reading== {{further reading cleanup|date=June 2021}} {{Refbegin}} * {{cite journal | last1 = Alper | first1 = T. M. | year = 1985 | title = A note on real measurement structures of scale type (m, m + 1) | journal = Journal of Mathematical Psychology | volume = 29 | pages = 73–81 | doi=10.1016/0022-2496(85)90019-7}} * {{cite journal | last1 = Alper | first1 = T. M. | year = 1987 | title = A classification of all order-preserving homeomorphism groups of the reals that satisfy finite uniqueness | journal = Journal of Mathematical Psychology | volume = 31 | issue = 2| pages = 135–154 | doi=10.1016/0022-2496(87)90012-5| doi-access = free }} * Briand, L. & El Emam, K. & Morasca, S. (1995). "[https://web.archive.org/web/20070926232755/http://www2.umassd.edu/swpi/ISERN/isern-95-04.pdf On the Application of Measurement Theory in Software Engineering]". ''Empirical Software Engineering'', ''1'', 61–88. * [[Norman Cliff|Cliff, N.]] (1996). ''Ordinal Methods for Behavioral Data Analysis''. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. {{ISBN|0-8058-1333-0}} * [[Norman Cliff|Cliff, N.]] & Keats, J. A. (2003). ''Ordinal Measurement in the Behavioral Sciences''. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. {{ISBN|0-8058-2093-0}} * {{Cite journal |date=December 1953 |author=Lord, Frederic M |title=On the Statistical Treatment of Football Numbers |journal=[[American Psychologist]] |volume=8 |issue=12 |pages=750–751 |doi=10.1037/h0063675 |url=http://www.courses.msstate.edu/jmg1/4123/Spring2008/Readings/Lord1953.pdf |access-date=16 September 2010 |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110720003408/http://www.courses.msstate.edu/jmg1/4123/Spring2008/Readings/Lord1953.pdf |archive-date=20 July 2011 }} :See also reprints in: :* ''Readings in Statistics'', Ch. 3, (Haber, A., Runyon, R. P., and Badia, P.) Reading, Mass: Addison–Wesley, 1970 :* {{Cite book |year=2007 |editor=Maranell, Gary Michael |chapter=Chapter 31 |title=Scaling: A Sourcebook for Behavioral Scientists |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=d11bUmyCRCYC&pg=PR3 |pages=402–405 |place=New Brunswick, New Jersey & London, UK |publisher=Aldine Transaction |isbn=978-0-202-36175-8 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=VfQpW6PYGKMC&pg=PA402 |access-date=16 September 2010}} * {{cite journal | last1 = Hardcastle | first1 = G. L. | year = 1995 | title = S. S. Stevens and the origins of operationism | journal = Philosophy of Science | volume = 62 | issue = 3| pages = 404–424 | doi=10.1086/289875| s2cid = 170941474 }} * Lord, F. M., & Novick, M. R. (1968). ''Statistical theories of mental test scores''. Reading, MA: Addison–Wesley. * {{cite journal | last1 = Luce | first1 = R. D. | year = 1986 | title = Uniqueness and homogeneity of ordered relational structures | url = http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:3203652| journal = Journal of Mathematical Psychology | volume = 30 | issue = 4| pages = 391–415 | doi=10.1016/0022-2496(86)90017-9| s2cid = 13567893 | url-access = subscription }} * {{cite journal | last1 = Luce | first1 = R. D. | year = 1987 | title = Measurement structures with Archimedean ordered translation groups | journal = Order | volume = 4 | issue = 2| pages = 165–189 | doi=10.1007/bf00337695| s2cid = 16080432 }} * {{cite journal | last1 = Luce | first1 = R. D. | year = 1997 | title = Quantification and symmetry: commentary on Michell 'Quantitative science and the definition of measurement in psychology' | journal = British Journal of Psychology | volume = 88 | issue = 3| pages = 395–398 | doi=10.1111/j.2044-8295.1997.tb02645.x}} * Luce, R. D. (2000). ''Utility of uncertain gains and losses: measurement theoretic and experimental approaches''. Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum. * {{cite journal | last1 = Luce | first1 = R. D. | s2cid = 12231599 | year = 2001 | title = Conditions equivalent to unit representations of ordered relational structures | journal = Journal of Mathematical Psychology | volume = 45 | issue = 1| pages = 81–98 | doi=10.1006/jmps.1999.1293| pmid = 11178923 }} * {{cite journal | last1 = Luce | first1 = R. D. | last2 = Tukey | first2 = J. W. | year = 1964 | title = Simultaneous conjoint measurement: a new scale type of fundamental measurement | journal = Journal of Mathematical Psychology | volume = 1 | pages = 1–27 | doi=10.1016/0022-2496(64)90015-x| citeseerx = 10.1.1.334.5018 }} * {{cite journal | last1 = Michell | first1 = J. | year = 1986 | title = Measurement scales and statistics: a clash of paradigms | journal = Psychological Bulletin | volume = 100 | issue = 3| pages = 398–407 | doi=10.1037/0033-2909.100.3.398}} * {{cite journal | last1 = Michell | first1 = J. | s2cid = 143169737 | year = 1997 | title = Quantitative science and the definition of measurement in psychology | journal = British Journal of Psychology | volume = 88 | issue = 3| pages = 355–383 | doi=10.1111/j.2044-8295.1997.tb02641.x}} * Michell, J. (1999). ''Measurement in Psychology – A critical history of a methodological concept''. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. * {{cite journal | last1 = Michell | first1 = J. | s2cid = 146702066 | year = 2008 | title = Is psychometrics pathological science? | journal = Measurement – Interdisciplinary Research & Perspectives | volume = 6 | issue = 1–2| pages = 7–24 | doi=10.1080/15366360802035489}} * {{cite journal | last1 = Narens | first1 = L. | year = 1981a | title = A general theory of ratio scalability with remarks about the measurement-theoretic concept of meaningfulness | journal = Theory and Decision | volume = 13 | pages = 1–70 | doi=10.1007/bf02342603| s2cid = 119401596 }} * {{cite journal | last1 = Narens | first1 = L. | year = 1981b | title = On the scales of measurement | journal = Journal of Mathematical Psychology | volume = 24 | issue = 3| pages = 249–275 | doi=10.1016/0022-2496(81)90045-6}} * Rasch, G. (1960). ''Probabilistic models for some intelligence and attainment tests''. Copenhagen: Danish Institute for Educational Research. * {{cite journal | last1 = Rozeboom | first1 = W. W. | year = 1966 | title = Scaling theory and the nature of measurement | journal = Synthese | volume = 16 | issue = 2| pages = 170–233 | doi=10.1007/bf00485356| s2cid = 46970420 }} * {{Cite journal |date=June 7, 1946 |author=Stevens, S. S. |author-link=Stanley Smith Stevens |title=On the Theory of Scales of Measurement |journal=[[Science (journal)|Science]] |volume=103 |issue=2684 |pages=677–680 |doi=10.1126/science.103.2684.677 |pmid=17750512 |url=http://www.academic.cmru.ac.th/phraisin/au/prasit/stevens/Stevens_Measurement.pdf |access-date=16 September 2010 |bibcode=1946Sci...103..677S |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20111125054925/http://www.academic.cmru.ac.th/phraisin/au/prasit/stevens/Stevens_Measurement.pdf |archive-date=25 November 2011 }} * Stevens, S. S. (1951). Mathematics, measurement and psychophysics. In S. S. Stevens (Ed.), ''Handbook of experimental psychology '' (pp. 1–49). New York: Wiley. * Stevens, S. S. (1975). ''Psychophysics''. New York: Wiley. * {{cite journal | last1 = von Eye | first1 = A. | year = 2005 | title = Review of Cliff and Keats, ''Ordinal measurement in the behavioral sciences'' | journal = Applied Psychological Measurement | volume = 29 | issue = 5| pages = 401–403 | doi=10.1177/0146621605276938| s2cid = 220583753 }} {{Refend}} {{Statistics}} {{wikiversity}} [[Category:Scientific method]] [[Category:Statistical data types]] [[Category:Measurement]] [[Category:Cognitive science]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Anchor
(
edit
)
Template:Blockquote
(
edit
)
Template:Citation needed
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite encyclopedia
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Distinguish
(
edit
)
Template:Further
(
edit
)
Template:Further reading cleanup
(
edit
)
Template:ISBN
(
edit
)
Template:Redirect
(
edit
)
Template:Refbegin
(
edit
)
Template:Refend
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Section link
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Statistics
(
edit
)
Template:Subscription required
(
edit
)
Template:Wikiversity
(
edit
)