Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Principle of explosion
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Theorem in formal logic}} {{redirect|EFQ|the literary baseball journal|Elysian Fields Quarterly}} {{redirect|Ex falso quodlibet|the musical form|Quodlibet|the audio player and library organizer|Quod Libet (software)||}} {{More citations needed|date=August 2020}} In [[classical logic]], [[intuitionistic logic]], and similar [[Formal system|logical systems]], the '''principle of explosion'''{{efn|{{Langx|la|ex falso [sequitur] quodlibet}}, 'from falsehood, anything [follows]'; or {{Langx|la|ex contradictione [sequitur] quodlibet|lit=from contradiction, anything [follows]|label=none}}.}}{{efn|Also known as the '''principle of Pseudo-Scotus''' (falsely attributed to [[Pseudo-Scotus|Duns Scotus]]).}} is the [[Laws of logic (disambiguation)|law]] according to which any [[Statement (logic)|statement]] can be proven from a [[contradiction]].<ref>{{cite journal |author1-link=Walter Carnielli |last1=Carnielli |first=Walter |first2=João |last2=Marcos |title=Ex contradictione non sequitur quodlibet |journal=Bulletin of Advanced Reasoning and Knowledge |volume=1 |issue= |pages=89–109 |date=2001 |doi= |url=https://www.advancedreasoningforum.org/galeria/docs/2023/07/25/1690305935.pdf }}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Smith |first1=Peter |title=An Introduction to Formal Logic |date=2020 |publisher=Cambridge University Press |edition=2nd |url=https://www.logicmatters.net/resources/pdfs/IFL2_LM.pdf }} Chapter 17.</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=MacFarlane |first1=John |title=Philosophical Logic: A Contemporary Introduction |date=2021 |publisher=Routledge}} Chapter 7.</ref> That is, from a contradiction, any [[proposition]] (including its [[negation]]) can be inferred; this is known as '''deductive explosion'''.<ref>{{cite journal | journal=[[Synthese]] | title=Some topological properties of paraconsistent models | last1=Başkent | first1=Can | date=2013 | doi=10.1007/s11229-013-0246-8 | volume=190 | issue=18 | page=4023 | s2cid=9276566 }}</ref><ref>{{cite book | series=Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science | publisher=Springer | title=Paraconsistent Logic: Consistency, Contradiction and Negation | last1=Carnielli | first1=Walter | last2=Coniglio | first2=Marcelo Esteban | volume=40 | year=2016 | doi=10.1007/978-3-319-33205-5 | isbn=978-3-319-33203-1 | at=ix}}</ref> The proof of this principle was first given by 12th-century French philosopher [[William of Soissons]].<ref> [[Graham Priest|Priest, Graham]]. 2011. "What's so bad about contradictions?" In ''The Law of Non-Contradicton'', edited by Priest, Beal, and Armour-Garb. Oxford: Clarendon Press. p. 25.</ref> Due to the principle of explosion, the existence of a contradiction ([[inconsistency]]) in a [[formal system|formal axiomatic system]] is disastrous; since any statement can be proven, it trivializes the concepts of truth and falsity.<ref name="McKubre-Jordens">{{cite web|last=McKubre-Jordens|first=Maarten|date=August 2011|title=This is not a carrot: Paraconsistent mathematics|url=https://plus.maths.org/content/not-carrot|access-date=January 14, 2017|work=Plus Magazine|publisher=Millennium Mathematics Project}}</ref> Around the turn of the 20th century, the discovery of contradictions such as [[Russell's paradox]] at the foundations of mathematics thus threatened the entire structure of mathematics. Mathematicians such as [[Gottlob Frege]], [[Ernst Zermelo]], [[Abraham Fraenkel]], and [[Thoralf Skolem]] put much effort into revising [[set theory]] to eliminate these contradictions, resulting in the modern [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]]. As a demonstration of the principle, consider two contradictory statements—"All [[lemon]]s are yellow" and "Not all lemons are yellow"—and suppose that both are true. If that is the case, anything can be proven, e.g., the assertion that "[[unicorn]]s exist", by using the following argument: # We know that "Not all lemons are yellow", as it has been assumed to be true. # We know that "All lemons are yellow", as it has been assumed to be true. # Therefore, the two-part statement "All lemons are yellow ''or'' unicorns exist" must also be true, since the first part of the statement ("All lemons are yellow") has already been assumed, and the use of "''or''" means that if even one part of the statement is true, the statement as a whole must be true as well. # However, since we also know that "Not all lemons are yellow" (as this has been assumed), the first part is false, and hence the second part must be true to ensure the two-part statement to be true, i.e., unicorns exist (this inference is known as the [[disjunctive syllogism]]). # The procedure may be repeated to prove that unicorns do ''not'' exist (hence proving an additional contradiction where unicorns do and do not exist), as well as any other [[well-formed formula]]. Thus, there is an ''explosion'' of true statements. In a different solution to the problems posed by the principle of explosion, some mathematicians have devised alternative theories of [[logic (mathematics)|logic]] called [[paraconsistent logic|''paraconsistent logics'']], which allow some contradictory statements to be proven without affecting the truth value of (all) other statements.<ref name="McKubre-Jordens" /> ==Symbolic representation== In [[symbolic logic]], the principle of explosion can be expressed schematically in the following way:<ref>{{cite book |last1=de Swart |first1=Harrie |title=Philosophical and Mathematical Logic |date=2018 |publisher=Springer }} p. 47.</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Gamut |first1=L. T. F. |title=Logic, Language and Meaning, Volume 1. Introduction to Logic |date=1991 |publisher=University of Chicago Press}} p. 139.</ref> {{block indent | <math> P, \lnot P \vdash Q</math> For any statements ''P'' and ''Q'', if ''P'' and not-''P'' are both true, then it logically follows that ''Q'' is true.}} == Proof == Below is the '''Lewis argument''',<ref name="MacFarlane2021"/> a formal proof of the principle of explosion using [[symbolic logic]]. {| class="wikitable" style="margin-left: auto; margin-right: auto; border: none; width: 45%" |- ! style="width:5%" | Step ! style="width:15%" | Proposition ! style="width:25%" | Derivation |- | 1 || <math>P\land\neg P</math> || Premise{{efn|Burgess2005 uses 2 and 3 as premises instead of this one}} |- | 2 || <math>P</math> || [[Conjunction elimination]] (1) |- | 3 || <math>\neg P</math> || [[Conjunction elimination]] (1) |- | 4 || <math>P \lor Q</math> || [[Disjunction introduction]] (2) |- | 5 || <math>Q</math> || [[Disjunctive syllogism]] (4,3) |- |} This proof was published by [[C. I. Lewis]] and is named after him, though versions of it were known to medieval logicians.<ref>{{cite book | last1=Lewis | first1=C I | last2=Langford | first2=C H | title=Symbolic Logic | edition=2nd | date=1959 | publisher=Dover | pages=250 | ISBN=9780486601700}} </ref><ref name="Burgess2005"> {{cite book | last1=Burgess | first1=John P | title=The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic (ed Stewart Shapiro) | date=2005 | publisher=Oxford University Press |page=732| ISBN=9780195325928}} </ref><ref name="MacFarlane2021">{{cite book | last1=MacFarlane | first1=John | title=Philosophical Logic: A Contemporary Introduction | date=2021 | publisher=Routledge | page=171 | ISBN=978-1-315-18524-8}}</ref> This is just the symbolic version of the informal argument given in the introduction, with <math>P</math> standing for "all lemons are yellow" and <math>Q</math> standing for "Unicorns exist". We start out by assuming that (1) all lemons are yellow and that (2) not all lemons are yellow. From the proposition that all lemons are yellow, we infer that (3) either all lemons are yellow or unicorns exist. But then from this and the fact that not all lemons are yellow, we infer that (4) unicorns exist by disjunctive syllogism. ===Semantic argument=== An alternate argument for the principle stems from [[model theory]]. A sentence <math>P</math> is a ''[[semantic consequence]]'' of a set of sentences <math>\Gamma</math> only if every model of <math>\Gamma</math> is a model of <math>P</math>. However, there is no model of the contradictory set <math>(P \wedge \lnot P)</math>. [[A fortiori]], there is no model of <math>(P \wedge \lnot P)</math> that is not a model of <math>Q</math>. Thus, vacuously, every model of <math>(P \wedge \lnot P)</math> is a model of <math>Q</math>. Thus <math>Q</math> is a semantic consequence of <math>(P \wedge \lnot P)</math>. ==Paraconsistent logic== [[Paraconsistent logic]]s have been developed that allow for [[subcontrary]]-forming operators. [[Formal semantics (logic)|Model-theoretic]] paraconsistent logicians often deny the assumption that there can be no model of <math>\{\phi , \lnot \phi \}</math> and devise semantical systems in which there are such models. Alternatively, they reject the idea that propositions can be classified as true or false. [[Proof-theoretic semantics|Proof-theoretic]] paraconsistent logics usually deny the validity of one of the steps necessary for deriving an explosion, typically including [[disjunctive syllogism]], [[disjunction introduction]], and ''[[reductio ad absurdum]]''. ==Usage== The [[metamathematics|metamathematical]] value of the principle of explosion is that for any logical system where this principle holds, any derived [[mathematical theory|theory]] which proves [[false (logic)|⊥]] (or an equivalent form, <math>\phi \land \lnot \phi</math>) is worthless because ''all'' its [[statement (logic)|statements]] would become [[theorem]]s, making it impossible to distinguish [[truth]] from falsehood. That is to say, the principle of explosion is an argument for the [[law of non-contradiction]] in classical logic, because without it all truth statements become meaningless. Reduction in proof strength of logics without the principle of explosion are discussed in [[minimal logic]]. ==See also== * [[Consequentia mirabilis]] – Clavius' Law * [[Dialetheism]] – belief in the existence of true contradictions * [[Law of excluded middle]] – every proposition is true or false * [[Law of noncontradiction]] – no proposition can be both true and not true * [[Paraconsistent logic]] – a family of logics used to address contradictions * [[Paradox of entailment]] – a seeming paradox derived from the principle of explosion * [[Reductio ad absurdum]] – concluding that a proposition is false because it produces a contradiction * [[Trivialism]] – the belief that all statements of the form "P and not-P" are true ==Notes== {{Notelist}} ==References== {{reflist}} {{Classical logic}} [[Category:Theorems in propositional logic]] [[Category:Classical logic]] [[Category:Principles]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Block indent
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Classical logic
(
edit
)
Template:Efn
(
edit
)
Template:More citations needed
(
edit
)
Template:Notelist
(
edit
)
Template:Redirect
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)