Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Unobservable
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Entity not directly observable by humans}} An '''unobservable''' (also called '''impalpable''') is an [[wikt:entity|entity]] whose existence, nature, properties, qualities or relations are not directly [[perception|observable]] by humans. In [[philosophy of science]], typical examples of "unobservables" are the [[gravity|force of gravity]], [[causality|causation]] and [[belief]]s or [[Motivation|desires]].<ref>[[Jerry Fodor|Fodor, J. A.]], ''Psychosemantics: The Problem of Meaning in the Philosophy of Mind'' ([[Cambridge, MA]] / [[London]]: [[MIT Press]], 1989), [https://books.google.com/books?id=3yoTDgAAQBAJ&lpg=PP1&hl=de&pg=PA7&redir_esc=y#v=onepage&q&f=false p. 7].</ref>{{rp|7}}<ref>{{cite book|last1=Dijk|first1=Bram van|title=Constructive Empiricism in the Social Sciences|date=2018|publisher=Utrecht University|page=54|url=http://dspace.library.uu.nl/handle/1874/366525}}</ref> The distinction between ''observable'' and ''unobservable'' plays a central role in [[Immanuel Kant]]'s distinction between [[noumenon|noumena]] and [[phenomenon|phenomena]] as well as in [[John Locke]]'s distinction between [[Primary/secondary quality distinction|primary and secondary qualities]]. There is considerable disagreement about which objects should be classified as unobservable, for example, whether bacteria studied using microscopes or positrons studied using cloud chambers count as unobservable. Different notions of unobservability have been formulated corresponding to different types of obstacles to their observation. == Kant on noumena == The distinction between "observable" and "unobservable" is similar to [[Immanuel Kant]]'s distinction between [[noumenon|noumena]] and [[phenomenon|phenomena]]. Noumena are the [[thing-in-itself|things-in-themselves]], i.e., raw things in their necessarily unknowable state,<ref>[[Stephen Palmquist|Palmquist, S. R.]], "The Radical Unknowability of Kant's 'Thing in Itself'", [[Cogito (magazine)|''Cogito'']] 3:2 (March 1985), pp. 101-115; reprinted as Appendix V of [https://staffweb.hkbu.edu.hk/ppp/ksp1/ Kant's System of Perspectives] ([[Lanham, Maryland|Lanham, MD]]: [[University Press of America]], 1993).</ref> before they pass through the formalizing apparatus of the senses and the mind in order to become perceived objects, which he refers to as "phenomena". According to Kant, humans can never know noumena; all that humans know is the phenomena. == Locke on primary and secondary qualities == Kant's distinction is similar to [[John Locke]]'s distinction between [[Primary/secondary quality distinction|primary and secondary qualities]]. Secondary qualities are what humans perceive such as redness, chirping, heat, mustiness or sweetness. Primary qualities would be the actual qualities of the things themselves which give rise to the secondary qualities which humans perceive. == Philosophy of science == The [[ontology|ontological nature]] and [[epistemology|epistemological]] issues concerning unobservables are central topics in philosophy of science. The theory that unobservables posited by scientific theories exist is referred to as [[scientific realism]]. It contrasts with [[instrumentalism]], which asserts that we should withhold [[ontological commitment]]s to unobservables even though it is useful for scientific theories to refer to them. The notion of observability plays a central role in [[constructive empiricism]]. According to [[Bas van Fraassen]], the goal of scientific theories is not truth about all entities but only truth about all observable entities.<ref>{{cite book |last1=Monton |first1=Bradley |last2=Mohler |first2=Chad |author1-link=:fi:Bradley Monton|title=Constructive Empiricism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/constructive-empiricism/|publisher=[[Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy]] (Summer 2017 Edition)|date=2017 }}</ref> If a theory is true in this restricted sense, it is called an ''empirically adequate'' theory. Van Fraassen characterizes observability counterfactually: "X is observable if there are circumstances which are such that, if X is present to us under those circumstances, then we observe it".<ref name="Fraassen">{{cite book |last=van Fraassen |first=Bas |authorlink=Bas van Fraassen|title=The Scientific Image |publisher=Oxford University Press |date=1980 |pages=16–17}}</ref> A problem with this and similar characterizations is to determine the exact extension of what is unobservable. There is little controversy that regular everyday objects that we can perceive without any aids are observable. Such objects include, for example, trees, chairs, or dogs. But controversy starts with cases where unaided perception fails. These include using telescopes to study distant galaxies,<ref>{{cite book |editor-last1=Churchland |editor-first1=Paul M. |authorlink=Paul Churchland |editor-last2=Hooker |editor-first2=Clifford A. |title=Images of Science: Essays on Realism and Empiricism |last=Churchland |first=Paul M. |chapter=The Ontological Status of Observables: In Praise of the Superempirical Virtues |publisher=University of Chicago Press |date=1985}}</ref> using microscopes to study bacteria, or using cloud chambers to study positrons.<ref name="Fraassen" /> Some philosophers have been motivated by these and similar examples to question the value of the distinction between observable and unobservable in general.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Hacking |first=Ian |title=Do We See through a Microscope? |journal=Pacific Philosophical Quarterly |volume=62 |issue=4 |date=1981|pages=305–322 |doi=10.1111/j.1468-0114.1981.tb00070.x |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/HACDWS }}</ref> == Kinds of unobservables == W. V. Metcalf distinguishes three kinds of unobservables.<ref>{{cite journal |last=Metcalf |first=W. V. |date=1940 |title=The Reality of the Unobservable |jstor=184849 |journal=Philosophy of Science |volume=7 |issue=3 |pages=337–341 |doi=10.1086/286640|s2cid=121713405 }}</ref> One is the logically unobservable, which involves a contradiction. An example would be a length which is both longer and shorter than a given length. The second is the practically unobservable, that which we can conceive of as observable by the known sense-faculties of man but we are prevented from observing by practical difficulties. The third kind is the physically unobservable, that which can never be observed by any existing sense-faculties of man. ==See also== * [[Banach–Tarski paradox]] * [[Empiricism]] * [[Future]] * [[Hidden variable theory]] * [[If a tree falls in a forest]] * [[Logical positivism]] * [[Object of the mind]] * [[Phenomenology (philosophy)|Phenomenology]] * [[Proxy (statistics)]], for an unobservable variable * [[Rationalism]] * [[Unobservable chaos]] == References == {{reflist}} {{metaphysics}} [[Category:Concepts in epistemology]] [[Category:Concepts in metaphysics]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Metaphysics
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Rp
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)