Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Real analysis
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{distinguish|Reanalysis}} {{short description|Mathematics of real numbers and real functions}} {{More citations needed|date=October 2024}} {{Math topics TOC}} In [[mathematics]], the branch of '''real analysis''' studies the behavior of [[real number]]s, [[sequence]]s and [[Series (mathematics)|series]] of real numbers, and [[real function]]s.<ref>{{Cite web|url=https://www.math.ucla.edu/~tao/resource/general/131ah.1.03w/week1.pdf|title=Lecture notes for MATH 131AH|last=Tao|first=Terence|date=2003|website=Course Website for MATH 131AH, Department of Mathematics, UCLA}}</ref> Some particular properties of real-valued sequences and functions that real analysis studies include [[Convergent series|convergence]], [[limit (mathematics)|limits]], [[continuous function|continuity]], [[smoothness]], [[derivative|differentiability]] and [[integral|integrability]]. Real analysis is distinguished from [[complex analysis]], which deals with the study of [[complex number]]s and their functions. ==Scope== {{cleanup|section|reason=This section goes too heavily into detail about each concept. It should just portray a brief overview in relation to the field of real analysis|date=June 2019}} ===Construction of the real numbers=== {{Main|Construction of the real numbers}} The theorems of real analysis rely on the properties of the (established) [[real number]] system. The real number system consists of an [[uncountable set]] (<math>\mathbb{R}</math>), together with two [[binary operation]]s denoted {{math|+}} and {{math|-}}, and a [[total order]] denoted {{math|≤}}. The operations make the real numbers a [[Field (mathematics)|field]], and, along with the order, an [[ordered field]]. The real number system is the unique ''[[Completeness (order theory)|complete]] ordered field'', in the sense that any other complete ordered field is [[Isomorphism|isomorphic]] to it. Intuitively, completeness means that there are no 'gaps' (or 'holes') in the real numbers. This property distinguishes the real numbers from other ordered fields (e.g., the rational numbers <math>\mathbb{Q}</math>) and is critical to the proof of several key properties of functions of the real numbers. The completeness of the reals is often conveniently expressed as the ''least upper bound property'' (see below). ===Order properties of the real numbers=== The real numbers have various [[lattice theory|lattice-theoretic]] properties that are absent in the complex numbers. Also, the real numbers form an [[ordered field]], in which sums and products of positive numbers are also positive. Moreover, the ordering of the real numbers is [[totally ordered|total]], and the real numbers have the [[least upper bound property]]: <blockquote>''Every nonempty subset of <math>\mathbb{R}</math> that has an upper bound has a [[Supremum|least upper bound]] that is also a real number.'' </blockquote>These [[partially ordered set|order-theoretic]] properties lead to a number of fundamental results in real analysis, such as the [[monotone convergence theorem]], the [[intermediate value theorem]] and the [[mean value theorem]]. However, while the results in real analysis are stated for real numbers, many of these results can be generalized to other mathematical objects. In particular, many ideas in [[functional analysis]] and [[operator theory]] generalize properties of the real numbers – such generalizations include the theories of [[Riesz space]]s and [[positive operator]]s. Also, mathematicians consider [[real part|real]] and [[imaginary part]]s of complex sequences, or by [[strong operator topology|pointwise evaluation]] of [[operator (mathematics)|operator]] sequences.{{Clarify|date=June 2021}} === Topological properties of the real numbers === Many of the theorems of real analysis are consequences of the topological properties of the real number line. The order properties of the real numbers described above are closely related to these topological properties. As a [[topological space]], the real numbers has a ''standard topology'', which is the [[order topology]] induced by order <math><</math>. Alternatively, by defining the ''metric'' or ''distance function'' <math>d:\mathbb{R}\times\mathbb{R}\to\mathbb{R}_{\geq 0}</math> using the [[absolute value]] function as {{nowrap|<math>d(x, y) = |x - y|</math>,}} the real numbers become the prototypical example of a [[metric space]]. The topology induced by metric <math>d</math> turns out to be identical to the standard topology induced by order <math><</math>. Theorems like the [[intermediate value theorem]] that are essentially topological in nature can often be proved in the more general setting of metric or topological spaces rather than in <math>\mathbb{R}</math> only. Often, such proofs tend to be shorter or simpler compared to classical proofs that apply direct methods. ===Sequences=== {{Main|Sequence}} A '''''sequence''''' is a [[function (mathematics)|function]] whose [[domain of a function|domain]] is a [[countable]], [[totally ordered]] set.<ref name="Sequences intro">{{cite web |title=Sequences intro |url=https://www.khanacademy.org/math/algebra/x2f8bb11595b61c86:sequences/x2f8bb11595b61c86:introduction-to-arithmetic-sequences/v/explicit-and-recursive-definitions-of-sequences |website=khanacademy.org}}</ref> The domain is usually taken to be the [[natural number]]s,<ref name="Gaughan">{{cite book|title=Introduction to Analysis |last=Gaughan |first=Edward |publisher=AMS (2009)|isbn=978-0-8218-4787-9|chapter=1.1 Sequences and Convergence|year=2009 }}</ref> although it is occasionally convenient to also consider bidirectional sequences indexed by the set of all integers, including negative indices. Of interest in real analysis, a '''''real-valued sequence''''', here indexed by the natural numbers, is a map <math>a : \N \to \R : n \mapsto a_n</math>. Each <math>a(n) = a_n</math> is referred to as a '''''term''''' (or, less commonly, an '''''element''''') of the sequence. A sequence is rarely denoted explicitly as a function; instead, by convention, it is almost always notated as if it were an ordered ∞-tuple, with individual terms or a general term enclosed in parentheses:<ref>Some authors (e.g., Rudin 1976) use braces instead and write <math>\{a_n\}</math>. However, this notation conflicts with the usual notation for a [[Set theory|set]], which, in contrast to a sequence, disregards the order and the multiplicity of its elements.</ref> <math display="block">(a_n) = (a_n)_{n \in \N}=(a_1, a_2, a_3, \dots) .</math> A sequence that tends to a [[Limit (mathematics)|limit]] (i.e., <math display="inline">\lim_{n \to \infty} a_n</math> exists) is said to be '''convergent'''; otherwise it is '''divergent'''. (''See the section on limits and convergence for details.'') A real-valued sequence <math>(a_n)</math> is '''''bounded''''' if there exists <math>M\in\R</math> such that <math>|a_n|<M</math> for all <math>n\in\mathbb{N}</math>. A real-valued sequence <math>(a_n)</math> is '''''monotonically increasing''''' or '''''decreasing''''' if <math display="block">a_1 \leq a_2 \leq a_3 \leq \cdots</math> or <math display="block">a_1 \geq a_2 \geq a_3 \geq \cdots</math> holds, respectively. If either holds, the sequence is said to be '''''monotonic'''''. The monotonicity is '''''strict''''' if the chained inequalities still hold with <math>\leq</math> or <math>\geq</math> replaced by < or >. Given a sequence <math>(a_n)</math>, another sequence <math>(b_k)</math> is a '''''subsequence''''' of <math>(a_n)</math> if <math>b_k=a_{n_k}</math> for all positive integers <math>k</math> and <math>(n_k)</math> is a strictly increasing sequence of natural numbers. ===Limits and convergence=== {{Main|Limit (mathematics)}} Roughly speaking, a '''limit''' is the value that a [[function (mathematics)|function]] or a [[sequence]] "approaches" as the input or index approaches some value.<ref>{{cite book|last=Stewart|first=James|author-link=James Stewart (mathematician)|title=Calculus: Early Transcendentals|publisher=[[Brooks/Cole]]|edition=6th|year=2008|isbn=978-0-495-01166-8|url=https://archive.org/details/calculusearlytra00stew_1}}</ref> (This value can include the symbols <math>\pm\infty</math> when addressing the behavior of a function or sequence as the variable increases or decreases without bound.) The idea of a limit is fundamental to [[calculus]] (and [[mathematical analysis]] in general) and its formal definition is used in turn to define notions like [[continuous function|continuity]], [[derivative]]s, and [[integral]]s. (In fact, the study of limiting behavior has been used as a characteristic that distinguishes calculus and mathematical analysis from other branches of mathematics.) The concept of limit was informally introduced for functions by [[Isaac Newton|Newton]] and [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|Leibniz]], at the end of the 17th century, for building [[infinitesimal calculus]]. For sequences, the concept was introduced by [[Augustin-Louis Cauchy|Cauchy]], and made rigorous, at the end of the 19th century by [[Bernard Bolzano|Bolzano]] and [[Karl Weierstrass|Weierstrass]], who gave the modern [[ε-δ definition]], which follows. '''Definition.''' Let <math>f</math> be a real-valued function defined on {{nowrap|<math>E\subset\mathbb{R}</math>.}} We say that '''''<math>f(x)</math> tends to <math>L</math> as <math>x</math> approaches <math>x_0</math>''''', or that '''''the limit of <math>f(x)</math> as <math>x</math> approaches <math>x_0</math> is <math>L</math>''''' if, for any <math>\varepsilon>0</math>, there exists <math>\delta>0</math> such that for all <math>x\in E</math>, <math>0 < |x - x_0| < \delta</math> implies that <math>|f(x) - L| < \varepsilon</math>. We write this symbolically as <math display="block">f(x)\to L\ \ \text{as}\ \ x\to x_0 ,</math> or as <math display="block">\lim_{x\to x_0} f(x) = L .</math> Intuitively, this definition can be thought of in the following way: We say that <math>f(x)\to L</math> as <math>x\to x_0</math>, when, given any positive number <math>\varepsilon</math>, no matter how small, we can always find a <math>\delta</math>, such that we can guarantee that <math>f(x)</math> and <math>L</math> are less than <math>\varepsilon</math> apart, as long as <math>x</math> (in the domain of <math>f</math>) is a real number that is less than <math>\delta</math> away from <math>x_0</math> but distinct from <math>x_0</math>. The purpose of the last stipulation, which corresponds to the condition <math>0<|x-x_0|</math> in the definition, is to ensure that <math display="inline">\lim_{x \to x_0} f(x)=L</math> does not imply anything about the value of <math>f(x_0)</math> itself. Actually, <math>x_0</math> does not even need to be in the domain of <math>f</math> in order for <math display="inline">\lim_{x \to x_0} f(x)</math> to exist. In a slightly different but related context, the concept of a limit applies to the behavior of a sequence <math>(a_n)</math> when <math>n</math> becomes large. '''Definition.''' Let <math>(a_n)</math> be a real-valued sequence. We say that <math>(a_n)</math> '''''converges to''''' <math>a</math> if, for any <math>\varepsilon > 0</math>, there exists a natural number <math>N</math> such that <math>n\geq N</math> implies that <math>|a-a_n| < \varepsilon</math>. We write this symbolically as <math display="block">a_n \to a\ \ \text{as}\ \ n \to \infty ,</math>or as<math display="block">\lim_{n \to \infty} a_n = a ;</math> if <math>(a_n)</math> fails to converge, we say that <math>(a_n)</math> '''''diverges'''''. Generalizing to a real-valued function of a real variable, a slight modification of this definition (replacement of sequence <math>(a_n)</math> and term <math>a_n</math> by function <math>f</math> and value <math>f(x)</math> and natural numbers <math>N</math> and <math>n</math> by real numbers <math>M</math> and <math>x</math>, respectively) yields the definition of the '''''limit of <math>f(x)</math> as <math>x</math> increases without bound''''', notated <math display="inline">\lim_{x \to \infty} f(x)</math>. Reversing the inequality <math>x\geq M</math> to <math>x \leq M</math> gives the corresponding definition of the limit of <math>f(x)</math> as <math>x</math> ''decreases'' ''without bound'', {{nowrap|<math display="inline">\lim_{x \to -\infty} f(x)</math>.}} Sometimes, it is useful to conclude that a sequence converges, even though the value to which it converges is unknown or irrelevant. In these cases, the concept of a [[Cauchy sequence]] is useful. '''Definition.''' Let <math>(a_n)</math> be a real-valued sequence. We say that <math>(a_n)</math> is a '''''Cauchy sequence''''' if, for any <math>\varepsilon > 0</math>, there exists a natural number <math>N</math> such that <math>m,n\geq N</math> implies that <math>|a_m-a_n| < \varepsilon</math>. It can be shown that a real-valued sequence is Cauchy [[if and only if]] it is convergent. This property of the real numbers is expressed by saying that the real numbers endowed with the standard metric, <math>(\R, |\cdot|)</math>, is a '''''[[complete metric space]]'''''. In a general metric space, however, a Cauchy sequence need not converge. In addition, for real-valued sequences that are monotonic, it can be shown that the sequence is bounded if and only if it is convergent. ==== Uniform and pointwise convergence for sequences of functions ==== {{Main|Uniform convergence}} In addition to sequences of numbers, one may also speak of ''sequences of functions'' ''on'' <math>E\subset \mathbb{R}</math>, that is, infinite, ordered families of functions <math>f_n:E\to\mathbb{R}</math>, denoted <math>(f_n)_{n=1}^\infty</math>, and their convergence properties. However, in the case of sequences of functions, there are two kinds of convergence, known as ''pointwise convergence'' and ''uniform convergence'', that need to be distinguished. Roughly speaking, pointwise convergence of functions <math>f_n</math> to a limiting function <math>f:E\to\mathbb{R}</math>, denoted <math>f_n \rightarrow f</math>, simply means that given any <math>x\in E</math>, <math>f_n(x)\to f(x)</math> as <math>n\to\infty</math>. In contrast, uniform convergence is a stronger type of convergence, in the sense that a uniformly convergent sequence of functions also converges pointwise, but not conversely. [[Uniform convergence]] requires members of the family of functions, <math>f_n</math>, to fall within some error <math>\varepsilon > 0</math> of <math>f</math> for ''every value of <math>x\in E</math>'', whenever <math>n\geq N</math>, for some integer <math>N</math>. For a family of functions to uniformly converge, sometimes denoted <math>f_n\rightrightarrows f</math>, such a value of <math>N</math> must exist for any <math>\varepsilon>0</math> given, no matter how small. Intuitively, we can visualize this situation by imagining that, for a large enough <math>N</math>, the functions <math>f_N, f_{N+1}, f_{N+2},\ldots</math> are all confined within a 'tube' of width <math>2\varepsilon</math> about <math>f</math> (that is, between <math>f - \varepsilon</math> and <math>f+\varepsilon</math>) ''for every value in their domain'' <math>E</math>. The distinction between pointwise and uniform convergence is important when exchanging the order of two limiting operations (e.g., taking a limit, a derivative, or integral) is desired: in order for the exchange to be well-behaved, many theorems of real analysis call for uniform convergence. For example, a sequence of continuous functions (see [[Real analysis#Continuity|below]]) is guaranteed to converge to a continuous limiting function if the convergence is uniform, while the limiting function may not be continuous if convergence is only pointwise. [[Karl Weierstrass]] is generally credited for clearly defining the concept of uniform convergence and fully investigating its implications. === Compactness === {{Main|Compactness}}Compactness is a concept from [[general topology]] that plays an important role in many of the theorems of real analysis. The property of compactness is a generalization of the notion of a set being ''closed'' and ''bounded''. (In the context of real analysis, these notions are equivalent: a set in Euclidean space is compact if and only if it is closed and bounded.) Briefly, a [[closed set]] contains all of its [[Boundary (topology)|boundary points]], while a set is [[Bounded set|bounded]] if there exists a real number such that the distance between any two points of the set is less than that number. In <math>\mathbb{R}</math>, sets that are closed and bounded, and therefore compact, include the empty set, any finite number of points, [[Interval (mathematics)|closed intervals]], and their finite unions. However, this list is not exhaustive; for instance, the set <math>\{1/n:n\in\mathbb{N}\}\cup \{0}\</math> is a compact set; the [[Cantor set|Cantor ternary set]] <math>\mathcal{C}\subset [0,1]</math> is another example of a compact set. On the other hand, the set <math>\{1/n:n\in\mathbb{N}\}</math> is not compact because it is bounded but not closed, as the boundary point 0 is not a member of the set. The set <math>[0,\infty)</math> is also not compact because it is closed but not bounded. For subsets of the real numbers, there are several equivalent definitions of compactness. '''Definition.''' A set <math>E\subset\mathbb{R}</math> is compact if it is closed and bounded. This definition also holds for Euclidean space of any finite dimension, <math>\mathbb{R}^n</math>, but it is not valid for metric spaces in general. The equivalence of the definition with the definition of compactness based on subcovers, given later in this section, is known as the [[Heine–Borel theorem|Heine-Borel theorem]]. A more general definition that applies to all metric spaces uses the notion of a subsequence (see above). '''Definition.''' A set <math>E</math> in a metric space is compact if every sequence in <math>E</math> has a convergent subsequence. This particular property is known as ''subsequential compactness''. In <math>\mathbb{R}</math>, a set is subsequentially compact if and only if it is closed and bounded, making this definition equivalent to the one given above. Subsequential compactness is equivalent to the definition of compactness based on subcovers for metric spaces, but not for topological spaces in general. The most general definition of compactness relies on the notion of ''open covers'' and ''subcovers'', which is applicable to topological spaces (and thus to metric spaces and <math>\mathbb{R}</math> as special cases). In brief, a collection of open sets <math>U_{\alpha}</math> is said to be an ''open cover'' of set <math>X</math> if the union of these sets is a superset of <math>X</math>. This open cover is said to have a ''finite subcover'' if a finite subcollection of the <math>U_{\alpha}</math> could be found that also covers <math>X</math>. '''Definition.''' A set <math>X</math> in a topological space is compact if every open cover of <math>X</math> has a finite subcover. Compact sets are well-behaved with respect to properties like convergence and continuity. For instance, any Cauchy sequence in a compact metric space is convergent. As another example, the image of a compact metric space under a continuous map is also compact. ===Continuity=== {{Main|Continuous function}} A [[function (mathematics)|function]] from the set of [[real number]]s to the real numbers can be represented by a [[graph of a function|graph]] in the [[Cartesian coordinate system|Cartesian plane]]; such a function is continuous if, roughly speaking, the graph is a single unbroken [[curve]] with no "holes" or "jumps". There are several ways to make this intuition mathematically rigorous. Several definitions of varying levels of generality can be given. In cases where two or more definitions are applicable, they are readily shown to be [[Equivalence relation|equivalent]] to one another, so the most convenient definition can be used to determine whether a given function is continuous or not. In the first definition given below, <math>f:I\to\R</math> is a function defined on a non-degenerate interval <math>I</math> of the set of real numbers as its domain. Some possibilities include <math>I=\R</math>, the whole set of real numbers, an [[open interval]] <math>I = (a, b) = \{x \in \R \mid a < x < b \}, </math> or a [[closed interval]] <math>I = [a, b] = \{x \in \R \mid a \leq x \leq b\}. </math> Here, <math>a</math> and <math>b</math> are distinct real numbers, and we exclude the case of <math>I</math> being empty or consisting of only one point, in particular. '''Definition.''' If <math>I\subset \mathbb{R}</math> is a non-degenerate interval, we say that <math>f:I \to \R</math> is '''''continuous at''''' <math>p\in I</math> if <math display="inline">\lim_{x \to p} f(x) = f(p)</math>. We say that <math>f</math> is a '''''continuous map''''' if <math>f</math> is continuous at every <math>p\in I</math>. In contrast to the requirements for <math>f</math> to have a limit at a point <math>p</math>, which do not constrain the behavior of <math>f</math> at <math>p</math> itself, the following two conditions, in addition to the existence of <math display="inline">\lim_{x\to p} f(x)</math>, must also hold in order for <math>f</math> to be continuous at <math>p</math>: '''(i)''' <math>f</math> must be defined at <math>p</math>, i.e., <math>p</math> is in the domain of <math>f</math>; ''and'' '''(ii)''' <math>f(x)\to f(p)</math> as <math>x\to p</math>. The definition above actually applies to any domain <math>E</math> that does not contain an [[isolated point]], or equivalently, <math>E</math> where every <math>p\in E</math> is a [[limit point]] of <math>E</math>. A more general definition applying to <math>f:X\to\mathbb{R}</math> with a general domain <math>X\subset \mathbb{R}</math> is the following: '''Definition.''' If <math>X</math> is an arbitrary subset of <math>\mathbb{R}</math>, we say that <math>f:X\to\mathbb{R}</math> is '''''continuous at''''' <math>p\in X</math> if, for any <math>\varepsilon>0</math>, there exists <math>\delta>0</math> such that for all <math>x\in X</math>, <math>|x-p|<\delta</math> implies that <math>|f(x)-f(p)| < \varepsilon</math>. We say that <math>f</math> is a '''''continuous map''''' if <math>f</math> is continuous at every <math>p\in X</math>. A consequence of this definition is that <math>f</math> is ''trivially continuous at any isolated point'' <math>p\in X</math>. This somewhat unintuitive treatment of isolated points is necessary to ensure that our definition of continuity for functions on the real line is consistent with the most general definition of continuity for maps between [[topological space]]s (which includes [[metric space]]s and <math>\mathbb{R}</math> in particular as special cases). This definition, which extends beyond the scope of our discussion of real analysis, is given below for completeness. '''Definition.''' If <math>X</math> and <math>Y</math> are topological spaces, we say that <math>f:X\to Y</math> is '''''continuous at''''' <math>p\in X</math> if <math>f^{-1} (V)</math> is a [[Neighborhood (topology)|neighborhood]] of <math>p</math> in <math>X</math> for every neighborhood <math>V</math> of <math>f(p)</math> in <math>Y</math>. We say that <math>f</math> is a '''''continuous map''''' if <math>f^{-1}(U)</math> is open in <math>X</math> for every <math>U</math> open in <math>Y</math>. (Here, <math>f^{-1}(S)</math> refers to the [[preimage]] of <math>S\subset Y</math> under <math>f</math>.) ====Uniform continuity==== {{Main|Uniform continuity}} '''Definition.''' If <math>X</math> is a subset of the [[real number]]s, we say a function <math>f:X\to\mathbb{R}</math> is '''''uniformly continuous''''' '''''on''''' <math>X</math> if, for any <math>\varepsilon > 0</math>, there exists a <math>\delta>0</math> such that for all <math>x,y\in X</math>, <math>|x-y|<\delta</math> implies that <math>|f(x)-f(y)| < \varepsilon</math>. Explicitly, when a function is uniformly continuous on <math>X</math>, the choice of <math>\delta</math> needed to fulfill the definition must work for ''all of'' <math>X</math> for a given <math>\varepsilon</math>. In contrast, when a function is continuous at every point <math>p\in X</math> (or said to be continuous on <math>X</math>), the choice of <math>\delta</math> may depend on both <math>\varepsilon</math> ''and'' <math>p</math>. In contrast to simple continuity, uniform continuity is a property of a function that only makes sense with a specified domain; to speak of uniform continuity at a single point <math>p</math> is meaningless. On a compact set, it is easily shown that all continuous functions are uniformly continuous. If <math>E</math> is a bounded noncompact subset of <math>\mathbb{R}</math>, then there exists <math>f:E\to\mathbb{R}</math> that is continuous but not uniformly continuous. As a simple example, consider <math>f:(0,1)\to\mathbb{R}</math> defined by <math>f(x)=1/x</math>. By choosing points close to 0, we can always make <math>|f(x)-f(y)| > \varepsilon</math> for any single choice of <math>\delta>0</math>, for a given <math>\varepsilon > 0</math>. ====Absolute continuity==== {{Main|Absolute continuity}} '''Definition.''' Let <math>I\subset\mathbb{R}</math> be an [[interval (mathematics)|interval]] on the [[real line]]. A function <math>f:I \to \mathbb{R}</math> is said to be '''''absolutely continuous''''' '''''on''''' <math>I</math> if for every positive number <math>\varepsilon</math>, there is a positive number <math>\delta</math> such that whenever a finite sequence of [[pairwise disjoint]] sub-intervals <math>(x_1, y_1), (x_2,y_2),\ldots, (x_n,y_n)</math> of <math>I</math> satisfies<ref>{{harvnb|Royden|1988|loc=Sect. 5.4, page 108}}; {{harvnb|Nielsen|1997|loc=Definition 15.6 on page 251}}; {{harvnb|Athreya|Lahiri|2006|loc=Definitions 4.4.1, 4.4.2 on pages 128,129}}. The interval ''I'' is assumed to be bounded and closed in the former two books but not the latter book.</ref> :<math>\sum_{k=1}^{n} (y_k - x_k) < \delta</math> then :<math>\sum_{k=1}^{n} | f(y_k) - f(x_k) | < \varepsilon.</math> Absolutely continuous functions are continuous: consider the case ''n'' = 1 in this definition. The collection of all absolutely continuous functions on ''I'' is denoted AC(''I''). Absolute continuity is a fundamental concept in the Lebesgue theory of integration, allowing the formulation of a generalized version of the fundamental theorem of calculus that applies to the Lebesgue integral. ===Differentiation=== {{Main|Derivative|Differential calculus|}} The notion of the ''derivative'' of a function or ''differentiability'' originates from the concept of approximating a function near a given point using the "best" linear approximation. This approximation, if it exists, is unique and is given by the line that is tangent to the function at the given point <math>a</math>, and the slope of the line is the derivative of the function at <math>a</math>. A function <math>f:\mathbb{R}\to\mathbb{R}</math> is '''''differentiable at <math>a</math>''''' if the [[limit of a function|limit]] :<math>f'(a)=\lim_{h\to 0}\frac{f(a+h)-f(a)}{h}</math> exists. This limit is known as the '''''derivative of <math>f</math> at <math>a</math>''''', and the function <math>f'</math>, possibly defined on only a subset of <math>\mathbb{R}</math>, is the '''''derivative''''' (or '''''derivative function''''') '''''of''''' '''''<math>f</math>'''''. If the derivative exists everywhere, the function is said to be '''''differentiable'''''. As a simple consequence of the definition, <math>f</math> is continuous at '''''<math>a</math>''''' if it is differentiable there. Differentiability is therefore a stronger regularity condition (condition describing the "smoothness" of a function) than continuity, and it is possible for a function to be continuous on the entire real line but not differentiable anywhere (see [[Weierstrass function|Weierstrass's nowhere differentiable continuous function]]). It is possible to discuss the existence of higher-order derivatives as well, by finding the derivative of a derivative function, and so on. One can classify functions by their '''''differentiability class'''''. The class <math>C^0</math> (sometimes <math>C^0([a,b])</math> to indicate the interval of applicability) consists of all continuous functions. The class <math>C^1</math> consists of all [[differentiable function]]s whose derivative is continuous; such functions are called '''''continuously differentiable'''''. Thus, a <math>C^1</math> function is exactly a function whose derivative exists and is of class <math>C^0</math>. In general, the classes ''<math>C^k</math>'' can be defined [[recursion|recursively]] by declaring <math>C^0</math> to be the set of all continuous functions and declaring ''<math>C^k</math>'' for any positive integer <math>k</math> to be the set of all differentiable functions whose derivative is in <math>C^{k-1}</math>. In particular, ''<math>C^k</math>'' is contained in <math>C^{k-1}</math> for every <math>k</math>, and there are examples to show that this containment is strict. Class <math>C^\infty</math> is the intersection of the sets ''<math>C^k</math>'' as ''<math>k</math>'' varies over the non-negative integers, and the members of this class are known as the '''''smooth functions'''''. Class <math>C^\omega</math> consists of all [[analytic function]]s, and is strictly contained in <math>C^\infty</math> (see [[bump function]] for a smooth function that is not analytic). ===Series=== {{Main|Series (mathematics)}} A series formalizes the imprecise notion of taking the sum of an endless sequence of numbers. The idea that taking the sum of an "infinite" number of terms can lead to a finite result was counterintuitive to the ancient Greeks and led to the formulation of a number of paradoxes by Zeno and other philosophers. The modern notion of assigning a value to a series avoids dealing with the ill-defined notion of adding an "infinite" number of terms. Instead, the finite sum of the first <math>n</math> terms of the sequence, known as a partial sum, is considered, and the concept of a limit is applied to the sequence of partial sums as <math>n</math> grows without bound. The series is assigned the value of this limit, if it exists. Given an (infinite) [[sequence]] <math>(a_n)</math>, we can define an associated '''''series''''' as the formal mathematical object {{nowrap|<math display="inline">a_1 + a_2 + a_3 + \cdots = \sum_{n=1}^{\infty} a_n</math>,}} sometimes simply written as <math display="inline">\sum a_n</math>. The '''''partial sums''''' of a series <math display="inline">\sum a_n</math> are the numbers <math display="inline">s_n=\sum_{j=1}^n a_j</math>. A series <math display="inline">\sum a_n</math> is said to be '''''convergent''''' if the sequence consisting of its partial sums, <math>(s_n)</math>, is convergent; otherwise it is '''''divergent'''''. The '''''sum''''' of a convergent series is defined as the number {{nowrap|<math display="inline">s = \lim_{n \to \infty} s_n</math>.}} The word "sum" is used here in a metaphorical sense as a shorthand for taking the limit of a sequence of partial sums and should not be interpreted as simply "adding" an infinite number of terms. For instance, in contrast to the behavior of finite sums, rearranging the terms of an infinite series may result in convergence to a different number (see the article on the ''[[Riemann rearrangement theorem]]'' for further discussion). An example of a convergent series is a [[geometric series]] which forms the basis of one of Zeno's famous [[Zeno's paradoxes|paradoxes]]: :<math>\sum_{n=1}^\infty \frac{1}{2^n} = \frac{1}{2} + \frac{1}{4} + \frac{1}{8} + \cdots = 1 .</math> In contrast, the [[Harmonic series (mathematics)|harmonic series]] has been known since the Middle Ages to be a divergent series: :<math>\sum_{n=1}^\infty \frac{1}{n} = 1 + \frac{1}{2} + \frac{1}{3} + \cdots = \infty .</math> (Here, "<math>=\infty</math>" is merely a notational convention to indicate that the partial sums of the series grow without bound.) A series <math display="inline">\sum a_n</math> is said to '''''[[Absolute convergence|converge absolutely]]''''' if <math display="inline">\sum |a_n|</math> is convergent. A convergent series <math display="inline">\sum a_n</math> for which <math display="inline">\sum |a_n|</math> diverges is said to '''''converge''''' '''''non-absolutely'''''.<ref>The term '''''unconditional convergence''''' refers to series whose sum does not depend on the order of the terms (i.e., any rearrangement gives the same sum). Convergence is termed '''''conditional''''' otherwise. For series in <math>\R^n</math>, it can be shown that absolute convergence and unconditional convergence are equivalent. Hence, the term "conditional convergence" is often used to mean non-absolute convergence. However, in the general setting of Banach spaces, the terms do not coincide, and there are unconditionally convergent series that do not converge absolutely.</ref> It is easily shown that absolute convergence of a series implies its convergence. On the other hand, an example of a series that converges non-absolutely is :<math>\sum_{n=1}^\infty \frac{(-1)^{n-1}}{n} = 1 - \frac{1}{2} + \frac{1}{3} - \frac{1}{4} + \cdots = \ln 2 .</math> ====Taylor series==== {{Main|Taylor series}} The Taylor series of a [[real-valued function|real]] or [[complex-valued function]] ''ƒ''(''x'') that is [[infinitely differentiable function|infinitely differentiable]] at a [[real number|real]] or [[complex number]] ''a'' is the [[power series]] <!-- As stated below, the Taylor series need not equal the function. So please don't write f(x)=... here. In other words, DO NOT CHANGE ANYTHING ABOUT THIS FORMULA-->:<math>f(a) + \frac{f'(a)}{1!} (x-a) + \frac{f''(a)}{2!} (x-a)^2 + \frac{f^{(3)}(a)}{3!} (x-a)^3 + \cdots. </math><!----> which can be written in the more compact [[Summation#Capital-sigma notation|sigma notation]] as :<math> \sum_{n=0} ^ {\infty} \frac {f^{(n)}(a)}{n!} \, (x-a)^{n}</math> where ''n''! denotes the [[factorial]] of ''n'' and ''ƒ''<sup> (''n'')</sup>(''a'') denotes the ''n''th [[derivative]] of ''ƒ'' evaluated at the point ''a''. The derivative of order zero ''ƒ'' is defined to be ''ƒ'' itself and {{nowrap|(''x'' − ''a'')<sup>0</sup>}} and 0! are both defined to be 1. In the case that {{nowrap|''a'' {{=}} 0}}, the series is also called a Maclaurin series. A Taylor series of ''f'' about point ''a'' may diverge, converge at only the point ''a'', converge for all ''x'' such that <math>|x-a|<R</math> (the largest such ''R'' for which convergence is guaranteed is called the ''radius of convergence''), or converge on the entire real line. Even a converging Taylor series may converge to a value different from the value of the function at that point. If the Taylor series at a point has a nonzero [[radius of convergence]], and sums to the function in the [[disc of convergence]], then the function is [[analytic function|analytic]]. The analytic functions have many fundamental properties. In particular, an analytic function of a real variable extends naturally to a function of a complex variable. It is in this way that the [[exponential function]], the [[logarithm]], the [[trigonometric functions]] and their [[inverse trigonometric functions|inverses]] are extended to functions of a complex variable. ====Fourier series==== {{Main|Fourier series}} [[Image:Fourier Series.svg|thumb|200px|The first four partial sums of the [[Fourier series]] for a [[Square wave (waveform)|square wave]]. Fourier series are an important tool in real analysis.]] Fourier series decomposes [[periodic function]]s or periodic signals into the sum of a (possibly infinite) set of simple oscillating functions, namely [[sine wave|sines and cosines]] (or [[complex exponential]]s). The study of Fourier series typically occurs and is handled within the branch [[mathematics]] > [[mathematical analysis]] > [[Fourier analysis]]. ===Integration=== Integration is a formalization of the problem of finding the area bound by a curve and the related problems of determining the length of a curve or volume enclosed by a surface. The basic strategy to solving problems of this type was known to the ancient Greeks and Chinese, and was known as the ''[[method of exhaustion]]''. Generally speaking, the desired area is bounded from above and below, respectively, by increasingly accurate circumscribing and inscribing polygonal approximations whose exact areas can be computed. By considering approximations consisting of a larger and larger ("infinite") number of smaller and smaller ("infinitesimal") pieces, the area bound by the curve can be deduced, as the upper and lower bounds defined by the approximations converge around a common value. The spirit of this basic strategy can easily be seen in the definition of the Riemann integral, in which the integral is said to exist if upper and lower Riemann (or Darboux) sums converge to a common value as thinner and thinner rectangular slices ("refinements") are considered. Though the machinery used to define it is much more elaborate compared to the Riemann integral, the Lebesgue integral was defined with similar basic ideas in mind. Compared to the Riemann integral, the more sophisticated Lebesgue integral allows area (or length, volume, etc.; termed a "measure" in general) to be defined and computed for much more complicated and irregular subsets of Euclidean space, although there still exist "non-measurable" subsets for which an area cannot be assigned. ====Riemann integration==== {{Main|Riemann integral}} The Riemann integral is defined in terms of [[Riemann sum]]s of functions with respect to tagged partitions of an interval. Let <math>[a,b]</math> be a [[Interval (mathematics)|closed interval]] of the real line; then a '''''tagged partition''''' <math>\cal{P}</math> of <math>[a,b]</math> is a finite sequence :<math> a = x_0 \le t_1 \le x_1 \le t_2 \le x_2 \le \cdots \le x_{n-1} \le t_n \le x_n = b . \,\!</math> This partitions the interval <math>[a,b]</math> into <math>n</math> sub-intervals <math>[x_{i-1},x_i]</math> indexed by <math>i=1,\ldots, n</math>, each of which is "tagged" with a distinguished point <math>t_i\in[x_{i-1},x_i]</math>. For a function <math>f</math> bounded on <math>[a,b]</math>, we define the '''''Riemann sum''''' of <math>f</math> with respect to tagged partition <math>\cal{P}</math> as :<math>\sum_{i=1}^{n} f(t_i) \Delta_i, </math> where <math>\Delta_i=x_i-x_{i-1}</math> is the width of sub-interval <math>i</math>. Thus, each term of the sum is the area of a rectangle with height equal to the function value at the distinguished point of the given sub-interval, and width the same as the sub-interval width. The '''''mesh''''' of such a tagged partition is the width of the largest sub-interval formed by the partition, <math display="inline">\|\Delta_i\| = \max_{i=1,\ldots, n}\Delta_i</math>. We say that the '''''Riemann integral''''' of <math>f</math> on <math>[a,b]</math> is <math>S</math> if for any <math>\varepsilon>0</math> there exists <math>\delta>0</math> such that, for any tagged partition <math>\cal{P}</math> with mesh <math>\| \Delta_i \| < \delta</math>, we have ::<math>\left| S - \sum_{i=1}^{n} f(t_i)\Delta_i \right| < \varepsilon.</math> This is sometimes denoted <math display="inline">\mathcal{R}\int_{a}^b f=S</math>. When the chosen tags give the maximum (respectively, minimum) value of each interval, the Riemann sum is known as the upper (respectively, lower) '''''Darboux sum'''''. A function is '''''Darboux integrable''''' if the upper and lower [[Darboux integral|Darboux sums]] can be made to be arbitrarily close to each other for a sufficiently small mesh. Although this definition gives the Darboux integral the appearance of being a special case of the Riemann integral, they are, in fact, equivalent, in the sense that a function is Darboux integrable if and only if it is Riemann integrable, and the values of the integrals are equal. In fact, calculus and real analysis textbooks often conflate the two, introducing the definition of the Darboux integral as that of the Riemann integral, due to the slightly easier to apply definition of the former. The [[fundamental theorem of calculus]] asserts that integration and differentiation are inverse operations in a certain sense. ====Lebesgue integration and measure==== {{Main|Lebesgue integral}} '''Lebesgue integration''' is a mathematical construction that extends the integral to a larger class of functions; it also extends the [[domain of a function|domains]] on which these functions can be defined. The concept of a [[Measure (mathematics)|'''''measure''''']], an abstraction of length, area, or volume, is central to Lebesgue integral [[probability theory]]. ===Distributions=== {{Main|Distribution (mathematics)}} '''Distributions''' (or '''[[generalized functions]]''') are objects that generalize [[function (mathematics)|function]]s. Distributions make it possible to [[derivative|differentiate]] functions whose derivatives do not exist in the classical sense. In particular, any [[locally integrable]] function has a distributional derivative. ===Relation to complex analysis=== Real analysis is an area of [[mathematical analysis|analysis]] that studies concepts such as sequences and their limits, continuity, [[derivative|differentiation]], [[integral|integration]] and sequences of functions. By definition, real analysis focuses on the [[real number]]s, often including positive and negative [[infinity (mathematics)|infinity]] to form the [[extended real line]]. Real analysis is closely related to [[complex analysis]], which studies broadly the same properties of [[complex number]]s. In complex analysis, it is natural to define [[derivative|differentiation]] via [[holomorphic functions]], which have a number of useful properties, such as repeated differentiability, expressibility as [[power series]], and satisfying the [[Cauchy integral formula]]. In real analysis, it is usually more natural to consider [[Differentiable function|differentiable]], [[smooth functions|smooth]], or [[harmonic functions]], which are more widely applicable, but may lack some more powerful properties of holomorphic functions. However, results such as the [[fundamental theorem of algebra]] are simpler when expressed in terms of complex numbers. Techniques from the [[theory of analytic functions]] of a complex variable are often used in real analysis – such as evaluation of real integrals by [[residue theorem|residue calculus]]. ==Important results== Important results include the [[Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem|Bolzano–Weierstrass]] and [[Heine–Borel theorem]]s, the [[intermediate value theorem]] and [[mean value theorem]], [[Taylor's theorem]], the [[fundamental theorem of calculus]], the [[Arzelà–Ascoli theorem|Arzelà-Ascoli theorem]], the [[Stone–Weierstrass theorem|Stone-Weierstrass theorem]], [[Fatou's lemma]], and the [[Monotone convergence theorem|monotone convergence]] and [[dominated convergence theorem]]s. == Generalizations and related areas of mathematics == Various ideas from real analysis can be generalized from the real line to broader or more abstract contexts. These generalizations link real analysis to other disciplines and subdisciplines. For instance, generalization of ideas like continuous functions and compactness from real analysis to [[metric space]]s and [[topological space]]s connects real analysis to the field of [[general topology]], while generalization of finite-dimensional Euclidean spaces to infinite-dimensional analogs led to the concepts of [[Banach space]]s and [[Hilbert space]]s and, more generally to [[functional analysis]]. [[Georg Cantor]]'s investigation of sets and sequence of real numbers, mappings between them, and the foundational issues of real analysis gave birth to [[naive set theory]]. The study of issues of [[Limit (mathematics)|convergence]] for sequences of functions eventually gave rise to [[Fourier analysis]] as a subdiscipline of mathematical analysis. Investigation of the consequences of generalizing differentiability from functions of a real variable to ones of a complex variable gave rise to the concept of [[holomorphic function]]s and the inception of [[complex analysis]] as another distinct subdiscipline of analysis. On the other hand, the generalization of integration from the Riemann sense to that of Lebesgue led to the formulation of the concept of abstract [[measure space]]s, a fundamental concept in [[measure theory]]. Finally, the generalization of integration from the real line to curves and surfaces in higher dimensional space brought about the study of [[vector calculus]], whose further generalization and formalization played an important role in the evolution of the concepts of [[differential form]]s and [[Differentiable manifold|smooth (differentiable) manifolds]] in [[differential geometry]] and other closely related areas of [[geometry]] and [[topology]]. ==See also== * [[List of real analysis topics]] * [[Time-scale calculus]] – a unification of real analysis with calculus of finite differences * [[Real multivariable function]] * [[Real coordinate space]] * [[Complex analysis]] ==References== {{reflist}} ==Sources== * {{citation | last1=Athreya | first1=Krishna B. | last2=Lahiri | first2=Soumendra N. | title = Measure theory and probability theory | publisher = Springer | year = 2006 | isbn=0-387-32903-X }} * {{citation | last=Nielsen | first=Ole A. | title = An introduction to integration and measure theory | publisher = Wiley-Interscience | year = 1997 | isbn=0-471-59518-7 }} * {{citation | last=Royden | first=H.L. | title = Real Analysis | publisher = Collier Macmillan | edition=third| year = 1988 | isbn=0-02-404151-3 }} ==Bibliography== *{{cite book |last=Abbott |first=Stephen |title=Understanding Analysis |series=Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics |isbn=0-387-95060-5 |year=2001 |location=New York |publisher=Springer-Verlag}} * {{cite book |title=Principles of real analysis |last2=Burkinshaw |first2=Owen |publisher=Academic |isbn=0-12-050257-7|year=1998|edition=3rd|last1=Aliprantis |first1=Charalambos D. |author-link1=Charalambos D. Aliprantis }} *{{cite book |title=Introduction to Real Analysis |last2=Sherbert |first2=Donald R. |publisher=John Wiley and Sons |isbn=978-0-471-43331-6|year=2011|edition=4th |location=New York|last1=Bartle |first1=Robert G. |author-link1=Robert G. Bartle }} *{{cite book |last=Bressoud |first=David |author-link=David Bressoud |title=A Radical Approach to Real Analysis |isbn=978-0-88385-747-2 |publisher=MAA |year=2007}} *{{cite book |last=Browder |first=Andrew |title=Mathematical Analysis: An Introduction |series=[[Undergraduate Texts in Mathematics]] |location=New York |publisher=Springer-Verlag |year=1996 |isbn=0-387-94614-4}} *{{Cite book|url=https://archive.org/details/CarothersN.L.RealAnalysisCambridge2000Isbn0521497566416S|title=Real Analysis|last=Carothers|first=Neal L.|publisher=Cambridge University Press|year=2000|isbn=978-0521497565|location=Cambridge}} *{{cite book |last1=Dangello |first1=Frank |last2=Seyfried |first2=Michael |title=Introductory Real Analysis |isbn=978-0-395-95933-6 |publisher=Brooks Cole |year=1999}} *{{cite book |last1=Kolmogorov |first1=A. N. |author-link1=Andrey Kolmogorov |last2=Fomin |first2=S. V. |author-link2=Sergei Fomin |others=Translated by Richard A. Silverman |title=Introductory Real Analysis |year=1975 |publisher=Dover Publications |url=https://archive.org/details/introductoryreal00kolm_0 |access-date=2 April 2013 |isbn=0486612260 }} *{{cite book|url=https://archive.org/details/PrinciplesOfMathematicalAnalysis|title=Principles of Mathematical Analysis|last=Rudin|first=Walter|publisher=McGraw–Hill|isbn=978-0-07-054235-8|year=1976|edition=3rd|series=Walter Rudin Student Series in Advanced Mathematics|location=New York|author-link=Walter Rudin}} *{{Cite book|url=https://archive.org/details/RudinW.RealAndComplexAnalysis3e1987|title=Real and Complex Analysis|last=Rudin|first=Walter|publisher=McGraw-Hill|isbn=978-0-07-054234-1|year=1987|edition=3rd|location=New York}} * {{Cite book|title=Calculus|publisher=Publish or Perish, Inc.|isbn=091409890X|year=1994|edition= 3rd|location=[[Houston]], Texas|last1=Spivak|first1=Michael|author-link1=Michael Spivak}} ==External links== * [https://textbooks.opensuny.org/how-we-got-from-there-to-here-a-story-of-real-analysis/ How We Got From There to Here: A Story of Real Analysis] by Robert Rogers and Eugene Boman * [http://www.worldscientific.com/worldscibooks/10.1142/8580 A First Course in Analysis] by Donald Yau * [http://www.analysiswebnotes.com Analysis WebNotes] by John Lindsay Orr * [http://www.mathcs.org/analysis/reals/index.html Interactive Real Analysis] by Bert G. Wachsmuth * [http://www-groups.mcs.st-andrews.ac.uk/~john/analysis/index.html A First Analysis Course] by John O'Connor * [http://www.trillia.com/zakon-analysisI.html Mathematical Analysis I] by Elias Zakon * [http://www.trillia.com/zakon-analysisII.html Mathematical Analysis II] by Elias Zakon * {{Cite book | last1=Trench | first1=William F. | title=Introduction to Real Analysis | url=http://ramanujan.math.trinity.edu/wtrench/texts/TRENCH_REAL_ANALYSIS.PDF | publisher=[[Prentice Hall]] | isbn=978-0-13-045786-8 | year=2003 }} * [http://www.economics.soton.ac.uk/staff/aldrich/Calculus%20and%20Analysis%20Earliest%20Uses.htm Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics: Calculus & Analysis] * [http://www.jirka.org/ra/ Basic Analysis: Introduction to Real Analysis] by Jiri Lebl * [https://www.mat.univie.ac.at/~gerald/ftp/book-ra/index.html Topics in Real Analysis] by [[Gerald Teschl]], University of Vienna. {{Analysis-footer}} [[Category:Real analysis| ]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Analysis-footer
(
edit
)
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Clarify
(
edit
)
Template:Cleanup
(
edit
)
Template:Distinguish
(
edit
)
Template:Harvnb
(
edit
)
Template:Main
(
edit
)
Template:Math
(
edit
)
Template:Math topics TOC
(
edit
)
Template:More citations needed
(
edit
)
Template:Nowrap
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)