Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Splitting lemma
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|About direct sums and exact sequences}} {{Distinguish|text=the [[splitting lemma (functions)|splitting lemma]] in [[singularity theory]]}} In [[mathematics]], and more specifically in [[homological algebra]], the '''splitting lemma''' states that in any [[abelian category]], the following statements are [[logical equivalence|equivalent]] for a [[short exact sequence]] : <math>0 \longrightarrow A \mathrel{\overset{q}{\longrightarrow}} B \mathrel{\overset{r}{\longrightarrow}} C \longrightarrow 0.</math> {{ordered list|{{glossary}}{{term|Left split}}{{defn|There exists a [[morphism]] {{math|''t'': ''B'' β ''A''}} such that {{math|''tq''}} is the [[identity function|identity]] {{math|id{{sub|''A''}}}} on {{math|''A''}},}}{{glossary end}}|{{glossary}}{{term|Right split}}{{defn|There exists a morphism {{math|''u'': ''C'' β ''B''}} such that {{math|''ru''}} is the identity {{math|id{{sub|''C''}}}} on {{math|''C''}},}}{{glossary end}}|{{glossary}}{{term|Direct sum}}{{defn|There is an [[isomorphism (category theory)|isomorphism]] {{mvar|h}} from {{math|''B''}} to the [[biproduct|direct sum]] of {{math|''A''}} and {{math|''C''}}, such that {{math|''hq''}} is the natural injection of {{math|''A''}} into the direct sum, and <math>rh^{-1}</math> is the natural projection of the direct sum [[surjective|onto]] {{math|''C''}}.}}{{glossary end}} }} If any of these statements holds, the sequence is called a '''[[split exact sequence]]''', and the sequence is said to ''split''. In the above short exact sequence, where the sequence splits, it allows one to refine the [[first isomorphism theorem]], which states that: : {{math|''C'' β ''B''/ker ''r'' β ''B''/''q''(''A'')}} (i.e., {{math|''C''}} isomorphic to the [[coimage]] of {{math|''r''}} or [[cokernel]] of {{math|''q''}}) to: : {{math|''B'' {{=}} ''q''(''A'') β ''u''(''C'') β ''A'' β ''C''}} where the first isomorphism theorem is then just the projection onto {{math|''C''}}. It is a [[category theory|categorical]] generalization of the [[rankβnullity theorem]] (in the form {{math|V β ker ''T'' β im ''T'')}} in [[linear algebra]]. ==Proof for the category of abelian groups== === {{math|3. β 1.}} and {{math|3. β 2.}} === First, to show that 3. implies both 1. and 2., we assume 3. and take as {{math|''t''}} the natural projection of the direct sum onto {{math|''A''}}, and take as {{math|''u''}} the natural injection of {{math|''C''}} into the direct sum. === {{math|1. β 3.}} === To [[mathematical proof|prove]] that 1. implies 3., first note that any member of ''B'' is in the set ({{math|[[kernel (algebra)|ker]] ''t'' + [[image (function)|im]] ''q''}}). This follows since for all {{math|''b''}} in {{math|''B''}}, {{math|''b'' {{=}} (''b'' β ''qt''(''b'')) + ''qt''(''b'')}}; {{math|''qt''(''b'')}} is in {{math|im ''q''}}, and {{math|''b'' β ''qt''(''b'')}} is in {{math|ker ''t''}}, since :{{math|''t''(''b'' β ''qt''(''b'')) {{=}} ''t''(''b'') β ''tqt''(''b'') {{=}} ''t''(''b'') β (''tq'')''t''(''b'') {{=}} ''t''(''b'') β ''t''(''b'') {{=}} 0.}} Next, the [[intersection (set theory)|intersection]] of {{math|im ''q''}} and {{math|ker ''t''}} is 0, since if there exists {{math|''a''}} in {{math|''A''}} such that {{math|''q''(''a'') {{=}} ''b''}}, and {{math|''t''(''b'') {{=}} 0}}, then {{math|0 {{=}} ''tq''(''a'') {{=}} ''a''}}; and therefore, {{math|''b'' {{=}} 0}}. This proves that {{math|''B''}} is the direct sum of {{math|im ''q''}} and {{math|ker ''t''}}. So, for all {{math|''b''}} in {{math|''B''}}, {{math|''b''}} can be uniquely identified by some {{math|''a''}} in {{math|''A''}}, {{math|''k''}} in {{math|ker ''t''}}, such that {{math|''b'' {{=}} ''q''(''a'') + ''k''}}. By exactness {{math|ker ''r'' {{=}} im ''q''}}. The subsequence {{math|''B'' βΆ ''C'' βΆ 0}} implies that {{math|''r''}} is [[surjective|onto]]; therefore for any {{math|''c''}} in {{math|''C''}} there exists some {{math|''b'' {{=}} ''q''(''a'') + ''k''}} such that {{math|''c'' {{=}} ''r''(''b'') {{=}} ''r''(''q''(''a'') + ''k'') {{=}} ''r''(''k'')}}. Therefore, for any ''c'' in ''C'', exists ''k'' in ker ''t'' such that ''c'' = ''r''(''k''), and ''r''(ker ''t'') = ''C''. If {{math|''r''(''k'') {{=}} 0}}, then {{math|''k''}} is in {{math|im ''q''}}; since the intersection of {{math|im ''q''}} and {{math|ker ''t'' {{=}} 0}}, then {{math|''k'' {{=}} 0}}. Therefore, the [[restriction (mathematics)|restriction]] {{math|''r'': ker ''t'' β ''C''}} is an isomorphism; and {{math|ker ''t''}} is isomorphic to {{math|''C''}}. Finally, {{math|im ''q''}} is isomorphic to {{math|''A''}} due to the exactness of {{math|0 βΆ ''A'' βΆ ''B''}}; so ''B'' is isomorphic to the direct sum of {{math|''A''}} and {{math|''C''}}, which proves (3). === {{math|2. β 3.}} === To show that 2. implies 3., we follow a similar argument. Any member of {{math|''B''}} is in the set {{math|ker ''r'' + im ''u''}}; since for all {{math|''b''}} in {{math|''B''}}, {{math|''b'' {{=}} (''b'' β ''ur''(''b'')) + ''ur''(''b'')}}, which is in {{math|ker ''r'' + im ''u''}}. The intersection of {{math|ker ''r''}} and {{math|im ''u''}} is {{math|0}}, since if {{math|''r''(''b'') {{=}} 0}} and {{math|''u''(''c'') {{=}} ''b''}}, then {{math|0 {{=}} ''ru''(''c'') {{=}} ''c''}}. By exactness, {{math|im ''q'' {{=}} ker ''r''}}, and since {{math|''q''}} is an [[injective|injection]], {{math|im ''q''}} is isomorphic to {{math|''A''}}, so {{math|''A''}} is isomorphic to {{math|ker ''r''}}. Since {{math|''ru''}} is a [[bijection]], {{math|''u''}} is an injection, and thus {{math|im ''u''}} is isomorphic to {{math|''C''}}. So {{math|''B''}} is again the direct sum of {{math|''A''}} and {{math|''C''}}. An alternative "[[abstract nonsense]]" [https://math.stackexchange.com/q/753182 proof of the splitting lemma] may be formulated entirely in [[category theory|category theoretic]] terms. ==Non-abelian groups== In the form stated here, the splitting lemma does not hold in the full [[category of groups]], which is not an abelian category. ===Partially true=== It is partially true: if a short exact sequence of groups is left split or a direct sum (1. or 3.), then all of the conditions hold. For a direct sum this is clear, as one can inject from or project to the summands. For a left split sequence, the map {{math|''t'' Γ ''r'': ''B'' β ''A'' Γ ''C''}} gives an isomorphism, so {{math|''B''}} is a direct sum (3.), and thus inverting the isomorphism and composing with the natural injection {{math|''C'' β ''A'' Γ ''C''}} gives an injection {{math|''C'' β ''B''}} splitting {{math|''r''}} (2.). However, if a short exact sequence of groups is right split (2.), then it need not be left split or a direct sum (neither 1. nor 3. follows): the problem is that the image of the right splitting need not be [[normal subgroup|normal]]. What is true in this case is that {{math|''B''}} is a [[semidirect product]], though not in general a [[direct product of groups|direct product]]. ===Counterexample=== To form a counterexample, take the smallest [[non-abelian group]] {{math|''B'' β ''S''{{sub|3}}}}, the [[symmetric group]] on three letters. Let {{math|''A''}} denote the [[alternating group|alternating subgroup]], and let {{math|''C'' {{=}} ''B''/''A'' β {Β±1}}}. Let {{math|''q''}} and {{math|''r''}} denote the inclusion map and the [[parity of a permutation|sign]] map respectively, so that : <math>0 \longrightarrow A \mathrel{\stackrel{q}{\longrightarrow}} B \mathrel{\stackrel{r}{\longrightarrow}} C \longrightarrow 0 </math> is a short exact sequence. 3. fails, because {{math|''S''{{sub|3}}}} is not abelian, but 2. holds: we may define {{math|''u'': ''C'' β ''B''}} by mapping the generator to any [[cyclic permutation|two-cycle]]. Note for completeness that 1. fails: any map {{math|''t'': ''B'' β ''A''}} must map every two-cycle to the [[identity permutation|identity]] because the map has to be a [[group homomorphism]], while the [[order (group theory)|order]] of a two-cycle is 2 which can not be divided by the order of the elements in ''A'' other than the identity element, which is 3 as {{math|''A''}} is the alternating subgroup of {{math|''S''{{sub|3}}}}, or namely the [[cyclic group]] of [[order of a group|order]] 3. But every [[permutation]] is a product of two-cycles, so {{math|''t''}} is the trivial map, whence {{math|''tq'': ''A'' β ''A''}} is the trivial map, not the identity. ==References== * [[Saunders Mac Lane]]: ''Homology''. Reprint of the 1975 edition, Springer Classics in Mathematics, {{ISBN|3-540-58662-8}}, p. 16 * [[Allen Hatcher]]: ''Algebraic Topology''. 2002, Cambridge University Press, {{ISBN|0-521-79540-0}}, p. 147 {{DEFAULTSORT:Splitting Lemma}} [[Category:Homological algebra]] [[Category:Lemmas in category theory]] [[Category:Articles containing proofs]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Distinguish
(
edit
)
Template:ISBN
(
edit
)
Template:Math
(
edit
)
Template:Ordered list
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)