Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Universal prescriptivism
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Meta-ethical view}} {{distinguish|Linguistic prescription}} {{original research|date=January 2012}} <!-- Image with inadequate rationale removed: [[File:RMHare.jpg|thumb|right|R. M. Hare]] --> '''Universal prescriptivism''' (often simply called '''prescriptivism''') is the [[meta-ethics|meta-ethical]] view that claims that, rather than expressing [[proposition]]s, ethical [[Sentence (linguistics)|sentence]]s function similarly to [[Imperative mood|imperative]]s which are [[universalizability|universalizable]]—whoever makes a moral judgment is committed to the same judgment in any situation where the same relevant facts pertain.<ref>{{Cite web|title=Ethics - Existentialism|url=https://www.britannica.com/topic/ethics-philosophy|website=Encyclopedia Britannica|language=en|access-date=2020-05-28}}</ref><ref>{{Cite journal|last=Dahl|first=Norman O.|date=1987|title=A Prognosis for Universal Prescriptivism|journal=Philosophical Studies|volume=51|issue=3|pages=383–424|doi=10.1007/BF00354045|jstor=4319897|issn=0031-8116}}</ref> This makes prescriptivism a [[moral universalism|universalist]] form of [[non-cognitivism]]. Prescriptivism stands in opposition to other forms of non-cognitivism (such as [[emotivism]] and [[quasi-realism]]), as well as to all forms of [[Cognitivism (ethics)|cognitivism]] (including both [[moral realism]] and [[ethical subjectivism]]).<ref>{{Cite journal |last=van Roojen |first=Mark |date=2004-01-23 |title=Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/moral-cognitivism/}}</ref> Since prescriptivism was introduced by philosopher [[R. M. Hare]] in his 1952 book ''The Language of Morals'', it has been compared to emotivism and to the [[categorical imperative]] of [[Immanuel Kant]].<ref>Brandt, ''Theory'', 221: "[''The Language of Morals''] by R. M. Hare has proposed a view, otherwise very similar to the emotive theory, with modifications ..."</ref><ref>Brandt, ''Theory'', 224: "Hare's [universalizability] proposal is reminiscent of Kant's view that an act is morally permissible [[if and only if]] the maxim in terms of which the agent thinks of it could possibly serve as a universal rule of conduct, and if the agent is prepared to accept it as such."</ref> Unlike Kant, however, Hare does not invoke [[universalizability]] as a test of moral permissibility. Instead, he sees it as a consistency requirement that is built into the logic of moral language and helps to make moral thinking a rational enterprise. ==What prescriptivists claim== Hare originally proposed prescriptivism as a kind of amendment to emotivism.<ref>Warnock, G. J., ''Contemporary Moral'' ''Philosophy''. London: Macmillan, 1967, p. 30.</ref> Like emotivists, Hare believes that moral discourse is not primarily informative or fact-stating. But whereas emotivists claim that moral language is mainly intended to express feelings or to influence behavior, Hare believes that the central purpose of moral talk is to guide behavior by telling someone what to do. Its main purpose is to “prescribe” (recommend) a certain act, not to get someone to do that act or to express one's personal feelings or attitudes.<ref>Norman, Richard. ''The Moral Philosophers: An Introduction to Ethics'', 2nd ed. New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 166-67.</ref> To illustrate the prescriptivist view, consider the moral sentence, “Suicide is wrong.” According to [[moral realism]], such a sentence claims there to be some objective property of “wrongness” associated with the act of suicide. According to some versions of [[emotivism]], such a sentence merely expresses an attitude of the speaker; it only means something like “Boo on suicide!”, but according to prescriptivism, the statement “Suicide is wrong” means something more like “Do not commit suicide.”. What it expresses is thus not primarily a description or an emotion, but an ''imperative''. General value terms like “good”, “bad”, “right”, “wrong” and “ought” usually also have [[Descriptivist theory of names|descriptive]] and emotive meanings, but these are not their primary meanings according to prescriptivists. ==Criticisms== Prescriptivism has faced extensive criticism and currently has few adherents.<ref>Price, Anthony, "Richard Mervyn Hare", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2014 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/hare/>.</ref> Ethicists commonly dispute Hare's assertion that moral language lacks informativeness, challenging the idea that the primary purpose of moral discourse is not to convey moral truths or facts.<ref>Feldman, Fred. ''Introductory Ethics''. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall, 1978, pp. 246-47.</ref> Hare's argument that offering guidance always constitutes the primary goal of moral discourse is also questioned by numerous critics.<ref>Feldman, ''ibid''., p. 247; Warnock, ''Contemporary Moral Philosophy'', p. 35.</ref> Some critics observe that Hare seems to presume moral language is exclusively employed in discussions, debates, or commands, where one person instructs another or others on what to do. This perspective, it is argued, overlooks the broader usage of moral talk as a "language-game" serving diverse purposes. Lastly, critics contend that prescriptivism contradicts the common-sense differentiation between good and bad reasons for holding moral beliefs.<ref>Kerner, George C. ''The Revolution in Ethical Theory''. New York: Oxford, 1966, pp. 192-96; Feldman, ''Introductory'' ''Ethics'', pp. 246-47.</ref> Hare's stance suggests that a racist "fanatic" advocating the deportation of all minority-group members, while maintaining consistency (even if the racist is a member of the minority group), cannot be criticized for either irrationality or falsehood.<ref>Hare, R. M. ''Freedom and Reason''. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1963, p. 220.</ref> Kerner argues that, for Hare, morality fundamentally involves non-rational choice and commitment.<ref>Kerner, ''The Revolution'' ''in Ethical Theory'', p. 193.</ref> However, critics of Hare argue that reason should and does play a more substantial role in ethics than he acknowledges. == See also == * [[Non-cognitivism]] ==Notes== {{reflist}} ==References== * {{cite book |last=Brandt |first=Richard |author-link=Richard Brandt |title=''Ethical Theory'' |url=https://archive.org/details/ethicaltheorypro0000bran |url-access=registration |year=1959 |location=[[Englewood Cliffs]] |publisher=[[Prentice Hall]] |chapter=Noncognitivism: The Job of Ethical Sentences Is Not to State Facts |lccn=59010075 }} ==External links== * [http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-cognitivism/ Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism] in the [[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] * [http://universalprescriptivism.wordpress.com Universal Prescriptivism FAQ] {{Ethics}} [[Category:Metaethics]] [[Category:Ethical theories]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Distinguish
(
edit
)
Template:Ethics
(
edit
)
Template:Original research
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)