Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Subobject
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
In [[category theory]], a branch of [[mathematics]], a '''subobject''' is, roughly speaking, an [[Object (category theory)|object]] that sits inside another object in the same [[category (mathematics)|category]]. The notion is a generalization of concepts such as [[subset]]s from [[set theory]], [[subgroup]]s from [[group theory]],<ref name="Mac Lane">Mac Lane, p. 126</ref> and [[subspace (topology)|subspaces]] from [[topology]]. Since the detailed structure of objects is immaterial in category theory, the definition of subobject relies on a [[morphism]] that describes how one object sits inside another, rather than relying on the use of elements. The [[dual (category theory)|dual]] concept to a subobject is a '''{{visible anchor|quotient object}}'''. This generalizes concepts such as [[quotient set]]s, [[quotient group]]s, [[quotient space (topology)|quotient spaces]], [[quotient graph]]s, etc. ==Definitions== An appropriate categorical definition of "subobject" may vary with context, depending on the goal. One common definition is as follows. In detail, let ''<math>A</math>'' be an object of some category. Given two [[monomorphism]]s :<math>u: S \to A \ \text{and} \ v: T\to A</math> with [[codomain]] ''<math>A</math>'', we define an equivalence relation by <math>u \equiv v</math> if there exists an isomorphism <math>\phi: S \to T</math> with <math>u = v \circ \phi</math>. Equivalently, we write <math>u \leq v</math> if <math>u</math> [[Mathematical jargon#factor through|factors through]] ''<math>v</math>''βthat is, if there exists <math>\phi: S \to T</math> such that <math>u = v \circ \phi</math>. The binary relation <math>\equiv</math> defined by :<math>u \equiv v \iff u \leq v \ \text{and} \ v\leq u </math> is an [[equivalence relation]] on the monomorphisms with codomain ''<math>A</math>'', and the corresponding [[equivalence class]]es of these monomorphisms are the '''subobjects''' of ''<math>A</math>''. The relation β€ induces a [[partial order]] on the collection of subobjects of <math>A</math>. The collection of subobjects of an object may in fact be a [[proper class]]; this means that the discussion given is somewhat loose. If the subobject-collection of every object is a [[Set (mathematics)|set]], the category is called ''well-powered'' or, rarely, ''locally small'' (this clashes with a different usage of the term [[Locally small category|locally small]], namely that there is a set of morphisms between any two objects). To get the dual concept of '''quotient object''', replace "monomorphism" by "[[epimorphism]]" above and reverse arrows. A quotient object of ''A'' is then an equivalence class of epimorphisms with domain ''A.'' However, in some contexts these definitions are inadequate as they do not concord with well-established notions of subobject or quotient object. In the category of topological spaces, monomorphisms are precisely the injective continuous functions; but not all injective continuous functions are subspace embeddings. In the category of rings, the inclusion <math>\mathbb{Z} \hookrightarrow \mathbb{Q}</math> is an epimorphism but is not the quotient of <math>\mathbb{Z}</math> by a two-sided ideal. To get maps which truly behave like subobject embeddings or quotients, rather than as arbitrary injective functions or maps with dense image, one must restrict to monomorphisms and epimorphisms satisfying additional hypotheses. Therefore, one might define a "subobject" to be an equivalence class of so-called "regular monomorphisms" (monomorphisms which can be expressed as an equalizer of two morphisms) and a "quotient object" to be any equivalence class of "regular epimorphisms" (morphisms which can be expressed as a coequalizer of two morphisms) ==Interpretation== This definition corresponds to the ordinary understanding of a subobject outside category theory. When the category's objects are sets (possibly with additional structure, such as a group structure) and the morphisms are set functions (preserving the additional structure), one thinks of a monomorphism in terms of its image. An equivalence class of monomorphisms is determined by the image of each monomorphism in the class; that is, two monomorphisms ''f'' and ''g'' into an object ''T'' are equivalent if and only if their images are the same subset (thus, subobject) of ''T''. In that case there is the isomorphism <math>g^{-1} \circ f</math> of their domains under which corresponding elements of the domains map by ''f'' and ''g'', respectively, to the same element of ''T''; this explains the definition of equivalence. ==Examples== {{Category see also|Quotient objects}} In '''Set''', the [[category of sets]], a subobject of ''A'' corresponds to a [[subset]] ''B'' of ''A'', or rather the collection of all maps from sets [[equipotent]] to ''B'' with [[Image (mathematics)|image]] exactly ''B''. The subobject partial order of a set in '''Set''' is just its subset [[Lattice (order)|lattice]]. In '''Grp''', the [[category of groups]], the subobjects of ''A'' correspond to the [[subgroup]]s of ''A''. Given a [[partially ordered class]] '''P''' = (''P'', β€), we can form a category with the elements of ''P'' as objects, and a single arrow from ''p'' to ''q'' iff ''p'' β€ ''q''. If '''P''' has a greatest element, the subobject partial order of this greatest element will be '''P''' itself. This is in part because all arrows in such a category will be monomorphisms. A subobject of a [[terminal object]] is called a [[subterminal object]]. ==See also== *[[Subobject classifier]] *[[Subquotient]] ==Notes== {{reflist}} ==References== * {{citation | last=Mac Lane | first=Saunders | authorlink=Saunders Mac Lane | title=[[Categories for the Working Mathematician]] | edition=2nd | series=[[Graduate Texts in Mathematics]] | volume=5 | location=New York, NY | publisher=[[Springer-Verlag]] | year=1998 | isbn=0-387-98403-8 | zbl=0906.18001 }} * {{cite book | editor1-last=Pedicchio | editor1-first=Maria Cristina | editor2-last=Tholen | editor2-first=Walter | title=Categorical foundations. Special topics in order, topology, algebra, and sheaf theory | series=Encyclopedia of Mathematics and Its Applications | volume=97 | location=Cambridge | publisher=[[Cambridge University Press]] | year=2004 | isbn=0-521-83414-7 | zbl=1034.18001 }} [[Category:Objects (category theory)]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Category see also
(
edit
)
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Visible anchor
(
edit
)