Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Theodicy
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Theological attempt to resolve the problem of evil}} {{Multiple issues| {{Cleanup|reason=idiosyncratic tone and presentation, especially in the "biblical" section|date=December 2023}} {{Copy edit|date=December 2023}} }} {{use dmy dates|date=April 2024}} [[File:Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, Bernhard Christoph Francke.jpg|thumb|[[Gottfried Leibniz]] coined the term "theodicy" to justify God's existence in light of the apparent imperfections of the world.]] {{Theodicy}} {{God|related}} {{Philosophy of religion sidebar|challenges}} In the [[philosophy of religion]], a '''theodicy''' ({{IPAc-en|θ|iː|ˈ|ɒ|d|ɪ|s|i}}; meaning 'vindication of God', from [[Ancient Greek]] θεός ''theos'', "god" and δίκη ''dikē'', "justice") is an argument that attempts to resolve the [[problem of evil]] that arises when [[omnipotence|all power]] and [[omnibenevolence|all goodness]] are simultaneously ascribed to [[God]].<ref>{{Cite book|last=Pecorino|first=Philip A.|chapter-url=https://www.qcc.cuny.edu/socialsciences/ppecorino/intro_text/Chapter%203%20Religion/Problem_of_Evil.htm|title=An Introduction to Philosophy: An Online Textbook|publisher=Queensborough Community College|year=2000|chapter=Chapter 3: 'Philosophy of Religion', Section 11: Problem of Evil |url-status=live |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230906120055/https://www.qcc.cuny.edu/socialsciences/ppecorino/intro_text/Chapter%203%20Religion/Problem_of_Evil.htm |archive-date= 6 September 2023 }}</ref> Unlike a ''defence'', which merely tries to demonstrate that the coexistence of [[the existence of God|God]] and evil is logically possible, a theodicy additionally provides a framework wherein God and evil's existence is considered plausible.<ref>A defence is "an effort to show that there is no formal contradiction between the existence of God... and the existence of evil." Michael Rea and Louis B. Pojman, eds., ''Philosophy of Religion: An Anthology'' (Cengage Learning, 2015, 7th ed.), 229.</ref> The German philosopher and mathematician [[Gottfried Leibniz]] coined the term "theodicy" in 1710 in his work {{lang|fr|[[Théodicée]]}}, though numerous [[Religious responses to the problem of evil|responses to the problem of evil]] had previously been proposed. Similar to a theodicy, a [[cosmodicy]] attempts to justify the fundamental goodness of the universe, and an [[anthropodicy]] attempts to justify the goodness of humanity. ==Definition and etymology== As defined by [[Alvin Plantinga]], a theodicy is "an answer to the question of why God permits evil".<ref>{{cite book |last=Plantinga |first=Alvin |year=1974 |title=God, Freedom, and Evil |publisher=William B. Eerdmans |page=10}}</ref> Theodicy is defined as a theological construct that attempts to vindicate God in response to the [[problem of evil]] that appears inconsistent with the existence of an [[omnipotent]] and [[omnibenevolent]] God.<!--Definition is not this precise, doesn't refer to God's attributes: <ref>{{cite dictionary|url=http://www.thefreedictionary.com/theodicy|title=theodicy|dictionary=The Free Dictionary}}</ref>--><ref>{{cite book|title=The Bible on Suffering|year=2002|publisher=Paulist Press|location=New York|isbn=0-8091-4048-9|editor-first=Anthony J. |editor-last=Tambasco|page=1}}</ref> Another definition of theodicy is the vindication of divine goodness and providence in view of the existence of evil. The word ''theodicy'' derives from the [[Ancient Greek|Greek]] words {{langx|grc|Θεός|Theos|label=none}} and {{langx|grc|δίκη|dikē|label=none}}. {{Transliteration|grc|Theos}} is translated "God" and {{Transliteration|grc|dikē}} can be translated as either "trial" or "judgement".<ref>{{cite dictionary|url=https://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/text?doc=Perseus:text:1999.04.0057:entry=di/kh |title=δίκη |dictionary=[[A Greek–English Lexicon]]|via=The Perseus Project|publisher=Tufts University}}</ref> Thus, 'theodicy' literally means "justifying God".<ref>{{cite encyclopedia |encyclopedia=Encyclopædia Britannica |title=Theodicy |url=http://0-www.britannica.com.librarycatalog.vts.edu/EBchecked/topic/590596/theodicy |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210811090541/https://librarycatalog.vts.edu/wamvalidate?url=http://0-www.britannica.com.librarycatalog.vts.edu:80/EBchecked/topic/590596/theodicy |archive-date=2021-08-11 |access-date=20 October 2013|url-status=dead}}</ref> In the ''[[Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]]'', [[Nick Trakakis]] proposed an additional three requirements which must be contained within a theodicy: * Common sense views of the world * Widely held historical and scientific opinion * Plausible moral principles<ref name="IEP">{{cite encyclopedia |url=http://www.iep.utm.edu/evil-evi/#H4 |title=The Evidential Problem of Evil |encyclopedia=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |date=31 March 2005 |access-date=16 January 2012 |last=Trakakis |first=Nick}}</ref> As a response to the problem of evil, a theodicy is distinct from a defence. A defence attempts to demonstrate that the occurrence of evil does not contradict God's existence, but it does not propose that rational beings are able to understand why God permits evil. A theodicy shows that it is reasonable to believe in God despite evidence of evil in the world and offers a framework which can account for why evil exists.<ref>Bunnin & Tsui-James 2002, p. 481</ref> A theodicy is often based on a prior [[natural theology]], which exist to prove the existence of God,{{clarify|date=August 2023}} and seeks to demonstrate that God's existence remains probable after the problem of evil is posed by giving a justification for God's permitting evil to happen.<ref>Geivett 1995, pp. 60–61</ref> Defenses propose solutions to the [[problem of evil]], while theodicies attempt to answer the problem.<ref name="IEP" /> [[Pseudo-Dionysius]] defines evil by those aspects that show an absence of good.<ref name="N.T.Wright" />{{rp|37}} Writers in this tradition saw things as reflecting 'forms' and evil as a failure to reflect the appropriate form adequately: as a deficit of goodness where goodness ought to have been present. In the same line of thinking, [[Augustine of Hippo|St. Augustine]] also defined evil as an absence of good, as did the theologian and monk [[Thomas Aquinas]], who stated "a man is called ''bad'' insofar as he lacks a virtue, and an eye is called ''bad'' insofar as it lacks the power of sight."<ref name="Richard Swinburne" />{{rp|37}} ''Bad'' as an absence of ''good'' resurfaces in [[Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel|Hegel]], [[Martin Heidegger|Heidegger]] and [[Karl Barth|Barth]]. Very similar are the [[Neoplatonists]], such as [[Plotinus]] and the contemporary philosopher Denis O'Brien, who say that evil is a privation.<ref name="O'Brien">{{cite book |last=O'Brien |first=D. |year=1996 |chapter=Plotinus on matter and evil |title=The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus |editor-first=L. P. |editor-last=Gerson |location=Cambridge |publisher=Cambridge University Press |pages=171–195}}</ref><ref name="Plotinus">{{cite book |author=Plotinus |title=The Enneads |translator-first=S. |translator-last=Mackenna |location=London |publisher=Faber |edition=4th |others=Revised by B. S. Page |year=1969}}</ref> {{blockquote|It is important to note that there are at least two concepts of evil: a broad concept and a narrow concept. The broad concept picks out any bad state of affairs ... [and] has been divided into two categories: natural evil and moral evil. Natural evils are bad states of affairs which do not result from the intentions or negligence of moral agents. Hurricanes and toothaches are examples of natural evils. By contrast, moral evils do result from the intentions or negligence of moral agents. Murder and lying are examples of moral evils. Evil in the broad sense, which includes all natural and moral evils, tends to be the sort of evil referenced in theological contexts ... [T]he narrow concept of evil picks out only the most morally despicable ... [it] involves moral condemnation, [and] is appropriately ascribed only to moral agents and their actions.<ref name="Todd Calder">{{cite encyclopedia |last=Calder |first=Todd |title=The Concept of Evil |encyclopedia=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |date=Winter 2016 |editor-first=Edward N. |editor-last=Zalta |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/concept-evil/}}</ref>}} [[Marxism]], "selectively elaborating Hegel", defines evil in terms of its effect.<ref name="N.T.Wright">{{cite book|last1=Wright|first1=N. T.|title=Evil and the Justice of God|year=2006|publisher=Intervarsity Press|location=Downer's Grove, Illinois|isbn=978-0-8308-3415-0}}</ref>{{rp|44}} Philosopher John Kekes says the effect of evil must include actual harm that "interferes with the functioning of a person as a full-fledged agent".<ref>Kekes 1998, 217</ref><ref name="Todd Calder" /> Christian philosophers and theologians such as [[Richard Swinburne]] and [[N. T. Wright]] also define evil in terms of effect, stating that an "act is objectively good (or bad) if it is good (or bad) in its consequences".<ref name="Richard Swinburne">{{cite book|last1=Swinburne|first1=Richard|title=Providence and the Problem of Evil|date=1998|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=Oxford, England|isbn=0-19-823799-5}}</ref>{{rp|12}}<ref name="N.T.Wright" /> [[Hinduism]] defines evil in terms of its effect, saying "the evils that afflict people (and indeed animals) in the present life are the effects of wrongs committed in a previous life."<ref name="N.T.Wright" />{{rp|34}} Some contemporary philosophers argue a focus on the effects of evil is inadequate as a definition since evil can observe without actively causing the harm, and it is still evil.<ref name="Todd Calder" /> Philosopher [[Susan Neiman]] says "a [[Crimes against humanity|''crime against humanity'']] is something for which we have procedures, ... [and it] can be ... fit into the rest of our experience. To call an action ''evil'' is to suggest that it cannot [be fitted in]".<ref name="Susan Nieman">{{cite book|last1=Nieman|first1=Susan|title=Evil in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy|publisher=Princeton University Press|location=Princeton, New Jersey|isbn=978-0-691-16850-0|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3LpKCAAAQBAJ&q=Evil%20in%20Modern%20Thought%20by%20Susan%20Nieman&pg=PR4|date=2015-08-25}}</ref>{{rp|8}} [[Immanuel Kant]] was the first to offer a purely secular theory of evil, giving an evaluative definition of evil based on its cause as having a will that is not fully good. Kant has been an important influence on philosophers like [[Hannah Arendt]], [[Claudia Card]], and Richard Bernstein.<ref name="Immanuel Kant">{{cite book|last1=Kant|first1=Immanuel|title=Kant: Religion Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason: And Other Writings|date=2003|publisher=Cambridge University Press|location=Cambridge, England|isbn=0-521-59049-3}}</ref> "Hannah Arendt ... uses the term ['radical evil'] to denote a new form of wrongdoing which cannot be captured by other moral concepts."<ref name="Todd Calder" /> Claudia Card says evil is excessive wrongdoing; others like [[Hillel Steiner]] say evil is qualitatively, not quantitatively, distinct from mere wrongdoing.<ref name="Todd Calder" /> [[John Locke]], [[Thomas Hobbes]], and [[Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]] define good and evil in terms of pleasure and pain.<ref name="John Locke">{{cite book|last1=Locke|first1=John|title=An Essay Concerning Human Understanding|date=1836|publisher=B. Griffin and Co.|location=Glasgow}}</ref><ref name="Hobbes">{{cite book|last1=Hobbes|first1=Thomas|title=Leviathan|date=2018|publisher=Lerner Publishing Group|location=Minneapolis, Minnesota|isbn=978-151-248609-4}}</ref><ref name="Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz">{{cite book|last1=Leibniz|first1=Gottfried Wilhelm|author1-link=Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz|title=Theodicy|date=2009|publisher=Cosimo|isbn=978-1-61640-295-2}}</ref> Others such as Swinburne find that definition inadequate, saying, "the good of individual humans ... consists ... in their having free will ... the ability to develop ... character ..., to show courage and loyalty, to love, to be of use, to contemplate beauty and discover truth ... All that [good] ... cannot be achieved without ... suffering along the way."<ref name="Richard Swinburne" />{{rp|4}} {{blockquote|Most theorists writing about evil believe that evil action requires a certain sort of motivation ... the desire to cause harm, or to do wrong, ... pleasure (Steiner 2002), the desire to annihilate all being (Eagleton 2010), or the destruction of others for its own sake (Cole 2006). When evil is restricted to actions that follow from these sorts of motivations, theorists sometimes say that their subject is pure, radical, diabolical, or monstrous evil. This suggests that their discussion is restricted to a type, or form, of evil and not to evil per se.<ref name= "Todd Calder"/>|sign=|source=}} Some theorists define evil by what emotions are connected to it. "For example, Laurence Thomas believes that evildoers take delight in causing harm or feel hatred toward their victims (Thomas 1993, 76–77)."<ref name="Todd Calder" />{{citation needed|reason=Better to paraphrase and cite Thomas directly|date=May 2024}} Buddhism defines various types of evil, one type defines as behavior resulting from a failure to emotionally detach from the world.<ref name="Nyanaponika Thera">{{cite book|last1=Thera|first1=Nyanaponika|title=The Roots of Good and Evil: Buddhist Texts translated from the Pali|date=2008|publisher=Buddhist Publication Society |isbn=978-955-24-0316-3}}</ref> Christian theologians generally define evil in terms of both human responsibility and the nature of God: "If we take the essentialist view of Christian ethics ... evil is anything contrary to God's good nature ... (character or attributes)."<ref name="Joseph B. Onyango Okello">{{cite book|last1=Onyango Okello|first1=Joseph B.|title=Evil and Pain: A Critique of the Materialistic Account of Evil|date=2017|publisher=Wipf and Stock|location=Eugene, Oregon|isbn=978-1-5326-0134-7}}</ref> The Judaic view, while acknowledging the difference between the human and divine perspective of evil, is rooted in the nature of creation itself and the limitation inherent in matter's capacity to be perfected; the action of free will includes the potential for perfection from individual effort and leaves the responsibility for evil in human hands.<ref name="Oliver Leaman">{{cite book|last1=Leaman|first1=Oliver|title=Evil and Suffering in Jewish Philosophy|date=1995|publisher=Cambridge University Press|location=New York|isbn=0-521-41724-4}}</ref>{{rp|70}} As Swinburne notes: "[It is] deeply central to the whole tradition of Christian (and other western) religion that God is loving toward his creation and that involves him behaving in morally good ways toward it."<ref name="Richard Swinburne" />{{rp|3}} Within Christianity, "God is supposed to be in some way personal ... a being who is essentially eternal, omnipotent, omniscient, Creator and sustainer of the universe, and perfectly good. An omnipotent being is one who can do anything logically possible ... such a being could not make me exist and not exist at the same time but he could eliminate the stars ... An omniscient being is one who knows everything logically possible for him to know".<ref name="Richard Swinburne" />{{rp|3–15}} "God's perfect goodness is moral goodness."<ref name="Richard Swinburne" />{{rp|15}} ==Reasons for theodicy== Theodicies are developed to answer the question of why a good [[God]] permits the manifestation of [[evil]], thus resolving the issue of the [[problem of evil]]. Some theodicies also address the problem of evil "to make the existence of an [[omniscience|all-knowing]], [[omnipotence|all-powerful]] and [[omnibenevolence|all-good or omnibenevolent]] God consistent with the existence of evil or suffering in the world".<ref>{{Cite book|last=Pecorino|first=Philip A.|url=https://www.qcc.cuny.edu/socialsciences/ppecorino/intro_text/Chapter%203%20Religion/Problem_of_Evil.htm|title=An Introduction to Philosophy: An Online Textbook|publisher=Queensborough Community College|year=2000|chapter=Chapter 3: 'Philosophy of Religion', Section 11: Problem of Evil}}</ref> The philosopher Richard Swinburne says "most theists need a theodicy, [they need] an account of reasons why God might allow evil to occur."<ref name="Richard Swinburne" />{{rp|2}} According to [[Andrew Loke|Loke]], theodicies might have a therapeutical use for some people, though their main purpose is to provide a sound theistic argument rather than to succeed as a therapy.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Loke |first1=Andrew Ter Ern |title=Evil, Sin and Christian Theism |date=2022 |publisher=Routledge |page=11}}</ref> However, theodicies do "seek to provide hope to the sufferers that... evils can be defeated just as minor tribulations can be defeated."<ref>{{cite book |last1=Loke |first1=Andrew Ter Ern |title=Evil, Sin and Christian Theism |date=2022 |publisher=Routledge |page=8}}</ref> ==History== The term ''theodicy'' was coined by the German philosopher [[Gottfried Leibniz]] in his 1710 work, written in French, {{lang|fr|[[Essais de Théodicée sur la bonté de Dieu, la liberté de l'homme et l'origine du mal]]}} (''Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil'').<ref>Leibniz 1734</ref> Leibniz's {{lang|fr|Théodicée}} was a response to [[skepticism|skeptical]] Protestant philosopher [[Pierre Bayle]], who wrote in his work {{lang|fr|[[Dictionnaire Historique et Critique]]}} that, after rejecting three attempts to solve it, he saw no rational solution to the problem of evil. Bayle argued that this state of affairs must simply be accepted because the Bible asserts the coexistence of God and evil.<ref>{{cite encyclopedia | url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/bayle/ | title=Pierre Bayle | encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy | date=7 February 2003 | access-date=January 22, 2012 | last=Lennon |first=Thomas}}</ref> In ''[[The Catholic Encyclopedia]]'' (1914), Constantine Kempf argued that, inspired by Leibniz's work, philosophers called their works on the problem of evil "theodicies", and philosophy about God was brought under the discipline of theodicy. He argued that theodicy began to include all of [[natural theology]], meaning that theodicy came to consist of the human knowledge of God through the systematic use of reason.<ref>{{cite encyclopedia | url=http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/14569a.htm | title=Theodicy | encyclopedia=The Catholic Encyclopedia | year=2012 | access-date=4 September 2012 | last=Kempf |first=Constantine}}</ref> In 1966, British philosopher [[John Hick]] published ''Evil and the God of Love'', in which he surveyed various Christian responses to the problem of evil, before developing his own.<ref>Cheetham 2003, p. 40</ref> In his work, Hick identified and distinguished between three types of theodicy: [[Plotinian theodicy|Plotinian]], which was named after [[Plotinus]], [[Augustinian theodicy|Augustinian]], which had dominated [[Western Christianity]] for many centuries, and [[Irenaean theodicy|Irenaean]], which was developed by the Eastern [[Church Father]] [[Irenaeus]], a version of which Hick subscribed to himself.<ref>Hall 2003, p. 132</ref> In his dialogue "Is God a Taoist?",<ref>Smullyan 1977, p. 86</ref> published in 1977 in his book ''[[The Tao Is Silent]]'', [[Raymond Smullyan]] claims to prove that it is logically impossible to have sentient beings without allowing "evil", even for God, just as it is impossible for him to create a triangle in the Euclidean plane having an angular sum other than 180 degrees. Therefore, the capability of feeling implies free will, which may allow for "evil", understood here as hurting other sentient beings. The problem of evil happening to good or innocent people is not addressed directly here, but both reincarnation and karma are hinted at.<ref>{{Cite book |last= |first= |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/1105767117 |title=Perspectives on Reincarnation: Hindu, Christian, and Scientific |date= 18 January 2019|publisher=Multidisciplinary Digital Publishing Institute |isbn=978-3-03897-535-9 |location= |oclc=1105767117}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal |last=Freschi |first=Elisa |date=2021-10-12 |title=Is the Theory of Karman the Solution to the Problem of Evil? Some Thoughts from Viśiṣṭādvaita Vedānta |journal=Religions |language=en |volume=12 |issue=10 |pages=862 |doi=10.3390/rel12100862 |issn=2077-1444|doi-access=free |hdl=1807/107705 |hdl-access=free }}</ref> ===Ancient religions=== "Writings and discourses on theodicy by Jews, Greeks, Christians, and Eastern religions have graced our planet for thousands of years."<ref>{{cite book |last=Birnbaum |first=David |year=1989 |title=God and Evil |location=Hoboken |publisher=Ktav |page=4}}</ref> In the [[Middle Kingdom of Egypt]] (2000–1700 BC) as "in Ancient Mesopotamian and Israelite literature", theodicy was an important issue.<ref>{{cite book |last=Assman |first=Jan |year=2001 |title=The Search for God in Ancient Egypt |translator-first=David |translator-last=Lorton |publisher=Cornell University Press |page=169}}</ref>{{non sequitur|date=January 2025}} Philip Irving Mitchell of [[Dallas Baptist University]] notes that some philosophers have cast the pursuit of theodicy as a modern one, as earlier scholars used the problem of evil to support the existence of one particular god over another, explain wisdom, or explain a conversion, rather than to justify God's goodness.<ref>{{cite web | url=http://www3.dbu.edu/mitchell/theodicy.htm | title=Theodicy: An Overview | publisher=Dallas Baptist University | access-date=17 July 2012 | last=Mitchell |first=Philip Irving}}</ref> [[Sarah Iles Johnston]] argues that ancient civilizations, such as the ancient [[Ancient Mesopotamia|Mesopotamians]], [[ancient Greece|Greeks]], [[Ancient Rome|Romans]], and [[Ancient Egypt|Egyptians]] held [[polytheistic]] beliefs that may have enabled them to deal with the concept of theodicy differently. These religions taught the existence of many [[deity|gods]] and [[goddess]]es who controlled various aspects of daily life. These early religions may have avoided the question of theodicy by endowing their deities with the same flaws and jealousies that plagued [[human]]ity. No one god or goddess was fundamentally good or evil; this explained that bad things could happen to good people if they angered a deity because the gods could exercise the same free will that humankind possesses. Such religions taught that some gods were more inclined to be helpful and benevolent while others were more likely to be spiteful and aggressive. In this sense, the evil gods could be blamed for misfortune, while the good gods could be petitioned with prayer and sacrifices to make things right. There was still a sense of justice in that individuals who were right with the gods could avoid punishment.<ref>Johnston 2004, pp. 531–547</ref> The "[[Epicurean trilemma]]", however, was already raised {{circa|300 BC}} by [[Epicurus]], according to [[David Hume]] in 1779. According to Hume, the trilemma describes the problem of reconciling an omnipotent deity with its benevolence and the existence of evil. However, if Epicurus did write a discussion on the specific problems that Hume attributes to him, it would not have been tied with the question of an omnibenevolent and omniscient God, as Hume assumes (for Hume does not cite, nor make any implication that he had knowledge of Epicurus's writings on this matter that held any greater weight than academic hearsay or legend).{{original research inline|reason=Opinion about Hume's interpretation of Epicurus must be attributed to a source|date=May 2024}} ===Biblical theodicy=== {{Main|Theodicy and the Bible}} The biblical account of the justification of evil and suffering in God's presence has similarities and contrasts in the Hebrew Bible and the New Testament. For the Hebrew Bible, the [[Book of Job]] is often quoted as the authoritative source of discussion.<ref>{{cite book |last=Steiner |first=George |chapter=Introduction |title=The Old Testament |edition=Modern Library }}</ref>{{full citation needed|reason=date, publisher?|date=May 2024}}<ref name="Grace Ko">{{cite book|title=Theodicy in Habakkuk|last1=Ko|first1=Grace|date=2014|publisher=Paternoster|location=United Kingdom}}</ref>{{rp|Chapter 3: Job}} {{Blockquote|text=The author of Job seeks to expand the understanding of divine justice ... beyond mere retribution, to include a system of divine sovereignty [showing] the King has the right to test His subject's loyalty ... The book of Job corrects the rigid and overly simplistic doctrine of retribution in attributing suffering to sin and punishment. It closes with a focus on the bond between creator and creation, on placing one in that, and on hope rooted in belief that God is in ultimate control.|sign=|source=}} It is generally accepted that God's responsive speeches in Job do not directly answer Job's complaints; God does not attempt to justify himself or reveal the reason for Job's suffering to him; instead, God's speeches focus on increasing Job's overall understanding of his relationship with God. This exemplifies Biblical theodicy.<ref name="Mark S. M. Scott"/>{{rp|21,28}} There is general agreement among Bible scholars that the Bible "does not admit of a singular perspective on evil ... Instead we encounter a variety of perspectives ... Consequently [the Bible focuses on] moral and spiritual remedies, not rational or logical [justifications] ... It is simply that the Bible operates within a cosmic, moral and spiritual landscape rather than within a rationalist, abstract, ontological landscape."<ref name="Mark S. M. Scott">{{cite book|last1=Scott|first1=Mark S. M.|title=Pathways in Theodicy: An Introduction to the Problem of Evil|date=2015|publisher=Fortress Press|isbn=978-1-4514-6470-2}}</ref>{{rp|27}} This is evidenced by God's first and second speeches in Job. God's first speech concerns human ignorance and God's authority. Job had seen himself at the center of events, lamenting that God had singled him out to oppress; God responded that Job was not the center; God was; his kingdom was complex, and he governed on a large scale. Since God is in dominion over all the earth, Job cannot conceivably condemn him unless Job proves that he can do all the things God can.<ref name="Grace Ko" />{{rp|Chapter 3:Job}} God's second speech is against human self-righteousness. Job has vehemently accused God of thwarting justice as "the omnipotent tyrant, the cosmic thug". Some scholars interpret God's response as an admission of failure on his part, but he goes on to say he has the power and, in his own timing, will bring justice in the end.<ref name="Grace Ko" />{{rp|Chapter 3:Job}} "Isaiah is generally recognized as one of the most progressive books of the prophetic corpus."<ref name="Tod Linafelt">{{cite book|editor1-last=Linafelt|editor1-first=Tod|title=Strange Fire: Reading the Bible After the Holocaust|date=2000|publisher=New York University Press|isbn=0-8147-5165-2}}</ref>{{rp|208}} Christian theologians state that in the Bible "suffering is understood as having transcendent meaning ... human agency can give particular instances of suffering a mystical significance that transforms it into something productive."<ref name="Sarah K. Pinnock">{{cite book|last1=Pinnock|first1=Sarah K.|title=Beyond Theodicy: Jewish and Christian Continental Thinkers Respond to the Holocaust|date=2002|publisher=State University of New York Press|location=New York|isbn=0-7914-5523-8}}</ref> Theodicy in the [[Book of Ezekiel]] (and also in Jeremiah 31:29–30) confronts the concept of personal moral responsibility. The book exemplifies the power of sin in that "The main point is stated at the beginning and at the end—'the soul that sins shall die.{{'"}} To Christians, the 'power of sin' was abolished in the death and resurrection of [[Jesus]], which rendered all Christians forgiven and righteous. The main point "is explicated by a case history of a family traced through three generations". It is not about heredity but understanding divine justice in a world under divine governance.<ref>{{cite book|last1=Blenkinsopp|first1=Joseph|title=Ezekiel|date=1990|publisher=John Knox Press|location=Louisville|isbn=0-8042-3118-4}}</ref>{{rp|82}} "Theodicy in the Minor Prophets differs little from that in Isaiah, Jeremiah and Ezekiel."<ref name="Paul L. Redditt">{{cite book|last1=Redditt|first1=Paul L.|title=Thematic Threads in the Book of the Twelve|date=2003|publisher=Walter De Gruyter|location=New York|isbn=3-11-017594-0}}</ref> For example, the first chapter of [[Habakkuk]] raises questions about God's justice, laments God's inaction in punishing injustice, and looks for God's action in response—then objects to what God chooses.<ref name="Grace Ko" />{{rp|Chapter 1}} Instead of engaging in debate, God gives Habakkuk a vision of the future which includes five oracles that form a theodicy: # God has a plan and has appointed a time for judgment. It may be slow in coming as humans see things, but it will come; # The woe oracles confront the prevalence of evil in the world and the justice those acts have earned; # The vision of the manifestation of God is a recognition of God's power to address these issues; # God, as a warrior, will fight for his people; # The song of triumph says the faithful will prevail by holding to trust and hope.<ref name="Grace Ko" />{{rp|Intro, Chapter 3}} Joel and the other minor prophets demonstrate that theodicy and eschatology are connected in the Bible.<ref name="Paul L. Redditt" />{{rp|201}} Psalm 73 presents the internal struggle created by personal suffering and the prosperity of the wicked. The writer gains perspective when he "enters the sanctuary of God (16–17)" seeing that God's justice will eventually prevail. He reaffirms his relationship with God, is ashamed of his resentment, and chooses trust.<ref name="Grace Ko" />{{rp|Chapter 3:Psalm 73}} Psalm 77 contains real outspokenness to God as well as determination to hold onto faith and trust.<ref name="Grace Ko" />{{rp|Chapter 3:Psalm 77}} For Christians, the scriptures assure them that the allowance of evil is for a good purpose based on relationship with God.<ref name="Frame & Torres 2015">{{cite book|first1=John M. |last1=Frame |first2=Joseph E. |last2=Torres |name-list-style=and |title=Apologetics: A Justification of Christian Belief |location=Phillipsburg, New Jersey |publisher=P&R |year=2015 }}</ref>{{rp|184}} "Some of the good ... cannot be achieved without delay and suffering, and the evil of this world is indeed necessary for the achievement of those good purposes. ... God has the right to allow such evils to occur, so long as the 'goods' are facilitated and the 'evils' are limited and compensated in the way that various other Christian doctrines (of human free will, life after death, the end of the world, etc.) affirm ... the 'good states' which (according to Christian doctrine) God seeks are so good that they outweigh the accompanying evils."<ref name="Richard Swinburne" />{{rp|Intro., 51}} This is somewhat illustrated in—according to Christian interpretation—the [[Book of Exodus]] when Pharaoh is described as being raised up that God's name be known in all the earth (Exodus 9:16). In Christian theology, this is mirrored in [[Book of Romans|Romans]] 9, wherein Paul appeals to God's sovereignty as sufficient explanation, with God's goodness experientially known to the Christian.<ref name="Frame & Torres 2015"/>{{rp|178–79}} ===Augustinian theodicy=== {{Main|Augustinian theodicy}} The [[Protestantism|Protestant]] and [[Calvinism|Calvinist]] reading of [[Augustinian theodicy]], as promoted primarily by [[John Hick]], is based on the writings of [[Augustine of Hippo]], a [[Christian philosophy|Christian philosopher]] and theologian who lived from AD 354 to 430.<ref>{{cite encyclopedia | url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/augustine/#OntEud | title=Saint Augustine |encyclopedia=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy | orig-date=24 March 2000 | date=12 November 2010 | access-date=9 October 2011 | last=Mendelson |first=Michael}}</ref> The Catholic (pre-Reformation) formulation of the same issue is substantially different and is outlined below. In Hick's approach, this form of theodicy argues that evil does not exist except as a [[privation]]—or corruption—of goodness, and therefore God did not create evil.<ref>Menn 2002, p. 170</ref> Augustinian scholars have argued that God created the world perfectly, with no evil or human suffering. Evil entered the world through the disobedience of [[Adam and Eve]], and the theodicy casts the existence of evil as a just punishment for this [[original sin]].<ref>Corey 2000, pp. 177–78</ref> The theodicy argues that humans have an evil nature in as much as it is deprived of their original goodness, form, order, and measure due to the inherited original sin of [[Adam]] and [[Eve]], but still ultimately remains good due to existence coming from God, for if nature were completely evil (deprived of the good), it would cease to exist.<ref>Green 2011, p. 779</ref> It maintains that God remains blameless and good.<ref>Geivett 1995, p. 19</ref> In the [[Roman Catholic theology|Roman Catholic]] reading of Augustine, the issue of [[just war]] as developed in his book [[City of God (book)|''The City of God'']] substantially established his position concerning the positive justification of killing, suffering and pain as inflicted upon an enemy when encountered in war for a just cause.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.christianitytoday.com/ct/2001/septemberweb-only/9-17-55.0.html |first=Robert L. |last=Holmes |title=A Time For War? |website=Christianity Today |date=2001-09-01 |access-date=2013-04-28}}</ref> Augustine asserted that peacefulness in the face of a grave wrong that could only be stopped by violence would be a sin. Defense of oneself or others could be necessary, especially when authorized by a legitimate authority. While not elaborating the conditions required for war to be just, Augustine nonetheless originated the very phrase, itself, in his work ''The City of God''.<ref name="Crusades Encyclopedia">{{cite web |first=Andrew |last=Holt |url=http://www.crusades-encyclopedia.com/augustineofhippo.html |title=Augustine of Hippo |year=2005<!--date in copyright notice--> |url-status=dead |archive-url=https://archive.today/20120728203512/http://www.crusades-encyclopedia.com/augustineofhippo.html |archive-date=2012-07-28 |website=Crusades-Encyclopedia |access-date=2013-04-28}}</ref> In essence, the pursuit of peace must include the option of fighting with all of its eventualities in order to preserve peace in the long-term.<ref name="Crusades Encyclopedia"/> Such a war could not be pre-emptive but defensive to restore peace.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.jknirp.com/mattox.htm |publisher=National Institute for the Renewal of the Priesthood |title=Saint Augustine and the Theory of Just War |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20131103033459/http://www.jknirp.com/mattox.htm |archive-date=2013-11-03 |date=2007-01-23 |access-date=2013-04-28}}</ref> [[Thomas Aquinas]], centuries later, used the authority of Augustine's arguments in an attempt to define the conditions under which a war could be just.<ref>{{cite web |url=http://www.catholiceducation.org/articles/politics/pg0029.html |title=The Just War |website=Catholic Education Resource Center |url-status=dead |access-date=2013-04-28 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20130523033051/http://www.catholiceducation.org/articles/politics/pg0029.html |archive-date=2013-05-23}}</ref><ref>{{cite book|title=The Story of Christianity|url=https://archive.org/details/storyofchristian01gonz|url-access=registration|last=Gonzalez |first=Justo L. |year=1984|publisher=Harper|isbn=0-06-185588-X|place=San Francisco}}</ref> ===Irenaean theodicy=== {{Main|Irenaean theodicy}} [[Irenaeus]] (died {{c.|202}}), born in the early 2nd century, expressed ideas that explained the existence of evil as necessary for human development. Irenaeus argued that human creation consists of two parts: humans are made first in the image and then in the likeness of God. The image of God consists of having the potential to achieve moral perfection, whereas the likeness of God is the achievement of that perfection. To attain moral perfection, Irenaeus suggested that humans must have free will. To achieve such free will, humans must experience suffering, and God must be at an [[epistemology|epistemic distance]] (a distance of knowledge) from humanity. Therefore, evil exists to allow humans to develop as moral agents.<ref name="Encountering evil"> Davis 2001, pp. 40–42</ref> In the 20th century, [[John Hick]] collated the ideas of Irenaeus into a distinct theodicy. He argued that the world exists as a "vale of soul-making" (a phrase that he drew from [[John Keats]]) and that suffering and evil must therefore occur. He argued that human goodness develops through the experience of evil and suffering.<ref>Stump 1999, pp. 222–227</ref> === Compensation theodicy === According to the strong version of Compensation Theodicy advanced by Seyyed Jaaber Mousavirad, there are two elements that, when considered together, can solve the problem of evil: {{ordered list|type=upper-alpha | The primary good within evil, even though it may not be greater than the evil itself or even return to the same inflicted individual. This element resolves the problem of the futility of evils. | Compensation in the afterlife. This element, as a complementary factor, can explain how the justice of God is compatible with evils.}} Given the strong version of this theodicy, if evils will be compensated, the existence of some good is enough to justify them, even though there will be no resulting greater good in this world. Likewise, if evils will be compensated, it is not necessary for them to be distributed equally. Even if evil has no good for an individual, while it has some good for others, it is reasonable for it to occur.<ref>{{Cite journal |last=Mousavirad |first=Seyyed Jaaber |date=2022-07-02 |title=Theory of Compensation and Problem of Evil; a New Defense |url=https://www.philosophy-of-religion.eu/index.php/ejpr/article/view/3357 |journal=European Journal for Philosophy of Religion |volume=14 |issue=2 |doi=10.24204/ejpr.2022.3357 |issn=1689-8311}}</ref> ===Origenian theodicy=== In direct response to John Hick's description of theodicy, Mark Scott has indicated that neither [[Augustine of Hippo]] nor [[Irenaeus|Irenaeus of Lyons]] provide an appropriate context for the discussion of Hick's theistic version of theodicy. As a theologian among the [[Church Fathers]] who articulated a theory of {{Transliteration|grc|[[apokatastasis]]}} (or [[universal reconciliation]]), [[Origen|Origen of Alexandria]] provides a more direct theological comparison for the discussion of Hick's presentation of universal salvation and theodicy. Neither Irenaeus nor Augustine endorsed a theology of universal salvation in any form comparable to that of John Hick.<ref>{{cite book |last=Scott |first=Mark |year=2012 |title=Origen and the Problem of Evil |publisher=Oxford University Press}}</ref> ===Relatively minor theodicies=== [[Michael Martin (philosopher)|Michael Martin]] summarizes what he calls "relatively minor" theodicies:<ref>{{cite book |first=Michael |last=Martin |title=Atheism: A Philosophical Justification |publisher=Temple University Press |year=1992 |pages=436–454}}</ref> * The [[finite God]] theodicy maintains that God is all-good ([[omnibenevolent]]) but not all-powerful ([[omnipotent]]). * The [[best of all possible worlds]] theodicy, a traditional theology defended by Leibniz, argues that the creation is the best of all possible worlds. * The [[original sin]] theodicy holds that evil came into the world because of humanity's original sin. * The ultimate harmony theodicy justifies evil as leading to "good long-range consequences". * The "degree of desirability of a conscious state" theodicy has been reckoned a "complex theodicy".{{by whom|reason=Blog source removed. Blogs are not [[WP:RS|reliable sources]]|date=May 2024}} It argues that a person's state is deemed evil only when it is undesirable to the person. However, because God cannot make a person's state desirable to the person, the theodic problem does not exist.<ref>{{cite book |first=Michael |last=Martin |title=Atheism: A Philosophical Justification |publisher=Temple University Press |year=1992 |pages=444–45}} Martin finds this theodicy in {{cite book |first=George |last=Schlesinger |title=Religion and Scientific Method |publisher=Springer |year=2012|mode=cs2}}, and judges it unsatisfactory.</ref> * The [[reincarnation]] theodicy believes that people suffer evil because of their wrongdoing in a previous life. * The contrast theodicy holds that evil is needed to enable people to appreciate or understand good. * The warning theodicy rationalizes evil as God's warning to people to mend their ways. A defence has been proposed by the American philosopher [[Alvin Plantinga]], which is focused on showing the logical possibility of God's existence. Plantinga's [[Alvin Plantinga's free-will defense|version of the free-will defence]] argued that the coexistence of God and evil is not logically impossible and that free will further explains the existence of evil without contradicting the existence of God.<ref>{{Cite web |date=2022-02-07 |title=Theodicy, Natural Evil and Simulation Theory |url=https://www.thearchitect.global/theodicy-natural-evil-and-simulation-theory/ |access-date=2022-06-08 |website=The Global Architect Institute |language=en-US}}</ref> == Islam == === Ashʿarī theology === Most Sunni theologians analyzed theodicy from an anti-realist [[Meta-ethics|metaethical]] standpoint.<ref name=shihadeh/> [[Ash'ari]] theologians argued that ordinary moral judgments stem from emotion and [[social convention]], which are inadequate to either condemn or justify divine actions.<ref name=shihadeh/> Ash'arites hold that God creates everything, including human actions, but distinguish creation ({{Transliteration|ar|khalq}}) from acquisition ({{Transliteration|ar|kasb}}) of actions.<ref name=roy>{{cite book|title=What is Islamic Philosophy?|first=Roy |last=Jackson|publisher=Routledge|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=5XPMAgAAQBAJ&pg=PA32|pages=32–33|isbn=9781317814047|date=2014-02-05}}</ref> They allow individuals the latter ability, though they do not posit existence of free will in a fuller sense of the term. In the words of [[Al-Shahrastani]] (1086–1153):<ref name=roy/> {{blockquote|God creates, in man, the power, ability, choice, and will to perform an act, and man, endowed with this derived power, chooses freely one of the alternatives and intends or wills to do the action, and, corresponding to this intention, God creates and completes the action.}} [[Ash'ari]] theology insists on ultimate divine transcendence and teaches that human knowledge regarding it is limited to what has been revealed through the prophets, so that on the question of God's creation of evil, revelation has to be accepted {{Transliteration|ar|bila kayfa}} (without asking how).<ref>{{cite encyclopedia|first=Tamara |last=Sonn|title=Tawḥīd|encyclopedia=The Oxford Encyclopedia of the Islamic World|editor-first=John L. |editor-last=Esposito|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=Oxford|year=2009|isbn=978-0-19-530513-5 |url=http://www.oxfordreference.com/view/10.1093/acref/9780195305135.001.0001/acref-9780195305135-e-0788?rskey=y8ZWqZ|url-access=subscription }}</ref><ref name=roy/> === Māturīdism === In contrast to Ash'arites, [[Maturidi]] adheres to [[moral realism]] (human mind is able to grasp good and evil independent from revelation),<ref>{{cite book |first=Oliver |last=Leaman |title=The Biographical Encyclopedia of Islamic Philosophy |publisher=Bloomsbury |year=2015 |isbn=978-1-472-56945-5 |page=311}}</ref> yet disagrees with the Mu'tazilite assertion that God's wisdom entails creating only what is good. Good and evil, though real, are considered to be created by God, thus God is not subject to good and evil, humans merely learn whatever God created. Blaming God for a violation of right and wrong is thus considered undue, since God created ''right'' and ''wrong'' in the first place.<ref name="auto">{{cite journal |last=Alper |first=Hülya |title=Maturidi'nin Mutezile Eleştirisi: Tanrı En İyiyi Yaratmak Zorunda mıdır? |trans-title=Maturidi's Criticism of Mu'tazila: Does God Have to Create the Best? |language=tr |journal=KADER Kelam Araştırmaları Dergisi |volume=11 |issue=1 |year=2013 |pages=17–36}}</ref> Whatever is considered evil by humans, would be ultimately good. A distinction exists among those who follow {{lang|ar-Latn|tawhid}} and those who reject it. Maturidi cites Surah [[Al Imran]] verse 178, to point out that God does not regard believers and unbelievers as equal; God would increase the sin of the sinners (and guide the believers).<ref name="auto"/> According to the Maturidite school of thought, ontological evil serves a greater purpose and is in essence secretly good.<ref>Miles, L. (2018). Introduction to the Study of Religion. Vereinigtes Königreich: EDTECH. p. 70</ref> Since God's wisdom is not considered to focus on choosing between good and evil, it is concerned with putting things in their proper place. The existence of evil as separate from good (or opposing good) is rejected throughout sources of Maturidite thinkers. Maturidi himself criticizes believing in the opposition of good and evil as a remnant of [[Persian religion|Persian]] [[Dualism (philosophy)|dualistic religions]].<ref>{{cite book |last=Bürgel |first=J. Christoph |chapter=Zoroastrianism as Viewed in Medieval Islamic Sources |title=Muslim Perceptions of Other Religions |year=1999 |pages=202–212}}</ref> [[Rumi]] likewise said in his refutation of ''[[Ahriman]]'' (principle of evil) that "good cannot exist without evil" and "there is no separation between them".<ref>{{cite thesis |type=MA |url=https://ir.lib.uwo.ca/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=10585&context=etd |last=Asghar |first=Irfan |title=The Notion of Evil in the Qur'an and Islamic Mystical Thought |publisher=The University of Western Ontario |year=2021}}</ref> === Mu'tazilism and Falsafa=== [[Mu'tazila]] theologians approached the problem of theodicy within a framework of [[moral realism]], according to which the moral value of acts is accessible to unaided reason, so that humans can make moral judgments about divine acts.<ref name=shihadeh>{{cite encyclopedia|first=Ayman |last=Shihadeh |title=Suffering|editor-first=Josef W. |editor-last=Meri|encyclopedia=Medieval Islamic Civilization: An Encyclopedia|publisher=Routledge|year=2005|page=772|url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LaV-IGZ8VKIC&pg=PA772|isbn=978-0-415-96692-4}}</ref> They argued that the divine act of creation is good despite existence of suffering, because it allows humans a compensation of greater reward in the afterlife.<ref name=shihadeh/> They posited that individuals have free will to commit evil and absolved God of responsibility for such acts.<ref name=shihadeh/> God's justice thus consists of punishing wrongdoers.<ref name=shihadeh/> Following the demise of Mu'tazila as a school, their theodicy was adopted in the [[Zaydi]] and [[Twelver]] branches of [[Shia Islam]].<ref name=shihadeh/> [[Ibn Sina]], the most influential Muslim philosopher, analyzed theodicy from a purely ontological, [[neoplatonic]] standpoint, aiming to prove that God, as the absolutely good First Cause, created a good world.<ref name=shihadeh/> Ibn Sina argued that evil refers either to a cause of an entity (such as burning in a fire), being a quality of another entity, or to its imperfection (such as blindness), in which case it does not exist as an entity. According to Ibn Sina, such qualities are necessary attributes of the best possible order of things, so that the good they serve is greater than the harm they cause.<ref name=shihadeh/> Philosophical Sufi theologians such as [[Ibn Arabi]] were influenced by the neoplatonic theodicy of [[Ibn Sina]].<ref name=shihadeh/> [[Al-Ghazali]] anticipated the optimistic theodicy of Leibniz in his dictum "There is nothing in possibility more wonderful than what is."<ref>{{cite encyclopedia|title=Religious Diversity, Evil, and a Variety of Theodicies |first=Michael L. |last=Peterson|encyclopedia=The Oxford Handbook of Religious Diversity|editor-first=Chad |editor-last=Meister|year=2011|page=162|url=http://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780195340136.001.0001/oxfordhb-9780195340136-e-12|url-access=subscription }}</ref> [[Fakhr al-Din al-Razi]], who represented the mainstream Sunni view, challenged Ibn Sina's analysis and argued that it merely sidesteps the real problem of evil, which is rooted in the human experience of suffering in a world that contains more pain than pleasure.<ref name=shihadeh/> === Atharī === The [[Hanbali]] scholar [[Ibn Taymiyya]], whose writings became influential in [[Wahhabism]], argued that, while God creates human acts, humans are responsible for their deeds as the agents of their acts.<ref name=hoover>{{cite encyclopedia|first=Jon|last=Hoover|title=Ḥanbalī Theology|editor-first=Sabine |editor-last=Schmidtke|encyclopedia=The Oxford Handbook of Islamic Theology|publisher=Oxford University Press|location=Oxford|year=2014|url=http://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199696703.001.0001/oxfordhb-9780199696703-e-014|url-access=subscription |page=642|doi=10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199696703.013.014 |isbn=978-0-19-969670-3 }}</ref> He held that divine creation is good from a causal standpoint, as God creates all things for wise purposes.<ref name=hoover/> Thus apparent evil is in actuality good in view of its purpose, and pure evil does not exist.<ref name=hoover/> This analysis was developed further with practical illustrations by [[Ibn al-Qayyim]].<ref name=hoover/> ==Alternatives== ===Jewish anti-theodicy=== {{Main|Holocaust theology}} In 1998, Jewish theologian [[Zachary Braiterman]] coined the term anti-theodicy in his book ''(God) After Auschwitz'' to describe Jews, both in a biblical and post-Holocaust context, whose response to the problem of evil is protest and refusal to investigate the relationship between God and suffering. An anti-theodicy acts in opposition to a theodicy and places full blame for all experience of evil onto God, but must rise from an individual's belief in and love of God. Anti-theodicy has been likened to [[Job (religious figure)|Job's]] protests in the [[Book of Job]].<ref>Marty & Taliaferro 2010, p. 17</ref> Braiterman wrote that an anti-theodicy rejects the idea that there is a meaningful relationship between God and evil or that God could be justified for the experience of evil.<ref>Gibbs & Wolfson 2002, p. 38</ref> [[File:Emmanuel Levinas.jpg|thumb|Levinas]] The [[Holocaust]] prompted a reconsideration of theodicy in some [[Jewish theology|Jewish]] circles.<ref>Pinnock 2002, p. 8</ref> French Jewish philosopher [[Emmanuel Levinas]], who had himself been a [[prisoner of war]] in Nazi Germany, declared theodicy to be "blasphemous", arguing that it is the "source of all immorality", and demanded that the project of theodicy be ended. Levinas asked whether the idea of [[moral absolutism|absolutism]] survived after the Holocaust; he proposed it did. He argued that humans are not called to justify God in the face of evil, but to attempt to live godly lives; rather than considering whether God was present during the Holocaust, the duty of humans is to build a world where goodness will prevail.<ref>Patterson & Roth 2005, pp. 189–90</ref> Professor of theology David R. Blumenthal, in his book ''Facing the Abusing God'', supports the "theology of protest", which he saw as presented in the 1979 play, ''[[The Trial of God]]''. He supports the view that survivors of the Holocaust cannot forgive God and so must protest about it. Blumenthal believes that a similar theology is presented in the Book of Job, in which Job does not question God's existence or power, but his morality and justice.<ref>Blumenthal 1993, pp. 250–51</ref> Other prominent voices in the Jewish tradition include the Nobel prize winning author Elie Wiesel and Richard L. Rubinstein in his book ''The Cunning of History''.<ref>Rubinstein, Richard L. ''The Cunning of History''.</ref> [[File:Rabbi Menachem Mendel Schneerson2 crop.jpg|thumb|Menachem Mendel Schneerson]] [[Menachem Mendel Schneerson]], the seventh Rebbe of [[Chabad|Chabad Lubavitch]], sought to elucidate how faith (or trust, {{Transliteration|he|emunah}}) in God defines the full, transcendental preconditions of anti-theodicy. Endorsing the attitude of "holy protest" found in the stories of Job and Jeremiah, but also in those of Abraham ([[Vayeira|Genesis 18]]) and Moses ([[Ki Tissa|Exodus 33]]), Rabbi Schneerson argued that a phenomenology of protest, when carried through to its logical limits, reveals a profound conviction in cosmic justice such as is first found in Abraham's question: "Will the Judge of the whole earth not do justice?" (Genesis 18:25).<ref>{{bibleverse|Genesis|18:25|JPS}}</ref> Recalling Kant's 1791 essay on the failure of all theoretical attempts in theodicy,<ref>''Über das Misslingen aller philosophischen Versuche in der Theodizee'' http://cas.uchicago.edu/workshops/germanphilosophy/files/2013/02/Kant-On-the-Miscarriage-of-all-Philosophical-Trials-at-Theodicy.pdf</ref> a viable practical theodicy is identified with [[Chabad messianism|messianism]]. This faithful anti-theodicy is worked out in a long letter of 26 April 1965 to [[Elie Wiesel]].<ref>http://www.chighel.com/opening-statement-7a/ {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150801100919/http://www.chighel.com/opening-statement-7a/ |date=2015-08-01 }} The original letter in Yiddish is found in R. Menachem Mendel Schneerson, ''Likutei Siḥot'', Vol. 33 (New York: Kehot, 1962–2001), pp. 255–60.</ref> Hannah Arendt offers notable resistance to this trend of anti-theodicy in her works ''[[The Origins of Totalitarianism]]'' and—more sensationally—in her reporting of the [[Eichmann trial]] collected in ''[[Eichmann in Jerusalem]]''. Without resorting to transcendental authority, purely by observation, Arendt arrives at a conclusion similar to Augustine's theodicy: She ascribes [[Eichmann trial|Adolf Eichmann's]] evil actions to a lack of empathic imagination and to the thoughtlessness of his conformity to norms of careerism within the [[Nazi Germany|Third Reich]]. She finds a thoughtlessness or total absence of consideration for other perspectives at the center of his behavior. The quality of this lack she describes as "[[Eichmann in Jerusalem#Banality of evil|the banality of evil]]." Arendt did not intend to propose "the banality of evil" as a technical term or fixed nomination by which to describe the void of empathic imagination she observed—it just happened to be a phrase within her description that was appropriated by the reviewing press and by other scholarly responsa. Banality is only a facet or particular quality of her vantage point looking into this emptiness. ===Christian alternatives to theodicy=== A number of Christian writers oppose theodicies. Todd Billings deems constructing theodicies to be a "destructive practice".<ref>Todd Billings, "Theodicy as a 'Lived Question': Moving Beyond a Theoretical Approach to Theodicy", http://www.luthersem.edu/ctrf/JCTR/Vol05/billings.htm {{Webarchive|url=https://web.archive.org/web/20110213041622/http://www2.luthersem.edu/ctrf/JCTR/Vol05/billings.htm |date=2011-02-13 }} Accessed 25 September 2013. About the author: http://www.westernsem.edu/about/faculty-staff/.</ref> In the same vein, [[Nick Trakakis]] observes that "theodical discourse can only add to the world's evils, not remove or illuminate them."<ref>Nick Trakakis, "Theodicy: The Solution to the Problem of Evil, or Part of the Problem?", [https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs11841-008-0063-6 Springerlink.com], accessed 19 December 2009.</ref><ref>{{cite journal |last1=Franklin |first1=James |date=2020 |title=Antitheodicy and the grading of theodicies by moral offensiveness |url=https://rdcu.be/b6cLu |journal=Sophia |volume=59 |issue= 3|pages=563–576 |doi=10.1007/s11841-020-00765-w |s2cid=225461563 |access-date=29 June 2021|hdl=1959.4/unsworks_71905 |hdl-access=free }}</ref> As an alternative to theodicy, some theologians have advocated "reflection on tragedy" as a more befitting reply to evil.<ref>Donald W. Musser and [[Joseph L. Price]], eds., ''A New Handbook of Christian Theology'' (Abingdon Press, 1992), s.v. "Tragedy."</ref> For example, Wendy Farley believes that "a desire for justice" and "anger and pity at suffering" should replace "theodicy's cool justifications of evil".<ref>Wendy Farley, ''Tragic Vision and Divine Compassion: a Contemporary Theodicy'' (Westminster John Knox Press, 1990) 12, 23.</ref> Sarah K. Pinnock opposes abstract theodicies that would legitimize evil and suffering. However, she endorses theodicy discussions in which people ponder God, evil, and suffering from a practical faith perspective.<ref>Sarah Katherine Pinnock, ''Beyond Theodicy'' (SUNY Press, 2002), 135, 141.</ref> [[File:David Bentley Hart 3 Nov 2022 Interview cropped.png|thumb|David Bentley Hart]] In an essay for [[The Hedgehog Review]], Eugene McCarraher called [[David Bentley Hart]]'s 2005 book ''[[The Doors of the Sea]]'' "a ferocious attack on theodicy in the wake of the previous year's tsunami" (referring to the [[2004 Indian Ocean earthquake and tsunami|2004 tsunami in the Indian Ocean]]).<ref>{{citation | publisher=[[The Hedgehog Review]] |title=A Divine Comedy |url=https://hedgehogreview.com/issues/america-on-the-brink/articles/a-divine-comedy}}</ref> As Hart says on page 58 of the book: "The principal task of theodicy is to explain why paradise is not a logical possibility." Hart's refusal to concede that theodicy has any positive capacity to explain the purpose of evil is in line with many Greek church fathers. For example, see Eric D. Perl's ''Theophany: The Neoplatonic Philosophy of Dionysius the Areopagite'': {{Blockquote |text=[[Dionysius the Areopagite|Dionysius]]' ...refusal to assign a cause to evil, then, marks not the failure but the success of his treatment of the problem. To explain evil, to attribute a cause to it, would necessarily be to explain it away, to deny that evil is genuinely evil at all. For to explain something is to show how it is in some way good. ...Only by not explaining evil, by insisting rather on its radical causelessness, its unintelligibility, can we take evil seriously as evil. This is why most "theodicies" fail precisely insofar as they succeed. To the extent that they satisfactorily account for or make sense of evil, they tacitly or expressly deny that it is evil and show that it is in fact good. Dionysius' treatment of evil, on the other hand, succeeds by failing, recognizing that the sheer negativity that is evil must be uncaused and hence inexplicable, for otherwise it would not be negativity and would not be evil. It has been wisely remarked that any satisfactory account of evil must enable us to retain our outrage at it. Most theodicies fail this test, for in supposedly allowing us to understand evil they justify it and thus take away our outrage. For Dionysius, however, evil remains outrageous precisely because it is irrational, because there is no reason, no justification for it. The privation theory of evil, expressed in a radical form by Dionysius, is not a shallow disregard or denial of the evident evils in the world. It means rather that, confronted with the evils in the world, we can only say that for no reason, and therefore outrageously, the world as we find it does not perfectly love God, the Good, the sole end of all love. And since the Good is the principle of intelligibility and hence of being, to the extent that anything fails to partake of that principle it is deficient in being. The recognition of evils in the world and in ourselves is the recognition that the world and ourselves, as we find them, are less than fully existent because we do not perfectly love God, the Good. }} [[Karl Barth]] viewed the evil of human suffering as ultimately in the "control of [[divine providence]]".<ref>Karl Barth, ''Church Dogmatics'' (T & T Clark, 1957), IV-1, 246.</ref> Given this view, Barth deemed it impossible for humans to devise a theodicy that establishes "the idea of the goodness of God".<ref>Barth, ''Church Dogmatics'', III-1, 368.</ref> For Barth, only the [[Crucifixion of Jesus|crucifixion]] could establish the goodness of God. In the crucifixion, God bears and suffers what humanity suffers.<ref>Barth, ''Church Dogmatics'', II-2, 165.</ref> This suffering by God Himself makes human theodicies anticlimactic.<ref>Barth, ''Church Dogmatics'', IV-1, 246.</ref> Barth found a "twofold justification" in the crucifixion:<ref>Barth, ''Church Dogmatics'', II-2, 223.</ref> the [[Justification (theology)|justification of sinful humanity]] and "the justification in which God justifies Himself".<ref>Barth, ''Church Dogmatics'', IV-1, 564.</ref> [[Christian Science]] offers a solution to the problem by denying that evil ultimately exists.<ref>Ben Dupre, "The Problem of Evil", 50 Philosophy Ideas You Really Need to Know, London, Quercus, 2007, p. 166: "Denying that there is ultimately any such thing as evil, as advocated by Christian Scientists, solves the problem at a stroke, but such a remedy is too hard for most to swallow."</ref><ref>Whale, J. S. The Christian answer to the problem of evil. 1948</ref> [[Mary Baker Eddy]] and [[Mark Twain]] had some contrasting views on theodicy and suffering, which are well-described by [[Stephen Gottschalk]].<ref>"Rolling Away the Stone: Mary Baker Eddy's Challenge to Materialism" (Indiana University Press, 2006) 83, 123, etc.</ref> [[Redemptive suffering]], based in [[Pope John Paul II]]'s [[theology of the body]], embraces suffering as having value in and of itself.<ref name="Adrian J. Reimers">{{cite news|last=Reimers|first=Adrian J.|title=Human Suffering and Jon Paul II's Theology of the Body|url=https://www3.nd.edu/~areimers/Suffering-JPII-expanded.htm|access-date=2017-08-08|archive-date=2014-12-28|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20141228055449/http://www3.nd.edu/~areimers/Suffering-JPII-expanded.htm|url-status=dead}}</ref><ref>{{cite web|url=http://www.catholicprimer.org/papal/theology_of_the_body.pdf|title=Catholicprimer.org|website=www.catholicprimer.org|access-date=2017-08-08|archive-date=2017-08-08|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20170808141833/http://catholicprimer.org/papal/theology_of_the_body.pdf|url-status=dead}}</ref> [[Eleonore Stump]] in ''Wandering in Darkness'' uses psychology, narrative and exegesis to demonstrate that redemptive suffering, as found in Thomistic theodicy, can constitute a consistent and cogent defence for the problem of suffering.<ref name="Eleonore Stump">{{cite book|last=Stump|first=Eleonore|title=Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering| publisher=Oxford University Press| location=N.Y. New York|year=2010|isbn=978-0-19-927742-1}}</ref> ===Free-will defense=== {{See also|Theodicy and the Bible#Bible and free-will theodicy}} As an alternative to a theodicy, a defense may be offered as a response to the problem of evil. A defense attempts to show that God's existence is not made logically impossible by the existence of evil; it does not need to be true or plausible, merely logically possible. American philosopher [[Alvin Plantinga]] offers [[Alvin Plantinga's free-will defense|a free-will defense]] which argues that human [[free will]] sufficiently explains the existence of evil while maintaining that God's existence remains logically possible.<ref>McGrath 1995, p. 193</ref> He argues that, if God's existence and the existence of evil are to be logically inconsistent, a premise must be provided which, if true, would make them inconsistent; as none has been provided, the existence of God and evil must be consistent. Free will furthers this argument by providing a premise which, in conjunction with the existence of evil, entails that God's existence remains consistent.<ref>Plantinga & Sennett 1998, pp. 22–24</ref> Opponents have argued this defense is discredited by the existence of non-human related evil such as droughts, tsunamis and malaria.<ref name="Ehrman2009">{{cite book|author=Bart D. Ehrman|title=God's Problem: How the Bible Fails to Answer Our Most Important Question – Why We Suffer|url=https://archive.org/details/godsproblemhowbi00ehrm|url-access=registration|date=13 October 2009|publisher=HarperCollins|isbn=978-0-06-174440-2|page=[https://archive.org/details/godsproblemhowbi00ehrm/page/12 12]}}</ref> In his recent book, ''Evil, Sin and Christian Theism'' (2022), [[Andrew Loke]] develops a Big Picture free-will defense argument arguing that God's justification for allowing suffering is not mainly based on an argument from future benefits but on the very nature of love which involves "allowing humans to exercise their free will in morally significant ways."<ref>{{cite book |last1=Loke |first1=Andrew Ter Ern |title=Evil, Sin and Christian Theism |date=2022 |publisher=Routledge |page=203}}</ref> He employs the Big Picture approach in which "Christian theism provides the big picture and uses a combination of theodicies" in defense of a moderate version of skeptical theism.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Loke |first1=Andrew Ter Ern |title=Evil, Sin and Christian Theism |date=2022 |publisher=Routledge |page=5}}</ref> The Big Picture approach, according to him, helps to put the problem of evil and suffering in perspective of the bigger picture that answers the Big Questions of a worldview such as "What is the greatest good? What is the meaning of life? Where do I come from? Where am I going?" He argues that Christian theism provides the best overall consistent answers to these questions: "the greatest good is to have a right relationship with God, the source of all good. The meaning of life...is to live our lives for the greatest good;...to glorify God and enjoy him..."<ref name="loke 13">{{cite book |last1=Loke |first1=Andrew Ter Ern |title=Evil, Sin and Christian Theism |date=2022 |publisher=Routledge |page=13}}</ref> The bigger picture of a just, all-powerful, and loving God who will ultimately defeat evil serves as the backdrop against which all temporal suffering can obtain a meaningful understanding.<ref name="loke 13"/> ===Cosmodicy and anthropodicy=== <!--'Cosmodicy' and 'Anthropodicy' redirect here--> A '''cosmodicy'''<!--boldface per WP:R#PLA--> attempts to justify the fundamental goodness of the [[universe]] in the face of [[evil]], and an '''anthropodicy'''<!--boldface per WP:R#PLA--> attempts to justify the fundamental goodness of [[human nature]] in the face of the evils produced by humans.<ref>Carsten Meiner, Kristin Veel, eds., ''The Cultural Life of Catastrophes and Crises'' (Walter de Gruyter, 2012), 243.</ref> Considering the relationship between theodicy and cosmodicy, {{ill|Johannes van der Ven|de|Johannes A. van der Ven}} argued that the choice between theodicy and cosmodicy is a false dilemma.<ref>Van der Ven 1989, p. 205</ref> Philip E. Devenish proposed what he described as "a nuanced view in which theodicy and cosmodicy are rendered complementary, rather than alternative concepts".<ref>Devenish 1992, pp. 5–23</ref> Theologian J. Matthew Ashley described the relationship between theodicy, cosmodicy and anthropodicy: {{blockquote|In classical terms, this is to broach the problem of theodicy: how to think about God in the face of the presence of suffering in God's creation. After God's dethronement as the subject of history, the question rebounds to the new subject of history: the human being. As a consequence, theodicy becomes anthropodicy – justifications of our faith in humanity as the subject of history, in the face of the suffering that is so inextricably woven into the history that humanity makes.<ref>Ashley 2010, pp. 870–902</ref>}} ==== Essential kenosis ==== Essential [[kenosis]] is a form of [[process theology]] (related to "[[open theism]]") that allows one to affirm that God is almighty, while simultaneously affirming that God cannot prevent genuine evil. Because out of love God necessarily gives [[freedom]], [[Agency (philosophy)|agency]], [[self-organization]], natural processes, and law-like regularities to creation, God cannot override, withdraw, or fail to provide such capacities. Consequently, God is not culpable for failing to prevent genuine evil. The work of [[Thomas Jay Oord]] explains this view most fully.<ref>{{Cite book|title = The Uncontrolling Love of God: An Open and Relational Account of Providence|publisher = IVP Academic|date = 2015-12-06|isbn = 978-0-8308-4084-7|language = en|first = Thomas Jay|last = Oord}}</ref><ref>{{Cite book|title = The Nature of Love: A Theology|url = https://www.amazon.com/Nature-Love-Dr-Thomas-Oord-ebook/dp/B003UD7QQ0/ref=sr_1_1?s=books&ie=UTF8&qid=1447257773&sr=1-1&keywords=nature+of+love+oord|publisher = Chalice Press|date = 2010-04-10|language = en|first = Thomas|last = Oord}}</ref> {{ill|Gijsbert van den Brink|nl}} effectively refutes any view which says God has restricted his power because of his love saying it creates a "metaphysical dualism", and it would not alleviate God's responsibility for evil because God could have prevented evil by not restricting himself. Van den Brink goes on to elaborate an explanation of power and love within the Trinitarian view which equates power and love, and what he calls "the power of love" as representative of God's involvement in the struggle against evil.<ref name="Gijsbert van den Brink">{{cite book| last=van den Brink| first=Gijsbert| title=Almighty God: A Study on the Doctrine of Divine Omnipotence| publisher=Kok Pharos publishing House| location=Kampen, the Netherlands|year=1993|pages=263–73}}</ref> ==See also== {{Portal|Religion}} * [[Augustinian theodicy]] * [[Dystheism]] * [[Global justice]] * [[Irenaean theodicy]] * [[Misotheism]] * [[Problem of hell]] * [[Theodicy and the Bible]] * [[Problem of evil in Hinduism|Theodicy in Hinduism]] * [[Utilitarianism]] == Citations == {{Reflist}} == General and cited references == * {{Cite book |title=Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God |publisher=Cornell University Press |year=1999 |author=Adams, Marilyn McCord |isbn=978-0-80148-686-9}} * {{Cite journal |title=Reading the universe story theologically: the contribution of a biblical narrative imagination |author=Ashley, J. Matthew |journal=Theological Studies |year=2010 |volume=71 |issue=4|pages=870–902 |doi=10.1177/004056391007100405 |s2cid=55990053 }} * Assman, Jan (2001). ''The Search for God in Ancient Egypt'' trans. David Lorton. Cornell University Press * Birnbaum, David (1989). ''God and Evil''. Ktav Publishing House * {{Cite book |title=Facing the Abusing God: A Theology of Protest |publisher=Westminster John Knox Press |year=1993 |author=Blumenthal, David R. |isbn=978-0-66425-464-3}} * {{Cite book |title=The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |year=2002 |last1=Bunnin |first1=Nicholas |last2=Tsui James |first2=E. P. |isbn=978-0-631-21908-8}} * {{Cite book |title=John Hick: a critical introduction and reflection |publisher=Ashgate Publishing |year=2003 |author=Cheetham, David |isbn=978-0-7546-1599-6}} * {{Cite book |title=Encountering evil: live options in theodicy |publisher=Westminster John Knox Press |author=Davis, Stephen T. |year=2001 |isbn=978-0-664-22251-2}} * {{Cite journal |title=Theodicy and Cosmodicy: The Contribution of Neoclassical Theism |author=Devenish, Philip E. |journal=Journal of Empirical Theology |year=1992 |volume=4}} * {{Cite book |title=God's Problem:How the Bible Fails to Answer Our Most Important Question – Why We Suffer |author=Ehrman, Bart D. |publisher=HarperCollins Publishers |year=2008 |isbn=978-0-06-117397-4 |url-access=registration |url=https://archive.org/details/godsproblemhowbi00ehrm }} * {{Cite book |title=Evil & the Evidence For God: The Challenge of John Hick's Theodicy |publisher=Temple University Press |year=1995 |author=Geiviett, R. Douglas |isbn=978-1-56639-397-3}} * Inati, Shams C. (2000). ''[https://books.google.com/books?id=2EfMiwC6SCsC The Problem of Evil: Ibn Sînâ's Theodicy]''. {{ISBN|1-58684-006-1}}. Global Academic Publishing, Binghamton University, New York. * {{Cite book |title=Suffering religion |publisher=Psychology Press |year=2002 |last1=Gibbs |first1=Robert |last2=Wolfson |first2=Elliot |isbn=978-0-415-26612-3}} * {{Cite book |title=Swinburne's hell and Hick's universalism: are we free to reject God? |publisher=Ashgate Publishing |year=2003 |author=Hall, Lindsey |isbn=978-0-7546-3400-3}} * {{Cite book |title=Religions of the Ancient World: A Guide |publisher=Harvard University Press |year=2004 |author=Johnston, Sarah Iles |isbn=978-0-674-01517-3}} * {{Cite book |title=Theodicy |author=Leibniz, Gottfried |year=1710}} * {{Cite book |title=Evil, Sin and Christian Theism |author=Loke, Andrew Ter Ern |publisher=Routledge |year=2022}} * {{Cite book |title=Dictionary of Philosophy of Religion |publisher=Continuum International Publishing Group |year=2010 |last1=Marty |first1=Marty |last2=Taliaferro |first2=Charles |isbn=978-1-4411-1197-5}} * {{Cite book |title=The Blackwell encyclopedia of modern Christian thought |publisher=Wiley-Blackwell |year=1995 |author=McGrath, Alister |isbn=978-0-631-19896-3}} * Neiman, Susan. ''Evil in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy'', 2002, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Revised edition, 2015. * Oord, Thomas Jay (2015), ''The Uncontrolling Love of God''. Intervarsity Academic. {{ISBN|978-0-8308-4084-7}} * {{Cite book |title=Fire in the ashes: God, evil, and the Holocaust |publisher=University of Washington Press |year=2005 |last1=Patterson |first1=David |last2=Roth |first2=John |isbn=978-0-295-98547-3}} * {{Cite book |title=Beyond theodicy: Jewish and Christian continental thinkers respond to the Holocaust |publisher=SUNY Press |year=2002 |author=Pinnock, Sarah Katherine |isbn=978-0-7914-5523-4}} * {{Cite book |title=The analytic theist: an Alvin Plantinga reader|publisher=Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing |year=1998|last1=Plantinga |first1=Alvin |last2=Sennett |first2=James |isbn=978-0-8028-4229-9}} * {{Cite web |title=Theorising Theodicy in the Study of Religion |publisher=University of Chicago Divinity School |author=Scott, Mark S. M. |year=2009 |url=https://divinity.uchicago.edu/sites/default/files/imce/pdfs/webforum/112009/Theorizing%20Theodicy%20final.pdf |access-date=2015-11-21 |archive-date=2015-09-12 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20150912004231/http://divinity.uchicago.edu/sites/default/files/imce/pdfs/webforum/112009/Theorizing%20Theodicy%20final.pdf |url-status=dead }} * {{Cite book |title=A primal perspective on the philosophy of religion |publisher=Springer |author=Sharma, Arvind |year=2006 |isbn=978-1-4020-5013-8}} * {{Cite book |title=The Tao is Silent|publisher=Harper |author=Smullyan, Raymond |year=1977|isbn=978-0-06-067469-4}} * {{Cite book |title=Philosophy of religion: the big questions |publisher=Wiley-Blackwell |author=Stump, Eleonore |year=1999 |isbn=978-0-631-20604-0}} * {{Cite book |title=A philosophy of evil |publisher=Dalkey Archive Press |year=2010 |isbn=978-1-56478-571-8 |first1= Lars Fr. H. |last1=Svendsen |first2=Kerri A. |last2=Pierce}} * {{Cite book |title=The Max Weber Dictionary: Key Words and Central Concepts |publisher=Stanford University Press |year=2005 |author=Swedberg, Richard |isbn=978-0-80475-095-0}} * {{Cite journal |title=Theodicy or cosmodicy: a false dilemma? |author=Van der Ven, Johannes A. |journal=Journal of Empirical Theology |year=1989 |volume=2 |issue=1}} * {{Cite journal |last=Watson |first=Simon R. |title= God in Creation: A Consideration of Natural Selection as the Sacrificial Means of a Free Creation |journal= Studies in Religion/Sciences Religieuses |year=2019 |volume=48 |number=2 |pages=216–236|doi=10.1177/0008429819830356 |s2cid=202271434 }} * {{Cite journal |last=Woo |first=B. Hoon |title= Is God the Author of Sin? – Jonathan Edwards's Theodicy |journal= [[Puritan Reformed Journal]] |year=2014 |volume=6 |number=1 |url=https://www.academia.edu/5972518 |pages=98–123}} * {{Cite book |title=Peter Berger and the Study of Religion |publisher=Routledge |year=2001 |author=Woodhead, Linda |isbn=978-0-41521-532-9}} ==External links== {{Wikiquote}} {{Commons category}} * {{SEP|theodicies|Theodicies|Laura W. Ekstrom}} * {{SEP|evil|The Problem of Evil|Michael Tooley}} * Brown, Paterson. [https://web.archive.org/web/20101227173500/http://metalog.org/files/tpb/rel.m.html "Religious Morality"], ''Mind'', 1963. * Brown, Paterson. [https://web.archive.org/web/20101227180203/http://metalog.org/files/tpb/reply.html "Religious Morality: A Reply to Flew and Campbell"], ''Mind'', 1964. * Brown, Paterson. [https://web.archive.org/web/20101125212955/http://metalog.org/files/tpb/god.g.html "God and the Good"], ''Religious Studies'', 1967. * {{Catholic Encyclopedia|no-icon=1|prescript=|wstitle=Theodicy}} ** [http://www.newadvent.org/cathen/14569a.htm Theodicy] at New Advent * [https://www.christians.eu/why-does-god-allow-it/ Why Does God Allow It?] Article discussing men's responsibility on the one hand and his powerlessness regarding natural disasters on the other hand. {{Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz}} {{Hamartiology}} {{Philosophy of religion}} {{Authority control}} [[Category:Theodicy| ]] [[Category:1710s neologisms]] [[Category:Christian apologetics]] [[Category:God in Christianity]] [[Category:Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz]] [[Category:Problem of evil]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:'"
(
edit
)
Template:Authority control
(
edit
)
Template:Bibleverse
(
edit
)
Template:Blockquote
(
edit
)
Template:By whom
(
edit
)
Template:C.
(
edit
)
Template:Catholic Encyclopedia
(
edit
)
Template:Circa
(
edit
)
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:Citation needed
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite dictionary
(
edit
)
Template:Cite encyclopedia
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite news
(
edit
)
Template:Cite thesis
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Clarify
(
edit
)
Template:Comma separated entries
(
edit
)
Template:Commons category
(
edit
)
Template:Error
(
edit
)
Template:Full citation needed
(
edit
)
Template:God
(
edit
)
Template:Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
(
edit
)
Template:Hamartiology
(
edit
)
Template:IPAc-en
(
edit
)
Template:ISBN
(
edit
)
Template:Ill
(
edit
)
Template:Lang
(
edit
)
Template:Langx
(
edit
)
Template:Main
(
edit
)
Template:Main other
(
edit
)
Template:Multiple issues
(
edit
)
Template:Non sequitur
(
edit
)
Template:Ordered list
(
edit
)
Template:Original research inline
(
edit
)
Template:Philosophy of religion
(
edit
)
Template:Philosophy of religion sidebar
(
edit
)
Template:Portal
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Rp
(
edit
)
Template:SEP
(
edit
)
Template:See also
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Sister project
(
edit
)
Template:Theodicy
(
edit
)
Template:Transliteration
(
edit
)
Template:Use dmy dates
(
edit
)
Template:Webarchive
(
edit
)
Template:Wikiquote
(
edit
)