Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Pareto efficiency
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Weakly optimal allocation of resources}} {{Use mdy dates|date=January 2016}} {{Economics sidebar}} In [[welfare economics]], a '''Pareto improvement''' formalizes the idea of an outcome being "better in every possible way". A change is called a Pareto improvement if it leaves at least one person in society better off without leaving anyone else worse off than they were before. A situation is called '''Pareto efficient''' or '''Pareto optimal''' if all possible Pareto improvements have already been made; in other words, there are no longer any ways left to make one person better off, without making some other person worse-off.<ref>{{Cite web |title=Martin J. Osborne |url=https://economics.utoronto.ca/osborne/ |access-date=2022-12-10 |website=economics.utoronto.ca}}</ref> In [[social choice theory]], the same concept is sometimes called the '''unanimity principle''', which says that if ''everyone'' in a society ([[strict inequality|non-strictly]]) prefers A to B, society as a whole also non-strictly prefers A to B. The [[Pareto frontier|Pareto front]] consists of all Pareto-efficient situations.<ref>{{Cite web|url=http://www.cenaero.be/Page.asp?docid=27103&|title=Pareto Front|last=proximedia|website=www.cenaero.be|access-date=2018-10-08|archive-date=February 26, 2020|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200226003108/http://www.cenaero.be/Page.asp?docid=27103&|url-status=dead}}</ref> In addition to the context of efficiency in ''allocation'', the concept of Pareto efficiency also arises in the context of [[productive efficiency|''efficiency in production'']] vs. ''[[x-inefficiency]]'': a set of outputs of goods is Pareto-efficient if there is no feasible re-allocation of productive inputs such that output of one product increases while the outputs of all other goods either increase or remain the same.<ref>[[John D. Black|Black, J. D.]], Hashimzade, N., [[Gareth Myles|Myles, G.]] (eds.), ''A Dictionary of Economics'', 5th ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017), [https://books.google.com/books?id=WyvYDQAAQBAJ&pg=PT459 p. 459].</ref> Besides economics, the notion of Pareto efficiency has also been applied to selecting alternatives in [[engineering]] and [[biology]]. Each option is first assessed, under multiple criteria, and then a subset of options is identified with the property that no other option can categorically outperform the specified option. It is a statement of impossibility of improving one variable without harming other variables in the subject of [[multi-objective optimization]] (also termed '''Pareto optimization'''). == History == The concept is named after [[Vilfredo Pareto]] (1848–1923), an Italian [[civil engineer]] and [[economist]], who used the concept in his studies of [[economic efficiency]] and [[income distribution]]. Pareto originally used the word "optimal" for the concept, but this is somewhat of a [[misnomer]]: Pareto's concept more closely aligns with an idea of "efficiency", because it does not identify a single "best" (optimal) outcome. Instead, it only identifies a set of outcomes that ''might'' be considered optimal, by at least one person.<ref name="Palgrave Macmillan">{{cite book |last1=Lockwood |first1=B. |title=The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics |date=2008 |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |location=London |isbn=978-1-349-95121-5 |edition=2nd}}</ref> == Overview == Formally, a state is Pareto-optimal if there is no alternative state where at least one participant's well-being is higher, and nobody else's well-being is lower. If there is a state change that satisfies this condition, the new state is called a "Pareto improvement". When no Pareto improvements are possible, the state is a "Pareto optimum". In other words, Pareto efficiency is when it is impossible to make one party better off without making another party worse off.<ref name=":1">{{Cite web |title=Pareto Efficiency |url=https://corporatefinanceinstitute.com/resources/economics/pareto-efficiency/ |access-date=2022-12-10 |website=Corporate Finance Institute |language=en-US}}</ref> This state indicates that resources can no longer be allocated in a way that makes one party better off without harming other parties. In a state of Pareto Efficiency, resources are allocated in the most efficient way possible.<ref name=":1" /> Pareto efficiency is mathematically represented when there is no other strategy profile ''s''' such that ''u<sub>i</sub> (s') ≥ u<sub>i</sub> (s)'' for every player ''i'' and ''u<sub>j</sub> (s') > u<sub>j</sub> (s)'' for some player ''j''. In this equation ''s'' represents the strategy profile, ''u'' represents the utility or benefit, and ''j'' represents the player.<ref name=":2">{{Cite book |last=Watson |first=Joel |title=Strategy: An Introduction to Game Theory |publisher=W. W. Norton and Company |year=2013 |edition=3rd}}</ref> Efficiency is an important criterion for judging behavior in a game. In [[zero-sum games]], every outcome is Pareto-efficient. A special case of a state is an allocation of resources. The formal presentation of the concept in an economy is the following: Consider an economy with <math> n</math> agents and <math> k </math> goods. Then an allocation <math> \{x_1, \dots, x_n\} </math>, where <math> x_i \in \mathbb{R}^k </math> for all ''i'', is ''Pareto-optimal'' if there is no other feasible allocation <math> \{x_1', \dots, x_n'\} </math> where, for utility function <math> u_i </math> for each agent <math> i </math>, <math> u_i(x_i') \geq u_i(x_i) </math> for all <math> i \in \{1, \dots, n\} </math> with <math> u_i(x_i') > u_i(x_i) </math> for some <math> i</math>.<ref name="AndreuMas95">{{citation|author-link=Andreu Mas-Colell|last1=Mas-Colell|first1=A.|first2=Michael D.|last2=Whinston|first3=Jerry R.|last3=Green|year=1995|title=Microeconomic Theory|chapter=Chapter 16: Equilibrium and its Basic Welfare Properties|publisher=Oxford University Press|isbn=978-0-19-510268-0|url-access=registration|url=https://archive.org/details/isbn_9780198089537}}.</ref> Here, in this simple economy, "feasibility" refers to an allocation where the total amount of each good that is allocated sums to no more than the total amount of the good in the economy. In a more complex economy with production, an allocation would consist both of consumption [[Vector space|vectors]] and production vectors, and feasibility would require that the total amount of each consumed good is no greater than the initial endowment plus the amount produced. Under the assumptions of the [[first welfare theorem]], a [[competitive market]] leads to a Pareto-efficient outcome. This result was first demonstrated mathematically by economists [[Kenneth Arrow]] and [[Gérard Debreu]].<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Gerard |first1=Debreu |title=Valuation Equilibrium and Pareto Optimum |year=1959 |journal=Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America |volume=40 |issue=7 |pages=588–592 |doi=10.1073/pnas.40.7.588 |jstor=89325 |pmid=16589528 |pmc=528000 |doi-access=free}}</ref> However, the result only holds under the assumptions of the theorem: markets exist for all possible goods, there are no [[externality|externalities]], markets are perfectly competitive, and market participants have [[perfect information]]. In the absence of perfect information or complete markets, outcomes will generally be Pareto-inefficient, per the [[Joseph Stiglitz#Information asymmetry|Greenwald–Stiglitz theorem]].<ref>{{Cite journal |doi=10.2307/1891114 |last1=Greenwald |first1=B. |last2=Stiglitz |first2=J. E. |author1-link=Bruce Greenwald |author2-link=Joseph E. Stiglitz |journal=Quarterly Journal of Economics |volume=101 |issue=2 |pages=229–264 |year=1986 |title=Externalities in economies with imperfect information and incomplete markets |jstor=1891114|doi-access=free }}</ref> The [[second welfare theorem]] is essentially the reverse of the first welfare theorem. It states that under similar, ideal assumptions, any Pareto optimum can be obtained by some [[competitive equilibrium]], or [[free market]] system, although it may also require a [[lump-sum]] transfer of wealth.<ref name="AndreuMas95"/> ===Pareto efficiency and market failure=== An ineffective distribution of resources in a free market is known as [[market failure]]. Given that there is room for improvement, market failure implies Pareto inefficiency. For instance, excessive use of negative commodities (such as drugs and cigarettes) results in expenses to non-smokers as well as early mortality for smokers. [[Cigarette tax]]es may help individuals stop smoking while also raising money to address ailments brought on by smoking. ===Pareto efficiency and equity=== A Pareto improvement may be seen, but this does not always imply that the result is desirable or equitable. After a Pareto improvement, inequality could still exist. However, it does imply that any change will violate the "do no harm" principle, because at least one person will be worse off. A society may be Pareto efficient but have significant levels of inequality. The most equitable course of action would be to split the pie into three equal portions if there were three persons and a pie. The third person does not lose out (even if he does not partake in the pie), hence splitting it in half and giving it to two individuals would be considered Pareto efficient. On a frontier of production possibilities, Pareto efficiency will happen. It is impossible to raise the output of products without decreasing the output of services when an economy is functioning on a basic production potential frontier, such as at point A, B, or C. == Pareto order == If multiple sub-goals <math>f_i</math> (with <math>i > 1</math>) exist, combined into a vector-valued objective function <math>\vec{f}=(f_1, \dots f_n)^T</math>, generally, finding a unique optimum <math>\vec{x}^* </math> becomes challenging. This is due to the absence of a [[total order]] relation for <math>n >1</math> which would not always prioritize one target over another target (like the [[lexicographical order]]). In the multi-objective optimization setting, various solutions can be "incomparable"<ref>"The main difficulty is that, in contrast to the single-objective case where there is a total order relation between solutions, Pareto dominance is a partial order, which leads to solutions (and solution sets) being incomparable" Li, M., López-Ibáñez, M., & Yao, X. (Accepted/In press). Multi-Objective Archiving. IEEE Transactions on Evolutionary Computation. https://arxiv.org/pdf/2303.09685.pdf</ref> as there is no total order relation to facilitate the comparison <math>\vec{f}(\vec{x}^*) \geq \vec{f}(\vec{x})</math>. Only the Pareto order is applicable: Consider a vector-valued minimization problem: <math>\vec{y}^{(1)} \in \mathbb{R}^m</math> Pareto dominates <math>\vec{y}^{(2)} \in \mathbb{R}^m</math> if and only if:<ref name = "Emmerich2018">Emmerich, M.T.M., Deutz, A.H. A tutorial on multiobjective optimization: fundamentals and evolutionary methods. Nat Comput 17, 585–609 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11047-018-9685-y</ref> :<math>\forall i \in \{1,\dots m\}:\vec{y}_i^{(1)} \leq \vec{y}_i^{(2)}</math> and <math>\exists j \in \{1,\dots m\}:\vec{y}_j^{(1)} < \vec{y}_j^{(2)}.</math> We then write <math>\vec{y}^{(1)} \prec \vec{y}^{(2)}</math>, where <math>\prec</math> is the Pareto order. This means that <math>\vec{y}^{(1)}</math> is not worse than <math>\vec{y}^{(2)}</math> in any goal but is better (since smaller) in at least one goal <math>j</math>. The Pareto order is a strict [[partial order]], though it is not a [[product order]] (neither non-strict nor strict). If<ref name="Emmerich2018" /> <math>\vec{f}(\vec{x}_1) \prec \vec{f}(\vec{x}_2)</math>, then this defines a [[preorder]] in the search space and we say <math>\vec{x}_1</math> Pareto dominates the alternative <math>\vec{x}_2</math> and we write <math>\vec{x}_1 \prec_{\vec{f}} \vec{x}_2</math>. [[Image:Pareto order dominated.png|thumb|<math>\vec{f}(x)</math> dominates <math>\vec{f}(y)</math> in the Pareto order (which seeks to minimize the goals <math>f_1</math> and <math>f_2</math>).]] [[Image:Pareto order not dominated.png|thumb|<math>\vec{f}(x)</math> does not dominate <math>\vec{f}(y)</math> in the Pareto order and <math>\vec{f}(y)</math> does not dominate <math>\vec{f}(x)</math> in the Pareto order (which seeks to minimize the goals <math>f_1</math> and <math>f_2</math>).]] == Variants == === Weak Pareto efficiency{{anchor|weak}} === '''Weak Pareto efficiency''' is a situation that cannot be strictly improved for ''every'' individual.<ref>{{Cite book |doi=10.1007/978-1-4020-9160-5_341 |chapter = Pareto Optimality|title = Encyclopedia of Global Justice |pages=808–809 |year = 2011 |last1 = Mock |first1 = William B. T. | isbn=978-1-4020-9159-9}}</ref> Formally, a '''strong Pareto improvement''' is defined as a situation in which all agents are strictly better-off (in contrast to just "Pareto improvement", which requires that one agent is strictly better-off and the other agents are at least as good). A situation is '''weak Pareto-efficient''' if it has no strong Pareto improvements. Any strong Pareto improvement is also a weak Pareto improvement. The opposite is not true; for example, consider a resource allocation problem with two resources, which Alice values at {10, 0}, and George values at {5, 5}. Consider the allocation giving all resources to Alice, where the utility profile is (10, 0): * It is a weak PO, since no other allocation is strictly better to both agents (there are no strong Pareto improvements). * But it is not a strong PO, since the allocation in which George gets the second resource is strictly better for George and weakly better for Alice (it is a weak Pareto improvement){{snd}} its utility profile is (10, 5). A market does not require [[local nonsatiation]] to get to a weak Pareto optimum.<ref>Markey‐Towler, Brendan and John Foster. "[http://www.uq.edu.au/economics/abstract/476.pdf Why economic theory has little to say about the causes and effects of inequality]", School of Economics, [[University of Queensland]], Australia, 21 February 2013, RePEc:qld:uq2004:476.</ref> === Constrained Pareto efficiency {{anchor|Constrained Pareto efficiency}}=== '''Constrained Pareto efficiency''' is a weakening of Pareto optimality, accounting for the fact that a potential planner (e.g., the government) may not be able to improve upon a decentralized market outcome, even if that outcome is inefficient. This will occur if it is limited by the same informational or institutional constraints as are individual agents.<ref>Magill, M., & [[Martine Quinzii|Quinzii, M.]], ''Theory of Incomplete Markets'', MIT Press, 2002, [https://books.google.com/books?id=d66GXq2F2M0C&pg=PA104 p. 104].</ref> An example is of a setting where individuals have private information (for example, a labor market where the worker's own productivity is known to the worker but not to a potential employer, or a used-car market where the quality of a car is known to the seller but not to the buyer) which results in [[moral hazard]] or an [[adverse selection]] and a sub-optimal outcome. In such a case, a planner who wishes to improve the situation is unlikely to have access to any information that the participants in the markets do not have. Hence, the planner cannot implement allocation rules which are based on the idiosyncratic characteristics of individuals; for example, "if a person is of type ''A'', they pay price ''p''<sub>1</sub>, but if of type ''B'', they pay price ''p''<sub>2</sub>" (see [[Lindahl prices]]). Essentially, only anonymous rules are allowed (of the sort "Everyone pays price ''p''") or rules based on observable behavior; "if any person chooses ''x'' at price ''p<sub>x</sub>'', then they get a subsidy of ten dollars, and nothing otherwise". If there exists no allowed rule that can successfully improve upon the market outcome, then that outcome is said to be "constrained Pareto-optimal". === Fractional Pareto efficiency{{anchor|fractional}} === {{Main|Fractional Pareto efficiency}} '''Fractional Pareto efficiency''' is a strengthening of Pareto efficiency in the context of [[fair item allocation]]. An allocation of indivisible items is '''fractionally Pareto-efficient (fPE or fPO)''' if it is not Pareto-dominated even by an allocation in which some items are split between agents. This is in contrast to standard Pareto efficiency, which only considers domination by feasible (discrete) allocations.<ref name=":0">Barman, S., Krishnamurthy, S. K., & Vaish, R., [https://arxiv.org/abs/1707.04731 "Finding Fair and Efficient Allocations"], ''EC '18: Proceedings of the 2018 ACM Conference on Economics and Computation'', June 2018.</ref><ref>{{cite journal|last1=Sandomirskiy|first1=Fedor|last2=Segal-Halevi|first2=Erel|title=Efficient Fair Division with Minimal Sharing|journal=Operations Research |year=2022 |volume=70 |issue=3 |pages=1762–1782 |doi=10.1287/opre.2022.2279 |arxiv=1908.01669|s2cid=247922344 }}</ref> As an example, consider an item allocation problem with two items, which Alice values at {3, 2} and George values at {4, 1}. Consider the allocation giving the first item to Alice and the second to George, where the utility profile is (3, 1): * It is Pareto-efficient, since any other discrete allocation (without splitting items) makes someone worse-off. * However, it is not fractionally Pareto-efficient, since it is Pareto-dominated by the allocation giving to Alice 1/2 of the first item and the whole second item, and the other 1/2 of the first item to George{{snd}} its utility profile is (3.5, 2). === Ex-ante Pareto efficiency === When the decision process is random, such as in [[fair random assignment]] or [[random social choice]] or [[fractional approval voting]], there is a difference between '''ex-post''' and '''ex-ante Pareto efficiency''': * Ex-post Pareto efficiency means that any outcome of the random process is Pareto-efficient. * Ex-ante Pareto efficiency means that the ''lottery'' determined by the process is Pareto-efficient with respect to the ''expected'' utilities. That is: no other lottery gives a higher expected utility to one agent and at least as high expected utility to all agents. If some lottery ''L'' is ex-ante PE, then it is also ex-post PE. ''Proof'': suppose that one of the ex-post outcomes ''x'' of ''L'' is Pareto-dominated by some other outcome ''y''. Then, by moving some probability mass from ''x'' to ''y'', one attains another lottery ''L{{'}}'' that ex-ante Pareto-dominates ''L''. The opposite is not true: ex-ante PE is stronger that ex-post PE. For example, suppose there are two objects{{snd}} a car and a house. Alice values the car at 2 and the house at 3; George values the car at 2 and the house at 9. Consider the following two lotteries: # With probability 1/2, give car to Alice and house to George; otherwise, give car to George and house to Alice. The expected utility is {{nobr|(2/2 + 3/2) {{=}} 2.5}} for Alice and {{nobr|(2/2 + 9/2) {{=}} 5.5}} for George. Both allocations are ex-post PE, since the one who got the car cannot be made better-off without harming the one who got the house. # With probability 1, give car to Alice, then with probability 1/3 give the house to Alice, otherwise give it to George. The expected utility is {{nobr|(2 + 3/3) {{=}} 3}} for Alice and {{nobr|(9 × 2/3) {{=}} 6}} for George. Again, both allocations are ex-post PE. While both lotteries are ex-post PE, the lottery 1 is not ex-ante PE, since it is Pareto-dominated by lottery 2. Another example involves [[dichotomous preferences]].<ref name=":02">{{Cite journal |last1=Bogomolnaia |first1=Anna |last2=Moulin |first2=Hervé |last3=Stong |first3=Richard |date=2005-06-01 |title=Collective choice under dichotomous preferences |url=http://www.ruf.rice.edu/~econ/papers/2003papers/09bogomolnaia.pdf |journal=Journal of Economic Theory |language=en |volume=122 |issue=2 |pages=165–184 |doi=10.1016/j.jet.2004.05.005 |issn=0022-0531}}</ref> There are 5 possible outcomes {{nobr|(''a'', ''b'', ''c'', ''d'', ''e'')}} and 6 voters. The voters' approval sets are {{nobr|(''ac'', ''ad'', ''ae'', ''bc'', ''bd'', ''be'')}}. All five outcomes are PE, so every lottery is ex-post PE. But the lottery selecting ''c'', ''d'', ''e'' with probability 1/3 each is not ex-ante PE, since it gives an expected utility of 1/3 to each voter, while the lottery selecting ''a'', ''b'' with probability 1/2 each gives an expected utility of 1/2 to each voter. === Bayesian Pareto efficiency === {{Main|Bayesian efficiency}} '''Bayesian efficiency''' is an adaptation of Pareto efficiency to settings in which players have incomplete information regarding the types of other players. === Ordinal Pareto efficiency === {{Main|Ordinal Pareto efficiency}} '''Ordinal Pareto efficiency''' is an adaptation of Pareto efficiency to settings in which players report only rankings on individual items, and we do not know for sure how they rank entire bundles. == Pareto efficiency and equity == Although an outcome may be a Pareto improvement, this does not imply that the outcome is equitable. It is possible that inequality persists even after a Pareto improvement. Despite the fact that it is frequently used in conjunction with the idea of Pareto optimality, the term "efficiency" refers to the process of increasing societal productivity.<ref>Nicola. (2013). Efficiency and Equity in Welfare Economics (1st ed. 2013). Springer Berlin Heidelberg : Imprint: Springer.</ref> It is possible for a society to have Pareto efficiency while also have high levels of inequality. Consider the following scenario: there is a pie and three persons; the most equitable way would be to divide the pie into three equal portions. However, if the pie is divided in half and shared between two people, it is considered Pareto efficient{{snd}} meaning that the third person does not lose out (despite the fact that he does not receive a piece of the pie). When making judgments, it is critical to consider a variety of aspects, including social efficiency, overall welfare, and issues such as diminishing marginal value. == Pareto efficiency and market failure == In order to fully understand market failure, one must first comprehend market success, which is defined as the ability of a set of idealized competitive markets to achieve an equilibrium allocation of resources that is Pareto-optimal in terms of resource allocation. According to the definition of market failure, it is a circumstance in which the conclusion of the first fundamental theorem of welfare is erroneous; that is, when the allocations made through markets are not efficient.<ref>Ledyard, J. O. (1989). Market Failure. In: Eatwell, J., Milgate, M., Newman, P. (eds.) Allocation, Information and Markets. The New Palgrave. Palgrave Macmillan, London. {{doi|10.1007/978-1-349-20215-7_19}}.</ref> In a free market, market failure is defined as an inefficient allocation of resources. Due to the fact that it is feasible to improve, market failure implies Pareto inefficiency. For example, excessive consumption of depreciating items (drugs/tobacco) results in external costs to non-smokers, as well as premature death for smokers who do not quit. An increase in the price of cigarettes could motivate people to quit smoking while also raising funds for the treatment of smoking-related ailments. === Approximate Pareto efficiency === Given some ''ε'' > 0, an outcome is called '''''ε''-Pareto-efficient''' if no other outcome gives all agents at least the same utility, and one agent a utility at least (1 + ''ε'') higher. This captures the notion that improvements smaller than (1 + ''ε'') are negligible and should not be considered a breach of efficiency. == Pareto-efficiency and welfare-maximization == {{See also|Pareto-efficient envy-free division}} Suppose each agent ''i'' is assigned a positive weight ''a<sub>i</sub>''. For every allocation ''x'', define the ''welfare'' of ''x'' as the weighted sum of utilities of all agents in ''x'': : <math>W_a(x) := \sum_{i=1}^n a_i u_i(x).</math> Let ''x<sub>a</sub>'' be an allocation that maximizes the welfare over all allocations: : <math>x_a \in \arg\max_x W_a(x).</math> It is easy to show that the allocation ''x<sub>a</sub>'' is Pareto-efficient: since all weights are positive, any Pareto improvement would increase the sum, contradicting the definition of ''x<sub>a</sub>''. Japanese neo-[[Léon Walras#General equilibrium theory|Walrasian]] economist [[Takashi Negishi]] proved<ref>{{cite journal |last=Negishi |first=Takashi |date=1960 |title=Welfare Economics and Existence of an Equilibrium for a Competitive Economy |journal=Metroeconomica |volume=12 |issue=2–3 |pages=92–97 |doi=10.1111/j.1467-999X.1960.tb00275.x }}</ref> that, under certain assumptions, the opposite is also true: for ''every'' Pareto-efficient allocation ''x'', there exists a positive vector ''a'' such that ''x'' maximizes ''W<sub>a</sub>''. A shorter proof is provided by [[Hal Varian]].<ref>{{cite journal |doi=10.1016/0047-2727(76)90018-9 |title=Two problems in the theory of fairness |journal=Journal of Public Economics |volume=5 |issue=3–4 |pages=249–260 |year=1976 |last1=Varian |first1=Hal R. |hdl=1721.1/64180 |hdl-access=free }}</ref> == Use in engineering== The notion of Pareto efficiency has been used in engineering.<ref>Goodarzi, E., Ziaei, M., & Hosseinipour, E. Z., ''Introduction to Optimization Analysis in Hydrosystem Engineering'' ([[Berlin]]/[[Heidelberg]]: [[Springer Science+Business Media|Springer]], 2014), [https://books.google.com/books?id=WjS8BAAAQBAJ&pg=PT111 pp. 111–148].</ref> Given a set of choices and a way of valuing them, the '''[[Pareto front]]''' (or '''Pareto set''' or '''Pareto frontier''') is the set of choices that are Pareto-efficient. By restricting attention to the set of choices that are Pareto-efficient, a designer can make [[trade-off]]s within this set, rather than considering the full range of every parameter.<ref>Jahan, A., Edwards, K. L., & Bahraminasab, M., ''Multi-criteria Decision Analysis'', 2nd ed. ([[Amsterdam]]: [[Elsevier]], 2013), [https://books.google.com/books?id=3mreBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA63 pp. 63–65].</ref> == Use in public policy == Modern microeconomic theory has drawn heavily upon the concept of Pareto efficiency for inspiration. Pareto and his successors have tended to describe this technical definition of optimal resource allocation in the context of it being an equilibrium that can theoretically be achieved within an abstract model of market competition. It has therefore very often been treated as a corroboration of [[Adam Smith]]'s "[[invisible hand]]" notion. More specifically, it motivated the debate over "[[market socialism]]" in the 1930s.<ref name="Palgrave Macmillan"/> However, because the Pareto-efficient outcome is difficult to assess in the real world when issues including asymmetric information, signalling, adverse selection, and moral hazard are introduced, most people do not take the theorems of welfare economics as accurate descriptions of the real world. Therefore, the significance of the two welfare theorems of economics is in their ability to generate a framework that has dominated neoclassical thinking about public policy. That framework is that the welfare economics theorems allow the political economy to be studied in the following two situations: "market failure" and "the problem of redistribution".<ref name="Lockwood">Lockwood B. (2008) ''Pareto Efficiency''. In: Palgrave Macmillan (eds.) ''The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics''. Palgrave Macmillan, London.</ref> Analysis of "market failure" can be understood by the literature surrounding externalities. When comparing the "real" economy to the complete contingent markets economy (which is considered efficient), the inefficiencies become clear. These inefficiencies, or externalities, are then able to be addressed by mechanisms, including property rights and corrective taxes.<ref name="Lockwood"/> Analysis of "the problem with redistribution" deals with the observed political question of how income or commodity taxes should be utilized. The theorem tells us that no taxation is Pareto-efficient and that taxation with redistribution is Pareto-inefficient. Because of this, most of the literature is focused on finding solutions where given there is a tax structure, how can the tax structure prescribe a situation where no person could be made better off by a change in available taxes.<ref name="Lockwood"/> == Use in biology == Pareto optimisation has also been studied in biological processes.<ref>Moore, J. H., Hill, D. P., Sulovari, A., & Kidd, L. C., "Genetic Analysis of Prostate Cancer Using Computational Evolution, Pareto-Optimization and Post-processing", in R. Riolo, E. Vladislavleva, M. D. Ritchie, & J. H. Moore (eds.), ''Genetic Programming Theory and Practice X'' (Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, 2013), [https://books.google.com/books?id=YZZAAAAAQBAJ&pg=PA86 pp. 87–102].</ref> In bacteria, [[Gene|genes]] were shown to be either inexpensive to make (resource-efficient) or easier to read ([[Translation (biology)|translation]]-efficient). [[Natural selection]] acts to push highly expressed genes towards the Pareto frontier for resource use and translational efficiency.<ref>Eiben, A. E., & Smith, J. E., ''Introduction to Evolutionary Computing'' (Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, 2003), [https://books.google.com/books?id=7IOE5VIpFpwC&pg=PT166 pp. 166–169].</ref> Genes near the Pareto frontier were also shown to evolve more slowly (indicating that they are providing a selective advantage).<ref>Seward, E. A., & Kelly, S., [https://genomebiology.biomedcentral.com/articles/10.1186/s13059-018-1480-7 "Selection-driven cost-efficiency optimization of transcripts modulates gene evolutionary rate in bacteria"], ''[[Genome Biology]]'', Vol. 19, 2018.</ref> == Common misconceptions == It would be incorrect to treat Pareto efficiency as equivalent to societal optimization,<ref>[[Jacques Drèze|Drèze, J.]], ''Essays on Economic Decisions Under Uncertainty'' ([[Cambridge]]: [[Cambridge University Press]], 1987), [https://books.google.com/books?id=LWE4AAAAIAAJ&pg=PA358 pp. 358–364].</ref> as the latter is a [[normative]] concept, which is a matter of interpretation that typically would account for the consequence of degrees of inequality of distribution.<ref>Backhaus, J. G., ''The Elgar Companion to Law and Economics'' ([[Cheltenham|Cheltenham, UK]] / [[Northampton, MA]]: [[Edward Elgar Publishing|Edward Elgar]], 2005), [https://books.google.com/books?id=EtguKoWHUHYC&pg=PA10 pp. 10–15].</ref> An example would be the interpretation of one school district with low property tax revenue versus another with much higher revenue as a sign that more equal distribution occurs with the help of government redistribution.<ref>Paulsen, M. B., "The Economics of the Public Sector: The Nature and Role of Public Policy in the Finance of Higher Education", in M. B. Paulsen, J. C. Smart (eds.) ''The Finance of Higher Education: Theory, Research, Policy, and Practice'' (New York: Agathon Press, 2001), [https://books.google.com/books?id=BlkPAy-gb8sC&pg=PA95 pp. 95–132].</ref> ==Criticism== Some commentators contest that Pareto efficiency could potentially serve as an ideological tool. With it implying that capitalism is self-regulated thereof, it is likely that the embedded structural problems such as unemployment would be treated as deviating from the equilibrium or norm, and thus neglected or discounted.<ref name="Palgrave Macmillan" /> Pareto efficiency does not require a totally equitable distribution of wealth, which is another aspect that draws in criticism.<ref>Bhushi, K. (ed.), ''Farm to Fingers: The Culture and Politics of Food in Contemporary India'' (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2018), [https://books.google.com/books?id=NYJIDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA222 p. 222].</ref> An economy in which a wealthy few hold the [[Wealth condensation|vast majority of resources]] can be Pareto-efficient. A simple example is the distribution of a pie among three people. The most equitable distribution would assign one third to each person. However, the assignment of, say, a half section to each of two individuals and none to the third is also Pareto-optimal despite not being equitable, because none of the recipients could be made better off without decreasing someone else's share; and there are many other such distribution examples. An example of a Pareto-inefficient distribution of the pie would be allocation of a quarter of the pie to each of the three, with the remainder discarded.<ref>Wittman, D., ''Economic Foundations of Law and Organization'' (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006), [https://books.google.com/books?id=fOolQOtKM7QC&pg=PA18 p. 18].</ref> The [[liberal paradox]] elaborated by [[Amartya Sen]] shows that when people have preferences about what other people do, the goal of Pareto efficiency can come into conflict with the goal of individual liberty.<ref>Sen, A., ''Rationality and Freedom'' ([[Cambridge, Massachusetts|Cambridge, MA]] / London: [[Harvard University Press|Belknep Press]], 2004), [https://books.google.com/books?id=DaOY4DQ-MKAC&pg=PA92 pp. 92–94].</ref> Lastly, it is proposed that Pareto efficiency to some extent inhibited discussion of other possible criteria of efficiency. As [[Wharton School]] professor Ben Lockwood argues, one possible reason is that any other efficiency criteria established in the neoclassical domain will reduce to Pareto efficiency at the end.<ref name="Palgrave Macmillan"/> ==See also== * [[Admissible decision rule]], analog in [[decision theory]] * [[Arrow's impossibility theorem]] * [[Bayesian efficiency]] * [[Fundamental theorems of welfare economics]] * [[Deadweight loss]] * [[Economic efficiency]] * [[Highest and best use]] * [[Kaldor–Hicks efficiency]] * [[Marginal utility]] * [[Market failure]], when a market result is not Pareto-optimal * [[Maximal element]], concept in [[order theory]] * [[Maxima of a point set]] * [[Multi-objective optimization]] * [[Nash equilibrium]] * [[Pareto-efficient envy-free division]] * ''[[Social Choice and Individual Values]]'' for the "(weak) Pareto principle" * [[Stable marriage problem]] * [[Trade-off talking rational economic person|TOTREP]] * [[Welfare economics]] ==References== {{reflist|30em}} Pareto, V (1906). Manual of Political Economy. Oxford University Press. https://global.oup.com/academic/product/manual-of-political-economy-9780199607952?cc=ca&lang=en&. == Further reading == * {{Cite Fudenberg Tirole 1991|pages=[https://books.google.com/books?id=pFPHKwXro3QC&pg=PA18 18–23]}} * {{Cite journal |last1=Bendor | first1=Jonathan |last2= Mookherjee | first2=Dilip | title = Communitarian versus Universalistic norms | journal = [[Quarterly Journal of Political Science]] | volume = 3 | issue = 1 | pages = 33–61 | doi = 10.1561/100.00007028 | date = April 2008 }} * {{Cite journal | last = Kanbur | first = Ravi| author-link = Ravi Kanbur | title = Pareto's revenge | journal = Journal of Social and Economic Development | volume = 7 | issue = 1 | pages = 1–11 | date = January–June 2005 | url = http://www.arts.cornell.edu/poverty/kanbur/ParRev.pdf }} * {{cite book | last = Ng | first = Yew-Kwang | author-link = Yew-Kwang Ng | title = Welfare economics towards a more complete analysis | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=o-2GDAAAQBAJ| publisher = Palgrave Macmillan | location = Basingstoke, Hampshire New York | year = 2004 | isbn = 9780333971215 }} * {{Citation | author-first1=Ariel | author-last1=Rubinstein | author-first2=Martin J. | author-last2=Osborne | author-link1 = Ariel Rubinstein | contribution = Introduction | editor-first1=Ariel | editor-last1=Rubinstein | editor-first2=Martin J. | editor-last2=Osborne | editor-link1 = Ariel Rubinstein | title = A course in game theory | pages = 6–7 | publisher = MIT Press | location = Cambridge, Massachusetts | year = 1994 | isbn = 9780262650403 }} [https://books.google.com/books?id=5ntdaYX4LPkC&pg=PA6 Book preview.] * {{Cite journal | last = Mathur | first = Vijay K. | title = How well do we know Pareto optimality? | journal = The Journal of Economic Education | volume = 22 | issue = 2 | pages = 172–178 | doi = 10.2307/1182422 | date = Spring 1991 | jstor = 1182422 }} * {{Cite journal | last1 = Newbery | first1 = David M.G. | last2 = Stiglitz | first2 = Joseph E. | author-link1 = David Newbery | author-link2 = Joseph Stiglitz | title = Pareto inferior trade | journal = [[The Review of Economic Studies]] | volume = 51 | issue = 1 | pages = 1–12 | doi = 10.2307/2297701 | date = January 1984 | jstor = 2297701 }} {{Economics}} {{Game theory}} {{Vilfredo Pareto}} {{Voting systems}} {{Authority control}} {{DEFAULTSORT:Pareto Efficiency}} [[Category:Pareto efficiency| ]] [[Category:Game theory]] [[Category:Law and economics]] [[Category:Welfare economics]] [[Category:Management theory]] [[Category:Mathematical optimization]] [[Category:Electoral system criteria]] [[Category:Vilfredo Pareto]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:'
(
edit
)
Template:Anchor
(
edit
)
Template:Authority control
(
edit
)
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:Cite Fudenberg Tirole 1991
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Doi
(
edit
)
Template:Economics
(
edit
)
Template:Economics sidebar
(
edit
)
Template:Game theory
(
edit
)
Template:Main
(
edit
)
Template:Navbox with collapsible groups
(
edit
)
Template:Nobr
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:See also
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Snd
(
edit
)
Template:Use mdy dates
(
edit
)
Template:Vilfredo Pareto
(
edit
)
Template:Voting systems
(
edit
)