Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Postcognitivism
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Movements in cognitive science critical of cognitivism}} Movements in [[cognitive science]] are considered to be '''post-cognitivist''' if they are opposed to or move beyond the [[Cognitivism (psychology)|cognitivist]] theories posited by [[Noam Chomsky]], [[Jerry Fodor]], [[David Marr (psychologist)|David Marr]], and others. Postcognitivists challenge tenets within cognitivism, including ontological [[wikt:dualism|dualism]], [[direct and indirect realism|representational realism]], that cognition is independent of processes outside the mind and nervous system, that the electronic computer is an appropriate analogy for the mind, and that cognition occurs only within individuals.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Wallace |first1=B |last2=Ross |first2=A |last3=Davies |first3=J.B |last4=Anderson |first4=T |title=The Mind, the Body and the World: Psychology after Cognitivism |date=2007 |publisher=Imprint Academic |location=London |isbn=978-1-84540-073-6}}</ref> Researchers who have followed post-cognitive directions include [[James J. Gibson]], [[Hubert Dreyfus]], [[Gregory Bateson]], [[Michael Turvey]], [[Bradd Shore]], [[Jerome Bruner]], [[Vittorio Guidano]], [[Humberto Maturana]] and [[Francisco Varela]].<ref>Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.</ref> ==Hubert Dreyfus' critique of cognitivism== {{criticism section |date=April 2024}} Using the principles of [[Martin Heidegger]]'s philosophy, Dreyfus has been critical of cognitivism from the beginning. Despite continued resistance by old-school philosophers of cognition, he felt vindicated by the growth of new approaches. When Dreyfus' ideas were first introduced in the mid-1960s, they were met with ridicule and outright hostility.{{sfn|McCorduck|2004|pp=211–243}}{{sfn|Crevier|1993|pp=120–132}} By the 1980s, however, many of his perspectives were rediscovered by researchers working in [[robotics]] and the new field of [[connectionism]]—approaches now called "[[sub-symbolic]]" because they eschew early [[artificial intelligence]] (AI) research's emphasis on high level symbols. Historian and AI researcher [[Daniel Crevier]] writes: "time has proven the accuracy and perceptiveness of some of Dreyfus's comments."{{sfn|Crevier|1993|p=125}} Dreyfus said in 2007 "I figure I won and it's over—they've given up."<ref>Quoted in {{Harvnb|Fearn|2007|p=51}}</ref> In ''Mind Over Machine'' (1986), written during the heyday of [[expert system]]s, Dreyfus analyzed the difference between human expertise and the programs that claimed to capture it. This expanded on ideas from ''What Computers Can't Do'', where he had made a similar argument criticizing the "[[cognitive simulation]]" school of AI research practiced by [[Allen Newell]] and [[Herbert A. Simon]] in the 1960s.{{cn|date=September 2024}} Dreyfus argued that human problem solving and expertise depend on our background sense of the context, of what is important and interesting given the situation, rather than on the process of searching through combinations of possibilities to find what we need. Dreyfus would describe it in 1986 as the difference between "knowing-that" and "knowing-how", based on Heidegger's distinction of [[present-at-hand]] and [[ready-to-hand]].<ref>{{Harvnb|Dreyfus|Dreyfus|1986}} and see [http://socrates.berkeley.edu/~hdreyfus/html/paper_socrates.html From Socrates to Expert Systems]. The "knowing-how"/"knowing-that" terminology was introduced in the 1950s by philosopher [[Gilbert Ryle]].</ref> Knowing-that is our conscious, step-by-step problem-solving abilities. We use these skills when we encounter a difficult problem that requires us to stop, step back and search through ideas one at a time. At moments like this, the ideas become very precise and simple: they become context-free symbols, which we manipulate using logic and language. These are the skills that Newell and Simon had demonstrated with both psychological experiments and computer programs. Dreyfus agreed that their programs adequately imitated the skills he calls "knowing-that".{{cn|date=September 2024}} Knowing-how, on the other hand, is the way we deal with things normally. We take actions without using conscious symbolic reasoning at all, as when we recognize a face, drive ourselves to work, or find the right thing to say. We seem to simply jump to the appropriate response, without considering any alternatives. This is the essence of expertise, Dreyfus argued: when our intuitions have been trained to the point that we forget the rules and simply "size up the situation" and react.{{cn|date=September 2024}} The human sense of the situation, according to Dreyfus, is based on our goals, our bodies, and our culture—all of our unconscious intuitions, attitudes, and knowledge about the world. This "context" or "background" (related to Heidegger's [[Dasein]]) is a form of knowledge that is not stored in our brains symbolically, but intuitively in some way. It affects what we notice and what we do not, what we expect, and what possibilities we do not consider: we discriminate between what is essential and inessential. The things that are inessential are relegated to our "fringe consciousness" (borrowing a phrase from [[William James]]): the millions of things we are aware of but are not really thinking about right now.{{cn|date=September 2024}} Dreyfus did not believe that AI programs, as they were implemented in the 1970s and 1980s, could capture this "background" or do the kind of fast problem solving that it allows. He argued that our unconscious knowledge could ''never'' be captured symbolically. If AI could not find a way to address these issues, then it was doomed to failure, an exercise in "tree climbing with one's eyes on the moon."{{sfn|Dreyfus|1992|p=119}} ===Examples of postcognitivist thinking=== * [[Action-specific perception]] * [[Activity theory]] * [[Autopoiesis]] * [[Direct realism]] * [[Discursive psychology]] * [[Distributed cognition]] * [[Dynamicism]] * [[Ecological psychology]] * [[Embodied cognition]] * [[Embodied embedded cognition]] * [[Enactivism]] * [[Group cognition]] * [[Neurophenomenology]] * [[Postcognitive psychology]] * [[Situated cognition]] ==Notes== {{Reflist}} ==References== * Costall, A. and Still, A. (eds) (1987) ''Cognitive Psychology in Question''. Brighton: Harvester Press Ltd. * Costall, A. and Still, A. (eds) (1991) ''Against Cognitivism: Alternative Foundations for Cognitive Psychology.'' New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf. * {{Crevier 1993}} * {{Citation | last1=Dreyfus | first1=Hubert | author-link = Hubert Dreyfus | last2 = Dreyfus | first2 = Stuart | authorlink2 = Stuart Dreyfus | year = 1986 | title = Mind over Machine: The Power of Human Intuition and Expertise in the Era of the Computer | publisher = Blackwell | location = Oxford, U.K. }} * {{citation | last=Dreyfus | first=Hubert | author-link = Hubert Dreyfus | year =1992 | title = What Computers ''Still'' Can't Do | publisher = MIT Press | location = New York | isbn=978-0-262-54067-4 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=7vS2y-mQmpAC }} * {{Citation | last=Fearn | first = Nicholas | year =2007 | title= The Latest Answers to the Oldest Questions: A Philosophical Adventure with the World's Greatest Thinkers | publisher = Grove Press | location=New York | isbn = 9780802143471 | url=https://books.google.com/books?id=kXBsBnF_DVsC&q=Dreyfus }} * {{McCorduck 2004}} * Potter, J. (2000). "Post cognitivist psychology", ''Theory and Psychology, 10'', 31–37. * Stahl, G. (2015). ''The group as paradigmatic unit of analysis: The contested relationship of CSCL to the learning sciences.'' In M. Evans, M. Packer & K. Sawyer (Eds.), The learning sciences: Mapping the terrain. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Web: http://GerryStahl.net/pub/ls.pdf. * Wallace, B., Ross, A., Davies, J.B., and Anderson, T. (2007) ''The Mind, The Body and the World: Psychology After Cognitivism.'' London: Imprint Academic. * Witt, J. K. (2011). "Action's Effect on Perception", ''Current Directions in Psychological Sciences, 20'',201-206. * Zielke, B. (2004) ''Kognition und soziale Praxis: Der Soziale Konstruktionismus und die Perspektiven einer postkognitivistischen Psychologie.'' Bielefeld: transcript. [[Category:Enactive cognition]] [[Category:Psychological schools]] [[Category:Psychological theories]] {{psych-stub}}
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Asbox
(
edit
)
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cn
(
edit
)
Template:Crevier 1993
(
edit
)
Template:Criticism section
(
edit
)
Template:Harvnb
(
edit
)
Template:McCorduck 2004
(
edit
)
Template:Psych-stub
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Sfn
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)