Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Reliabilism
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Theory that beliefs are justified when from reliable processes}} '''Reliabilism''', a category of theories in the [[philosophy|philosophical]] discipline of [[epistemology]], has been advanced as a theory both of [[Theory of justification|justification]] and of [[knowledge]]. Process reliabilism has been used as an argument against [[philosophical skepticism]], such as the [[brain in a vat]] thought experiment.<ref name="kd47">{{cite web|url=http://pantheon.yale.edu/~kd47/responding.htm|title=Responding to Skepticism|last=DeRose|first=Keith|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20001114223600/http://pantheon.yale.edu/~kd47/responding.htm|archive-date=14 November 2000|year=1999}}</ref> Process reliabilism is a form of [[Internalism and externalism#Epistemology|epistemic externalism]].<ref name="kd47"/> ==Overview== A broadly reliabilist theory of knowledge is roughly as follows: <blockquote>Given that ''p'' stands for any [[proposition]] (such as, ''the sky is blue''), then one knows that ''p'' if and only if ''p'' is true, one believes that ''p'' is true, and one has arrived at the belief that ''p'' is true through some ''reliable process.''</blockquote> A broadly reliabilist theory of justified belief can be stated as follows: <blockquote>One has a justified belief that ''p'' if, and only if, the belief is the result of a reliable process.</blockquote> Moreover, a similar account can be given (and an elaborate version of this [[Warrant and Proper Function|has been given]] by [[Alvin Plantinga]]) for such notions as 'warranted belief' or 'epistemically rational belief'. Leading proponents of reliabilist theories of knowledge and justification have included [[Alvin Goldman]], [[Marshall Swain]], [[Kent Bach]] and more recently, Alvin Plantinga. Goldman's article "[[A Causal Theory of Knowing]]" (''Journal of Philosophy'', '''64''' (1967), pp. 357β372) is generally credited as being the first full treatment of the theory, though [[D. M. Armstrong]] is also regarded as an important source, and (according to [[Hugh Mellor]]) [[Frank P. Ramsey|Frank Ramsey]] was the very first to state the theory, albeit in passing. One classical or traditional [[philosophical analysis|analysis]] of 'knowledge' is ''[[justified true belief]]''. In order to have a valid claim of knowledge for any proposition, one must be justified in believing "p" and "p" must be true. Since [[Gettier]]<ref>{{cite journal|url=https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-01439314/file/2013%20Gettier%20Conocimiento.pdf|title=Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?|year=1963|first=Edmund L.|last=Gettier|journal=Analysis|volume=23|issue=6|pages=121β123|doi=10.1093/analys/23.6.121|jstor=3326922}}</ref> proposed his counterexamples the traditional analysis has included the further claim that knowledge must be more than justified true belief. Reliabilist theories of knowledge are sometimes presented as an alternative to that theory: rather than justification, all that is required is that the belief be the product of a reliable process. But reliabilism need not be regarded as an alternative, but instead as a further explication of the traditional analysis. On this view, those who offer reliabilist theories of justification further analyze the 'justification' part of the traditional analysis of 'knowledge' in terms of reliable processes. Not all reliabilists agree with such accounts of justification, but some do. ==Objections== {{Refimprove section|date=April 2011}} Some find reliabilisms of justification objectionable because it entails [[externalism (epistemology)|externalism]], which is the view that one can have knowledge, or have a justified belief, despite not knowing (having "access" to) the evidence, or other circumstances, that make the belief justified. Most reliabilists maintain that a belief can be justified, or can constitute knowledge, ''even if'' the believer does not know about or understand the process that makes the belief reliable. In defending this view, reliabilists (and externalists generally) are apt to point to examples from simple acts of perception: if one sees a bird in the tree outside one's window and thereby gains the belief that there is a bird in that tree, one might not at all understand the cognitive processes that account for one's successful act of perception; nevertheless, it is the fact that the processes worked reliably that accounts for why one's belief is justified. In short, one finds one holds a belief about the bird, and that belief is justified if any is, but one is not acquainted at all with the processes that led to the belief that justified one's having it. Another of the most common objections to reliabilism, made first to Goldman's reliable process theory of knowledge and later to other reliabilist theories, is the so-called generality problem.<ref>{{Cite journal | last1 = Conee | first1 = E. | last2 = Feldman | first2 = R. | title = The Generality Problem for Reliabilism | journal = Philosophical Studies | volume = 89 | issue = 1 | pages = 1β29 | doi = 10.1023/A:1004243308503| year = 1998 | jstor = 4320806| s2cid = 170425156 }}</ref> For any given justified belief (or instance of knowledge), one can easily identify many different (concurrently operating) "processes" from which the belief results. My belief that there is a bird in the tree outside my window might be accorded a result of the process of forming beliefs on the basis of sense-perception, of visual sense-perception, of visual sense-perception through non-opaque surfaces in daylight, and so forth, down to a variety of different very specifically described processes. Some of these processes might be statistically reliable, while others might not. It would no doubt be better to say, in any case, that we are choosing not which process to say resulted in the belief, but instead how to describe the process, out of the many different levels of generality on which it can be accurately described. An objection in a similar line was formulated by [[Stephen Stich]] in ''The Fragmentation of Reason''. Reliabilism usually considers that for generating justified beliefs a process needs to be reliable in a set of relevant possible scenarios. However, according to Stich, these scenarios are chosen in a culturally biased manner. Stich does not defend any alternative theory of knowledge or justification, but instead argues that all accounts of normative epistemic terms are culturally biased and instead only a pragmatic account can be given. Another objection to reliabilism is called the ''new evil demon problem''.<ref>{{cite journal |title=The Diagonal and the Demon |first=Juan |last=ComesaΓ±a |journal=Philosophical Studies |volume=110 |issue=3 |year=2002 |pages=249β266 |doi=10.1023/a:1020656411534 |s2cid=169069884 |url=http://philosophy.wisc.edu/comesana/diagonal.pdf |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20100614021049/http://philosophy.wisc.edu/comesana/diagonal.pdf |archive-date=2010-06-14 }}</ref> The evil demon problem originally motivated [[skepticism]], but can be repurposed to object to reliabilist accounts as follows: If our experiences are controlled by an evil demon, it may be the case that we believe ourselves to be doing things that we are not doing. However, these beliefs are clearly justified. [[Robert Brandom]] has called for a clarification of the role of [[belief]] in reliabilist theories. Brandom is concerned that unless the role of belief is stressed, reliabilism may attribute knowledge to things that would otherwise be considered incapable of possessing it. Brandom gives the example of a parrot that has been trained to consistently respond to red visual stimuli by saying 'that's red'. The proposition is true, the mechanism that produced it is reliable, but Brandom is reluctant to say that the parrot ''knows'' it is seeing red because he thinks it cannot ''believe'' that it is. For Brandom, beliefs pertain to concepts: without the latter there can be no former. Concepts are products of the 'game of giving and asking for reasons'. Hence, only those entities capable of reasoning, through language in a social context, can for Brandom believe and thus have knowledge. Brandom may be regarded as hybridising [[externalism]] and [[internalism]], allowing knowledge to be accounted for by reliable external process so long as a knower possess some internal understanding of why the belief is reliable. ==References== {{Reflist}} == External links == *{{PhilPapers|category|reliabilism}} *{{cite SEP |url-id=reliabilism |title=Reliabilist Epistemology}} *{{cite IEP |url-id=reliabil |title=Reliabilism}} *{{InPho|idea|1146}} {{epistemology}} {{Philosophical skepticism}} [[Category:Internalism and externalism]] [[Category:Theories of justification]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Cite IEP
(
edit
)
Template:Cite SEP
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Epistemology
(
edit
)
Template:InPho
(
edit
)
Template:PhilPapers
(
edit
)
Template:Philosophical skepticism
(
edit
)
Template:Refimprove section
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)