Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Unity of the proposition
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{more footnotes|date=December 2021}} In [[philosophy]], the '''unity of the [[proposition]]''' is the problem of explaining how a sentence in the [[indicative mood]] expresses more than just what a list of [[proper name]]s expresses. == History == The problem was discussed under this name by [[Bertrand Russell]], but can be traced back to [[Plato]]. In Plato's ''[[Sophist_(dialogue)|Sophist]]'', the simplest kind of sentence consists of just a proper name and a [[Universality (philosophy)|universal]] [[terminology|term]] (i.e. a [[predicate (grammar)|predicate]]). The name refers to or picks out some [[individual]] [[object (philosophy)|object]], and the predicate then says something about that individual. The difficulty is to explain how the predicate does this. If, as Plato thinks,<ref>{{cite SEP |last=Silverman |first=Allan |title=Plato's Middle Period Metaphysics and Epistemology |date=14 July 2014 |url=http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato-metaphysics/ |url-id=plato-metaphysics}}</ref> the predicate is the name of some universal [[concept]] or form, how do we explain how the sentence comes to be [[Truth|true]] or false? If, for example, "[[Socrates]] is wise" consists of just a name for Socrates, and a name for the universal concept of [[Wisdom]], how could the sentence be true ''or'' false? In either case, the "Socrates" [[Sign (linguistics)|signifies]] Socrates, and the predicate signifies Wisdom. But the sentence ''[[Logical assertion|asserts]]'' that Socrates is wise. The assertion of wisdom must consist in the assertion of some relation between Socrates and Wisdom. What is this relation? The problem was discussed much later by [[F. H. Bradley|Francis Bradley]]. If we assume that a sentence consists of two objects and a relation that connects them, and we represent this by three names, say John, loving, Mary, how do we express the fact that John loves Mary? For "John", "loving" and "Mary" would name the objects they do, even if this were not a fact. This is known as [[Bradley's regress]]. == Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein == The problem became significant in the early development of [[set theory]]. Set membership is a [[Formal set theory|formal]] [[Knowledge representation|representation]] of the relation between the two parts of the [[proposition]], and there are certain philosophical problems connected with this, as [[Frege]] realised when he investigated the distinction between [[concept and object]]. Assume that "Shergar is a horse" analyses into what "Shergar" names (an "Object", according to Frege), and what "is a horse" names (a "Concept"). Objects are fundamentally different from concepts, otherwise we get the problem of the unity of the proposition. A predicate cannot function as the [[subject (grammar)|subject]] of a sentence. But what are we doing when we talk about the concept ''is a horse''? Aren't we using the expression "the concept ''is a horse''", and isn't that a subject expression, which refers (on Frege's account) to an Object? Yes, says Frege, and on that account the concept ''is a horse'' is not a concept at all. This is a [[dogma]] that even Frege's most faithful followers found difficult to swallow. The difficulty was discussed in detail in ''[[Principia Mathematica|The Principles of Mathematics]]'' by Russell, who saw no resolution. :There appears to be an ultimate notion of assertion, given by the verb, which is lost as soon as we substitute a verbal noun, and is lost when the proposition in question is made the subject of some other proposition. ...Thus the contradiction which was to have been avoided, of an entity which cannot be made a logical subject, appears to have here become inevitable. This difficulty, which seems to be inherent in the very nature of truth and falsehood, is one with which I do not know how to deal with satisfactorily. ...I therefore leave this question to the [[logic]]ians with the above brief indication of a difficulty. (§ 52) Consider e.g. "A differs from B". The constituents of this proposition are simply A, difference and B. The proposition relates A and B, using the words "is ... from" in "A is different from B". But if we represent this contribution by words for relations, as e.g. "A <R> difference <R> B" we are back to a list of terms, we are essentially back at Bradley's regress. : A proposition, in fact, is essentially a ''unity'', and when analysis has destroyed the unity, no enumeration of constituents will restore the proposition. The verb, when used as a verb, embodies the unity of the proposition, and is thus distinguishable from the verb considered as a term, though I do not know how to give a clear account of the distinction. (§ 52) [[Ludwig Wittgenstein]] addresses the problem early on in the ''[[Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus]]''. In section 2.01 he claims that "states of affairs" are combinations of objects. In section 2.03 he explains that nothing is needed to link the objects, since the objects ''hang together''. The arrangement of words that in the sentence corresponds to the arrangement or ''structure'' of objects in the [[State of affairs (philosophy)|state of affairs]] expressed by the sentence. This is the so-called [[Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus#Picture theory|picture theory of the proposition]]. == See also == *[[Bradley's regress]] *[[Third man argument]] ==References == {{reflist}} == Bibliography == {{refbegin}} * Candlish, S., "The Unity of the Proposition and Russell’s Theories of Judgment", in ''Bertrand Russell and the Origins of Analytical Philosophy'', ed. Monk & Palmer (Bristol 1996). * Davidson, D., ''Truth and Predication'', (MIT Press 2005). * Gaskin, R., ''The Unity of the Proposition'', (Oxford 2008). * Gibson, M., ''From Naming to Saying. The Unity of the Proposition'', (Oxford 2004). * Joachim, H., ''The Nature of Truth'', (Oxford 1906) * Linsky L., "The Unity of the Proposition", ''Journal of the History of Philosophy'' 1992, 30. * Russell, B., ''The Principles of Mathematics'', (Oxford 1903). {{refend}} ==External links== * [http://stanford.library.usyd.edu.au/entries/truth-identity/ The Identity Theory of Truth] * [http://www.liv.ac.uk/~gaskin/proposition.html The Nature and Unity of the Proposition] * [https://web.archive.org/web/20060411172041/http://uk.geocities.com/frege@btinternet.com/cantor/joachim.htm Joachim's The Nature of Truth - contains a discussion of the problem] * [https://web.archive.org/web/20060423091434/http://uk.geocities.com/frege@btinternet.com/cantor/pofmathematics.htm Selection from Russell including a discussion of the problem] [[Category:Philosophy of language]] [[Category:Propositions]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Cite SEP
(
edit
)
Template:More footnotes
(
edit
)
Template:Refbegin
(
edit
)
Template:Refend
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)