Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Quantum indeterminacy
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Apparent lack of definite state before measurement of quantum systems}} {{Use American English|date=January 2019}}{{Quantum mechanics}}{{More citations needed|date=December 2008}} '''Quantum indeterminacy''' is the apparent ''necessary'' incompleteness in the description of a [[physical system]], that has become one of the characteristics of the standard description of [[quantum physics]]. Prior to quantum physics, it was thought that {{ordered list | list-style-type = lower-alpha | a physical system had a determinate [[Classical mechanics|state]] that uniquely determined all the values of its measurable properties, and | [[conversely]], the values of its measurable properties uniquely determined the state. }} '''Quantum indeterminacy''' can be quantitatively characterized by a [[probability distribution]] on the set of outcomes of [[Measurement problem|measurements]] of an [[observable]]. The distribution is uniquely determined by the system state, and moreover quantum mechanics provides a recipe for calculating this probability distribution. Indeterminacy in measurement was not an innovation of quantum mechanics, since it had been established early on by experimentalists that [[Observational error|errors]] in measurement may lead to indeterminate outcomes. By the later half of the 18th century, measurement errors were well understood, and it was known that they could either be reduced by better equipment or accounted for by statistical error models. In quantum mechanics, however, [[Uncertainty principle|indeterminacy]] is of a much more fundamental nature, having nothing to do with errors or disturbance. == Measurement == An adequate account of quantum indeterminacy requires a theory of measurement. Many theories have been proposed since the beginning of [[quantum mechanics]] and [[quantum measurement]] continues to be an active research area in both theoretical and experimental physics.<ref>V. Braginski and F. Khalili, ''Quantum Measurements'', Cambridge University Press, 1992.</ref> Possibly the first systematic attempt at a mathematical theory was developed by [[John von Neumann]]. The kinds of measurements he investigated are now called projective measurements. That theory was based in turn on the theory of [[projection-valued measure]]s for [[self-adjoint operator]]s that had been recently developed (by von Neumann and independently by [[Marshall Stone]]) and the [[mathematical formulation of quantum mechanics|Hilbert space formulation of quantum mechanics]] (attributed by von Neumann to [[Paul Dirac]]). In this formulation, the state of a physical system corresponds to a [[Vector (geometry)|vector]] of length 1 in a [[Hilbert space]] ''H'' over the [[complex number]]s. An observable is represented by a self-adjoint (i.e. [[Hermitian operator|Hermitian]]) operator ''A'' on ''H''. If ''H'' is finite [[Vector space dimension|dimensional]], by the [[spectral theorem]], ''A'' has an [[orthonormal basis]] of [[eigenvector]]s. If the system is in state ''ψ'', then immediately after measurement the system will occupy a state that is an eigenvector ''e'' of ''A'' and the observed value ''λ'' will be the corresponding eigenvalue of the equation {{nowrap|1=''Ae'' = ''λe''}}. It is immediate from this that measurement in general will be non-deterministic. Quantum mechanics, moreover, gives a recipe for computing a probability distribution Pr on the possible outcomes given the initial system state is ''ψ''. The probability is <math display="block"> \operatorname{Pr}(\lambda)= \langle \operatorname{E}(\lambda) \psi \mid \psi \rangle </math> where ''E''(''λ'') is the projection onto the space of eigenvectors of ''A'' with eigenvalue ''λ''. === Example === [[Image:PauliSpinStateSpace.png|frame|right|[[Bloch sphere]] showing eigenvectors for Pauli Spin matrices. The Bloch sphere is a two-dimensional surface the points of which correspond to the state space of a spin 1/2 particle. At the state ''ψ'' the values of ''σ''<sub>1</sub> are +1 whereas the values of ''σ''<sub>2</sub> and ''σ''<sub>3</sub> take the values +1, −1 with probability 1/2.]] In this example, we consider a single [[Spin-1/2|spin 1/2]] [[Elementary particle|particle]] (such as an electron) in which we only consider the spin degree of freedom. The corresponding Hilbert space is the two-dimensional complex Hilbert space '''C'''<sup>2</sup>, with each quantum state corresponding to a unit vector in '''C'''<sup>2</sup> (unique up to phase). In this case, the state space can be geometrically represented as the surface of a sphere, as shown in the figure on the right. The [[Pauli matrix|Pauli spin matrices]] <math display="block"> \sigma_1 = \begin{pmatrix} 0&1\\ 1&0 \end{pmatrix}, \quad \sigma_2 = \begin{pmatrix} 0&-i\\ i&0 \end{pmatrix}, \quad \sigma_3 = \begin{pmatrix} 1&0\\ 0&-1 \end{pmatrix} </math> are [[self-adjoint]] and correspond to spin-measurements along the 3 coordinate axes. The Pauli matrices all have the eigenvalues +1, −1. * For ''σ''<sub>1</sub>, these eigenvalues correspond to the eigenvectors <math display="block"> \frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} (1,1), \frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} (1,-1) </math> * For ''σ''<sub>3</sub>, they correspond to the eigenvectors <math display="block"> (1, 0), (0,1) </math> Thus in the state <math display="block"> \psi = \frac{1}{\sqrt{2}} (1,1), </math> ''σ''<sub>1</sub> has the determinate value +1, while measurement of ''σ''<sub>3</sub> can produce either +1, −1 each with probability 1/2. In fact, there is no state in which measurement of both ''σ''<sub>1</sub> and ''σ''<sub>3</sub> have determinate values. There are various questions that can be asked about the above indeterminacy assertion. # Can the apparent indeterminacy be construed as in fact deterministic, but dependent upon quantities not modeled in the current theory, which would therefore be incomplete? More precisely, are there ''hidden variables'' that could account for the statistical indeterminacy in a completely classical way? # Can the indeterminacy be understood as a disturbance of the system being measured? Von Neumann formulated the question 1) and provided an argument why the answer had to be no, ''if'' one accepted the formalism he was proposing. However, according to Bell, von Neumann's formal proof did not justify his informal conclusion.<ref>J.S. Bell, ''Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics'', Cambridge University Press, 2004, pg. 5.</ref> A definitive but partial negative answer to 1) has been established by experiment: because [[Bell's inequalities]] are violated, any such hidden variable(s) cannot be ''local'' (see [[Bell test experiments]]). The answer to 2) depends on how disturbance is understood, particularly since measurement entails disturbance (however note that this is the [[Observer effect (physics)|observer effect]], which is distinct from the uncertainty principle). Still, in the most natural interpretation the answer is also no. To see this, consider two sequences of measurements: (A) that measures exclusively ''σ''<sub>1</sub> and (B) that measures only ''σ''<sub>3</sub> of a spin system in the state ''ψ''. The measurement outcomes of (A) are all +1, while the statistical distribution of the measurements (B) is still divided between +1, −1 with equal probability. === Other examples of indeterminacy === Quantum indeterminacy can also be illustrated in terms of a particle with a definitely measured momentum for which there must be a fundamental limit to how precisely its location can be specified. This quantum [[uncertainty principle]] can be expressed in terms of other variables, for example, a particle with a definitely measured energy has a fundamental limit to how precisely one can specify how long it will have that energy. The magnitude involved in quantum uncertainty is on the order of the [[Planck constant]] ({{physconst|h}}). == Indeterminacy and incompleteness == Quantum indeterminacy is the assertion that the state of a system does not determine a unique collection of values for all its measurable properties. Indeed, according to the [[Kochen–Specker theorem]], in the quantum mechanical formalism it is impossible that, for a given quantum state, each one of these measurable properties ([[observable]]s) has a determinate (sharp) value. The values of an observable will be obtained non-deterministically in accordance with a probability distribution that is uniquely determined by the system state. Note that the state is destroyed by measurement, so when we refer to a collection of values, each measured value in this collection must be obtained using a freshly prepared state. This indeterminacy might be regarded as a kind of essential incompleteness in our description of a physical system. Notice however, that the indeterminacy as stated above only applies to values of measurements not to the quantum state. For example, in the spin 1/2 example discussed above, the system can be prepared in the state ''ψ'' by using measurement of ''σ''<sub>1</sub> as a ''filter'' that retains only those particles such that ''σ''<sub>1</sub> yields +1. By the von Neumann (so-called) postulates, immediately after the measurement the system is assuredly in the state ''ψ''. However, [[Albert Einstein]] believed that quantum state cannot be a complete description of a physical system and, it is commonly thought, never came to terms with quantum mechanics. In fact, Einstein, [[Boris Podolsky]] and [[Nathan Rosen]] showed that if quantum mechanics is correct, then the classical view of how the real world works (at least after special relativity) is no longer tenable. This view included the following two ideas: # A measurable property of a physical system whose value can be predicted with certainty is actually an element of (local) reality (this was the terminology used by [[EPR paradox|EPR]]). # Effects of local actions have a finite propagation speed. This failure of the classical view was one of the conclusions of the EPR [[thought experiment]] in which two remotely located [[observation|observers]], now commonly referred to as [[Alice and Bob]], perform independent measurements of spin on a pair of electrons, prepared at a source in a special state called a [[spin singlet]] state. It was a conclusion of EPR, using the formal apparatus of quantum theory, that once Alice measured spin in the ''x'' direction, Bob's measurement in the ''x'' direction was determined with certainty, whereas immediately before Alice's measurement Bob's outcome was only statistically determined. From this it follows that either value of spin in the ''x'' direction is not an element of reality or that the effect of Alice's measurement has infinite speed of propagation. == Indeterminacy for mixed states == We have described indeterminacy for a quantum system that is in a [[pure state]]. [[Mixed state (physics)|Mixed state]]s are a more general kind of state obtained by a statistical mixture of pure states. For mixed states the "quantum recipe" for determining the probability distribution of a measurement is determined as follows: Let ''A'' be an observable of a quantum mechanical system. ''A'' is given by a densely defined self-adjoint operator on ''H''. The [[spectral measure]] of ''A'' is a projection-valued measure defined by the condition : <math> \operatorname{E}_A(U) = \int_U \lambda \, d \operatorname{E}(\lambda), </math> for every Borel subset ''U'' of '''R'''. Given a mixed state ''S'', we introduce the ''distribution'' of ''A'' under ''S'' as follows: : <math> \operatorname{D}_A(U) = \operatorname{Tr}(\operatorname{E}_A(U) S). </math> This is a probability measure defined on the Borel subsets of '''R''' that is the probability distribution obtained by measuring ''A'' in ''S''. == Logical independence and quantum randomness == Quantum indeterminacy is often understood as information (or lack of it) whose existence we infer, occurring in individual quantum systems, prior to measurement. ''Quantum randomness'' is the statistical manifestation of that indeterminacy, witnessable in results of experiments repeated many times. However, the relationship between quantum indeterminacy and randomness is subtle and can be considered differently.<ref>Gregg Jaeger, "Quantum randomness and unpredictability" Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London A doi/10.1002/prop.201600053 (2016)|Online=http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/prop.201600053/epdf PDF</ref> In ''classical physics'', experiments of chance, such as coin-tossing and dice-throwing, are deterministic, in the sense that, perfect knowledge of the initial conditions would render outcomes perfectly predictable. The ‘randomness’ stems from ignorance of physical information in the initial toss or throw. In diametrical contrast, in the case of ''quantum physics'', the theorems of Kochen and Specker,<ref>S Kochen and E P Specker, ''The problem of hidden variables in quantum mechanics'', Journal of Mathematics and Mechanics '''17''' (1967), 59–87.</ref> the inequalities of John Bell,<ref>John Bell, ''On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox'', Physics '''1''' (1964), 195–200.</ref> and experimental evidence of [[Alain Aspect]],<ref>Alain Aspect, Jean Dalibard, and Gérard Roger, ''Experimental test of Bell’s inequalities using time-varying analyzers'', ''Physical Revue Letters'' '''49''' (1982), no. 25, 1804–1807.</ref><ref>Alain Aspect, Philippe Grangier, and Gérard Roger, ''Experimental realization of Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen–Bohm gedankenexperiment: A new violation of Bell’s inequalities'', Physical Review Letters '''49''' (1982), no. 2, 91–94.</ref> all indicate that quantum randomness does not stem from any such ''physical information''. In 2008, Tomasz Paterek et al. provided an explanation in ''mathematical information''. They proved that quantum randomness is, exclusively, the output of measurement experiments whose input settings introduce ''[[Independence (mathematical logic)|logical independence]]'' into quantum systems.<ref>Tomasz Paterek, Johannes Kofler, Robert Prevedel, Peter Klimek, Markus Aspelmeyer, Anton Zeilinger, and Caslav Brukner, "Logical independence and quantum randomness", ''New Journal of Physics'' '''12''' (2010), no. 013019, 1367–2630.</ref><ref>Tomasz Paterek, Johannes Kofler, Robert Prevedel, Peter Klimek, Markus Aspelmeyer, Anton Zeilinger, and Caslav Brukner, "Logical independence and quantum randomness – with experimental data", https://arxiv.org/pdf/0811.4542.pdf (2010).</ref> Logical independence is a well-known phenomenon in [[Mathematical logic|Mathematical Logic]]. It refers to the null logical connectivity that exists between mathematical propositions (in the same language) that neither prove nor disprove one another.<ref>Edward Russell Stabler, ''An introduction to mathematical thought'', Addison-Wesley Publishing Company Inc., Reading Massachusetts USA, 1948.</ref> In the work of Paterek et al., the researchers demonstrate a link connecting quantum randomness and ''logical independence'' in a formal system of Boolean propositions. In experiments measuring photon polarisation, Paterek et al. demonstrate statistics correlating predictable outcomes with logically dependent mathematical propositions, and random outcomes with propositions that are logically independent.<ref>Tomasz Paterek, Johannes Kofler, Robert Prevedel, Peter Klimek, Markus Aspelmeyer, Anton Zeilinger, and Caslav Brukner, "Logical independence and quantum randomness", ''New Journal of Physics'' '''12''' (2010), no. 013019, 1367–2630.</ref><ref>Tomasz Paterek, Johannes Kofler, Robert Prevedel, Peter Klimek, Markus Aspelmeyer, Anton Zeilinger, and Caslav Brukner, "Logical independence and quantum randomness – with experimental data", https://arxiv.org/pdf/0811.4542.pdf (2010).</ref> In 2020, Steve Faulkner reported on work following up on the findings of Tomasz Paterek et al.; showing what logical independence in the Paterek Boolean propositions means, in the domain of Matrix Mechanics proper. He showed how indeterminacy's ''indefiniteness'' arises in evolved density operators representing mixed states, where measurement processes encounter irreversible 'lost history' and ingression of ambiguity.<ref>Steve Faulkner, ''The Underlying Machinery of Quantum Indeterminacy'' (2020). [https://quantum-indeterminacy.science]</ref> == See also == {{Portal|Physics}} {{div col|colwidth=28em}} * [[Complementarity (physics)]] * [[Counterfactual definiteness]] * [[EPR paradox]] * [[Interpretations of quantum mechanics]]: [[Interpretations of quantum mechanics#Comparisons|Comparisons chart]] * [[Quantum contextuality]] * [[Quantum entanglement]] * [[Quantum measurement]] * [[Quantum mechanics]] * [[Uncertainty principle]] {{div col end}} == Notes == {{reflist}} == References == * A. Aspect, ''Bell's inequality test: more ideal than ever'', Nature '''398''' 189 (1999). [http://www-ece.rice.edu/~kono/ELEC565/Aspect_Nature.pdf] * G. Bergmann, ''The Logic of Quanta'', American Journal of Physics, 1947. Reprinted in Readings in the Philosophy of Science, Ed. H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck, Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1953. Discusses measurement, accuracy and determinism. * J.S. Bell, ''On the Einstein–Poldolsky–Rosen paradox'', Physics '''1''' 195 (1964). * A. Einstein, B. Podolsky, and N. Rosen, [http://www.drchinese.com/David/EPR.pdf ''Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered complete?''] Phys. Rev. '''47''' 777 (1935). [https://journals.aps.org/pr/abstract/10.1103/PhysRev.47.777] * G. Mackey, ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', W. A. Benjamin, 1963 (paperback reprint by Dover 2004). * J. von Neumann, ''Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', Princeton University Press, 1955. Reprinted in paperback form. Originally published in German in 1932. * R. Omnès, ''Understanding Quantum Mechanics'', Princeton University Press, 1999. == External links == * [http://www.oberlin.edu/physics/dstyer/TeachQM/misconnzz.pdf Common Misconceptions Regarding Quantum Mechanics] See especially part III "Misconceptions regarding measurement". {{DEFAULTSORT:Quantum Indeterminacy}} [[Category:Quantum mechanics]] [[Category:Determinism]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Div col
(
edit
)
Template:Div col end
(
edit
)
Template:More citations needed
(
edit
)
Template:Nowrap
(
edit
)
Template:Ordered list
(
edit
)
Template:Physconst
(
edit
)
Template:Portal
(
edit
)
Template:Quantum mechanics
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Use American English
(
edit
)