Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Loschmidt's paradox
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Conflict between known physical principles (time symmetry and entropy)}} In [[physics]], '''Loschmidt's paradox''' (named for [[Josef Loschmidt]]), also known as the '''reversibility paradox''', '''irreversibility paradox''', or '''''{{lang|de|Umkehreinwand}}''''' ({{ety|de||reversal objection}}),<ref>{{cite journal |title=Boltzmann's ''H'' theorem and the Loschmidt and the Zermelo paradoxes |author-last=Wu |author-first=Ta-You |author-link=Wu Ta-You |journal=[[International Journal of Theoretical Physics]] |date=December 1975 |volume=14 |issue=5 |page=289 |doi=10.1007/BF01807856 |bibcode=1975IJTP...14..289W |s2cid=119792996 }}</ref> is the objection that it should not be possible to deduce an [[irreversible process]] from time-symmetric dynamics. This puts the [[time reversal symmetry]] of (almost) all known low-level fundamental physical processes at odds with any attempt to infer from them the [[second law of thermodynamics]], which describes the behaviour of macroscopic systems. Both of these are well-accepted principles in physics, with sound observational and theoretical support, yet they seem to be in conflict, hence the [[paradox]]. == Origin == [[Johann Josef Loschmidt|Josef Loschmidt's]] criticism was provoked by the [[H-theorem]] of [[Boltzmann]], which employed [[kinetic theory of gases|kinetic theory]] to explain the increase of entropy in an ideal gas from a non-equilibrium state, when the molecules of the gas are allowed to collide. In 1876, Loschmidt pointed out that if there is a motion of a system from time ''t''<sub>0</sub> to time ''t''<sub>1</sub> to time ''t''<sub>2</sub> that leads to a steady decrease of ''H'' (increase of [[entropy (classical thermodynamics)|entropy]]) with time, then there is another allowed state of motion of the system at ''t''<sub>1</sub>, found by reversing all the velocities, in which ''H'' must increase. This revealed that one of Boltzmann's key assumptions, [[molecular chaos]], or, the ''Stosszahlansatz'', that all particle velocities were completely uncorrelated, did not follow from Newtonian dynamics. One can assert that possible correlations are uninteresting, and therefore decide to ignore them; but if one does so, one has changed the conceptual system, injecting an element of time-asymmetry by that very action. Reversible laws of motion cannot explain why we experience our world to be in such a comparatively low state of entropy at the moment (compared to the equilibrium entropy of [[heat death of the universe|universal heat death]]); and to have been at even lower entropy in the past. Later authors<ref>Waugh, J. S., Rhim, W.-K. and Pines, A.. "Spin echoes and Loschmidt's paradox" Pure and Applied Chemistry, vol. 32, no. 1-4, 1972, pp. 317-324. [https://doi.org/10.1351/pac197232010317]</ref> have coined the term "Loschmitz's demon" (in analogy to [[Maxwell's demon]], see [[Loschmidt's paradox#Information theory|below]]) for an entity that is able to reverse time evolution in a microscopic system, in their case of nuclear spins, which is indeed, if only for a short time, [[Spin echo|experimentally]] possible. === Before Loschmidt === In 1874, two years before the Loschmidt paper, [[William Thomson, 1st Baron Kelvin|William Thomson]] defended the second law against the time reversal objection in his paper "The kinetic theory of the dissipation of energy".<ref>[[William Thomson, 1st Baron Kelvin|Thomson, W. (Lord Kelvin)]] (1874/1875). [https://archive.org/stream/mathematicalphys05kelvuoft#page/11/mode/1up The kinetic theory of the dissipation of energy], ''[[Nature (journal)|Nature]]'', Vol. IX, 1874-04-09, 441–444.</ref> == Arrow of time == {{main|Arrow of time}} Any process that happens regularly in the forward direction of time but rarely or never in the opposite direction, such as entropy increasing in an isolated system, defines what physicists call an [[arrow of time]] in nature. This term only refers to an observation of an asymmetry in time; it is not meant to suggest an explanation for such asymmetries. Loschmidt's paradox is equivalent to the question of how it is possible that there could be a [[Entropy (arrow of time)|thermodynamic arrow of time]] given time-symmetric fundamental laws, since time-symmetry implies that for any process compatible with these fundamental laws, a reversed version that looked exactly like a film of the first process played backwards would be equally compatible with the same fundamental laws, and would even be equally probable if one were to pick the system's initial state randomly from the [[phase space]] of all possible states for that system. Although most of the arrows of time described by physicists are thought to be special cases of the thermodynamic arrow, there are a few that are believed to be unconnected, like the cosmological arrow of time based on the fact that the universe is expanding rather than contracting, and the fact that a few processes in particle physics actually violate time-symmetry, while they respect a related symmetry known as [[CPT symmetry]]. In the case of the cosmological arrow, most physicists believe that entropy would continue to increase even if the universe began to contract{{Citation needed|date=April 2022}} (although the physicist [[Thomas Gold]] once proposed a model in which the thermodynamic arrow would reverse in this phase). In the case of the violations of time-symmetry in particle physics, the situations in which they occur are rare and are only known to involve a few types of [[meson]] particles. Furthermore, due to [[CPT symmetry]], reversal of the direction of time is equivalent to renaming particles as [[antiparticle]]s and ''vice versa''. Therefore, this cannot explain Loschmidt's paradox. == Dynamical systems == {{main|Entropy as an arrow of time}} Current {{As of?|date=August 2023}} research in dynamical systems offers one possible mechanism for obtaining irreversibility from reversible systems. The central argument is based on the claim that the correct way to study the dynamics of macroscopic systems is to study the [[transfer operator]] corresponding to the microscopic equations of motion. It is then argued {{by whom|date=August 2023}} that the transfer operator is not [[Unitary (physics)|unitary]] (''i.e.'' is not reversible) but has [[Eigenvalues and eigenvectors|eigenvalues]] whose magnitude is strictly less than one; these eigenvalues corresponding to decaying physical states. This approach is fraught with various difficulties; it works well for only a handful of exactly solvable models.<ref>Dean J. Driebe, ''Fully Chaotic Maps and Broken Time Symmetry'', (1999) Kluwer Academic {{ISBN|0-7923-5564-4}}.</ref> Abstract mathematical tools used in the study of [[dissipative system]]s include definitions of [[mixing (mathematics)|mixing]], [[wandering set]]s, and [[ergodic theory]] in general. == Fluctuation theorem == {{unreferenced section|date=July 2024}} {{main|Fluctuation theorem}} One approach to handling Loschmidt's paradox is the [[fluctuation theorem]], derived heuristically by [[Denis Evans]] and [[Debra Searles]], which gives a numerical estimate of the probability that a system away from equilibrium will have a certain value for the dissipation function (often an entropy like property) over a certain amount of time.<ref>D. J. Evans and D. J. Searles, Adv. Phys. '''51''', 1529 (2002).</ref> The result is obtained with the exact time reversible dynamical equations of motion and the [[universal causation]] proposition. The fluctuation theorem is obtained using the fact that dynamics is time reversible.{{Citation needed|date=April 2022}} Quantitative predictions of this theorem have been confirmed in laboratory experiments at the [[Australian National University]] conducted by [[Edith M. Sevick]] et al. using [[optical tweezers]] apparatus.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Sevick |first=Edith |title=2002 RSC Annual Report - Polymers and Soft Condensed Matter |url=https://rsc.anu.edu.au/AnnualReport/Report2002/CB-report.html |access-date=2022-04-01 |website=Research School of Chemistry. Australian National University.}}</ref> This theorem is applicable for transient systems, which may initially be in equilibrium and then driven away (as was the case for the first experiment by Sevick et al.) or some other arbitrary initial state, including relaxation towards equilibrium. There is also an asymptotic result for systems which are in a nonequilibrium steady state at all times. There is a crucial point in the fluctuation theorem, that differs from how Loschmidt framed the paradox. Loschmidt considered the probability of observing a single trajectory, which is analogous to enquiring about the probability of observing a single point in phase space. In both of these cases the probability is always zero. To be able to effectively address this you must consider the probability density for a set of points in a small region of phase space, or a set of trajectories. The fluctuation theorem considers the probability density for all of the trajectories that are initially in an infinitesimally small region of phase space. This leads directly to the probability of finding a trajectory, in either the forward or the reverse trajectory sets, depending upon the initial probability distribution as well as the dissipation which is done as the system evolves. It is this crucial difference in approach that allows the fluctuation theorem to correctly solve the paradox. ==Information theory== A more recent proposal concentrates on the step of the paradox in which velocities are reversed. At that moment the gas becomes an open system, and in order to reverse the velocities, position and velocity measurements have to be made.<ref>{{cite journal|title=The reversibility paradox: Role of the velocity reversal step|author-last=Binder|author-first=P.M.|author-link=P.M. Binder|journal=[[International Journal of Theoretical Physics]]|date=2023|volume=62|issue=9 | page=200|doi=10.1007/s10773-023-05458-x |bibcode=2023IJTP...62..200B |url= https://rdcu.be/dmmuZ |doi-access=free}}</ref> Without this, no reversal is possible. These measurements are themselves either irreversible, or reversible. In the first case, they require an increase of entropy in the measuring device that will at least offset the decrease during the reversed evolution of the gas. In the second case, [[Landauer's principle]] can be evoked to reach the same conclusion. Hence, the gas+measuring device system obeys the Second Law of Thermodynamics. It is not a coincidence that this argument mirrors closely another one given by Bennett to explain away [[Maxwell’s demon]]. The difference is that the role of measurement is obvious in Maxwell’s demon, but not in Loschmidt’s paradox, which may explain the 40-year gap between both explanations. In the case of the single-trajectory paradox, this argument preempts the need for any other explanation, although some of them make valid points. The broader paradox, “an irreversible process cannot be deduced from reversible dynamics,” is not covered by the argument given in this section. == Big Bang == {{See also|Past hypothesis}} Another way of dealing with Loschmidt's paradox is to see the second law as an expression of a set of boundary conditions, in which our universe's time coordinate has a low-entropy starting point: the [[Big Bang]]. From this point of view, the arrow of time is determined entirely by the direction that leads away from the Big Bang, and a hypothetical universe with a maximum-entropy Big Bang would have no arrow of time. The theory of [[cosmic inflation]] tries to give reason why the early universe had such a low entropy. == See also == * [[Maximum entropy thermodynamics]] for one particular perspective on entropy, reversibility and the Second Law * [[Poincaré recurrence theorem]] * [[Reversible process (thermodynamics)|Reversibility]] * [[Statistical mechanics]] == References == <references/> * J. Loschmidt, Sitzungsber. Kais. Akad. Wiss. Wien, Math. Naturwiss. Classe 73, 128–142 (1876) == External links == * [http://www.nyu.edu/classes/tuckerman/stat.mech/lectures/lecture_3/node2.html Reversible laws of motion and the arrow of time] by Mark Tuckerman * Toy systems with time-reversible discrete dynamics showing entropy increase [https://archive.today/20121216121427/http://www.scientificblogging.com/hammock_physicist/fibonacci_chaos_and_times_arrow Fibonacci Iterated Map] ; [https://arxiv.org/abs/2310.01458 Ising-Conway Game] <!-- [[Category:Theoretical physics]] --> <!-- [[Category:Statistical mechanics]] --> <!-- [[Category:Thermodynamics]] --> [[Category:Philosophy of thermal and statistical physics]] [[Category:Non-equilibrium thermodynamics]] [[Category:Physical paradoxes]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:As of?
(
edit
)
Template:By whom
(
edit
)
Template:Citation needed
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Ety
(
edit
)
Template:ISBN
(
edit
)
Template:Lang
(
edit
)
Template:Main
(
edit
)
Template:See also
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Unreferenced section
(
edit
)