Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Value theory
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{short description|Systematic study of values}} {{good article}} {{distinguish|Theory of value (economics)}} {{Use American English|date=February 2025}} '''Value theory''', also called '''''axiology''''', studies the nature, sources, and types of [[Value (ethics and social sciences)|values]]. It is a branch of [[philosophy]] and an interdisciplinary field closely associated with [[social sciences]] such as [[economics]], [[sociology]], [[anthropology]], and [[psychology]]. Value is the worth of something, usually understood as covering both positive and negative degrees corresponding to the terms ''[[good]]'' and ''bad''. Values influence many human endeavors related to [[emotion]], [[decision-making]], and [[Action (philosophy)|action]]. Value theorists distinguish various types of values, like the contrast between [[Instrumental and intrinsic value|intrinsic and instrumental value]]. An entity has [[Intrinsic value (ethics)|intrinsic value]] if it is good in itself, independent of external factors. An entity has instrumental value if it is useful as a means leading to other good things. Other classifications focus on the type of benefit, including economic, moral, political, aesthetic, and religious values. Further categorizations distinguish absolute values from values that are relative to something else. Value [[Philosophical realism|realists]] state that values exist as [[Subjectivity and objectivity (philosophy)|objective]] features of reality. Anti-realists reject this, with some seeing values as subjective human creations and others viewing value statements as meaningless. Regarding the sources of value, [[hedonism|hedonists]] argue that only [[pleasure]] has intrinsic value, whereas desire theorists discuss [[desire]]s as the ultimate source of value. [[Perfectionism (philosophy)|Perfectionism]], another approach, emphasizes the cultivation of characteristic human abilities. Value [[Pluralism (philosophy)|pluralism]] identifies diverse sources of intrinsic value, raising the issue of whether values belonging to different types are comparable. Value theorists employ various [[Philosophical methodology|methods of inquiry]], ranging from [[Ethical intuitionism|reliance on intuitions]] and [[thought experiments]] to the analysis of language, [[Phenomenology (philosophy)|description of first-person experience]], observation of behavior, and [[Survey (human research)|surveys]]. [[Ethics]], a related field, focuses primarily on [[Normativity|normative]] concepts of right behavior, whereas value theory explores [[evaluation|evaluative]] concepts about what is good. In economics, [[Value (economics)#Theories|theories of value]] are frameworks to assess and explain the economic value of [[Commodity|commodities]]. Sociology and anthropology examine values as aspects of societies and cultures, reflecting dominant preferences and beliefs. Psychologists tend to understand values as abstract [[motivational]] goals that shape an individual's [[personality]]. The roots of value theory lie in [[ancient period|antiquity]] as reflections on the [[highest good]] that humans should pursue. Diverse traditions contributed to this area of thought during the [[Medieval philosophy|medieval]] and [[early modern philosophy|early modern periods]], but it was only established as a distinct discipline in the late 19th and early 20th centuries. == Definition == [[File:Socrates Louvre.jpg|thumb|upright=.8|alt=Photo of a marble bust of a bearded man|Even though early contributions to value theory were made in antiquity by philosophers such as [[Socrates]], this area of thought was only conceived as a distinct discipline in the late 19th and early 20th centuries.<ref>{{multiref|{{harvnb|Grünberg|2000|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cFsiNrHfN1AC&pg=PA11 11–12]}}|{{harvnb|Hart|1971|p=29}}|{{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA136 136–137]}}}}</ref>]]Value theory, also known as ''axiology'' and ''theory of values'', is the systematic study of [[Value (ethics and social sciences)|values]]. As a branch of [[philosophy]], it examines which things are good and what it means for something to be good. It distinguishes different types of values and explores how they can be measured and compared. This field also studies whether values are a fundamental aspect of reality and how they influence phenomena such as [[emotion]], [[desire]], decision, and [[Action (philosophy)|action]].<ref name="auto2">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Smith|Thomas|1998|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Hirose|Olson|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1–2]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=Lead section}} }}</ref> Value theory is relevant to many human endeavors because values are guiding principles that underlie the political, economic, scientific, and personal spheres.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Bahm|1993|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jqSRrmtQ_WoC&pg=PA1 1, 4–6]}} | {{harvnb|Li|2014|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=W2a4BAAAQBAJ&pg=PA67 67–68]}} }}</ref> It analyzes and evaluates phenomena such as [[well-being]], [[utility]], [[beauty]], human life, [[knowledge]], [[wisdom]], [[freedom]], [[love]], and [[justice]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hiles|2008|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=byh1AwAAQBAJ&pg=PT84 52–53]}} | {{harvnb|Li|2014|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=W2a4BAAAQBAJ&pg=PA67 67–68]}} | {{harvnb|Bahm|1993|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jqSRrmtQ_WoC&pg=PA4 4–5]}} }}</ref> The precise definition of value theory is debated and some theorists rely on alternative characterizations. In a broad sense, ''value theory'' is a catch-all label that encompasses all philosophical disciplines studying evaluative and normative topics. According to this view, value theory is one of the main branches of philosophy and includes [[ethics]], [[aesthetics]], [[social philosophy]], [[political philosophy]], and [[philosophy of religion]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA6 6–7]}} | {{harvnb|Bahm|1993|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jqSRrmtQ_WoC&pg=PA4 4]}} | {{harvnb|Cowan|2020|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=-2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA4 4]}} }}</ref> A similar broad characterization sees value theory as a multidisciplinary area of inquiry that integrates research from fields like [[sociology]], [[anthropology]], [[psychology]], and [[economics]] alongside philosophy.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=ADG4EAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1]}} | {{harvnb|Hirose|Olson|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1–2]}} | {{harvnb|Bahm|1993|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jqSRrmtQ_WoC&pg=PA4 4–5]}} }}</ref> In a narrow sense, value theory is a subdiscipline of ethics that is particularly relevant to the school of [[consequentialism]] since it determines how to assess the value of consequences.<ref name="auto7">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA6 6–7]}} | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA357 357]}} }}</ref> The word ''axiology'' has its origin in the [[ancient Greek]] terms {{lang|grc|ἄξιος}} ({{Transliteration|grc|axios}}, meaning {{gloss|worthy}} or {{gloss|of value}}) and {{lang|grc|λόγος}} ({{Transliteration|grc|logos}}, meaning {{gloss|study}} or {{gloss|theory of}}).<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Taliaferro|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=CfWoAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA25 24]}} | {{harvnb|Arneson|2009|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=2veMwywplPUC&pg=PA69 69–70]}} }}</ref> Even though the roots of value theory reach back to the [[ancient period]], this area of thought was only conceived as a distinct discipline in the late 19th and early 20th centuries, when the term ''axiology'' was coined.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Grünberg|2000|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cFsiNrHfN1AC&pg=PA11 11–12]}} | {{harvnb|Hart|1971|p=29}} }}</ref> The terms ''value theory'' and ''axiology'' are usually used as synonyms but some philosophers distinguish between them. According to one characterization, axiology is a subfield of value theory that limits itself to theories about which things are valuable and how valuable they are.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA6 6–7]}} }}</ref>{{efn|Another view sees axiology as the wider field and restricts value theory to questions concerning the nature of value.<ref>{{harvnb|Grenz|Guretzki|Nordling|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Iv-LCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA18 18]}}</ref>}} The term ''timology'' is an older and less common synonym.<ref>{{harvnb|Grünberg|2000|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cFsiNrHfN1AC&pg=PA11 11–12]}}</ref> == Value == {{main|Value (ethics and social sciences)}} Value is the worth, usefulness, or merit of something.{{efn|The term ''value'' has other meanings as well, such as the value of a [[mathematical]] variable expressing the information or quantity that this variable carries.<ref>{{harvnb|HarperCollins|2022}}</ref> Value theory is only interested in the evaluative sense of the term about being [[good]] or bad in a certain respect.<ref>{{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 1. Basic Questions}}</ref>}} Value theorists examine the expressions used to describe and compare values, called ''evaluative terms''.<ref name="auto8">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 1]}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|1969|p=1}} }}</ref> They are further interested in the types or categories of values. The proposed classifications overlap and are based on factors like the source, beneficiary, and function of the value.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Li|2014|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=W2a4BAAAQBAJ&pg=PA70 70]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 1.1 Varieties of Goodness}} | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA22 22–23]}} | {{harvnb|Rescher|1969|pp=13–14, 18}} }}</ref> === Evaluative terms === Values are expressed through evaluative terms. For example, the words ''good'', ''best'', ''great'', and ''excellent'' convey positive values, whereas words like ''bad'' and ''terrible'' indicate negative values.<ref name="auto8"/> Value theorists distinguish between thin and [[Thick concept|thick evaluative terms]]. Thin evaluative terms, like ''good'' and ''bad'', express pure evaluations without any additional descriptive content.{{efn|Some philosophers, such as [[G. E. M. Anscombe]], [[Philippa Foot]], and [[Iris Murdoch]], have argued that there are no pure thin evaluative terms.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wiland|Driver|2022|loc=§ 2. Moral and Political Philosophy}} | {{harvnb|Chappell|2013|pp=188–189}} }}</ref>}} They contrast with thick evaluative terms, like ''[[Courage|courageous]]'' and ''[[cruel]]'', which provide more information by expressing other qualities, such as [[character trait]]s, in addition to the evaluation.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA2 2–3]}} | {{harvnb|Hirose|Olson|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA3 3]}} }}</ref> Values are often understood as degrees that cover positive and negative magnitudes corresponding to good and bad. The term ''value'' is sometimes restricted to positive degrees to contrast with the term ''disvalue'' for negative degrees. The words ''better'' and ''worse'' are used to compare degrees, but it is controversial whether a quantitative comparison is always possible.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 1.2 Good, Better, Bad, § 2.3 Incommensurability/Incomparability}} | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA122 122–123]}} | {{harvnb|Tappolet|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA82 82]}} | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|pp=636–637}} }}</ref> [[Evaluation]] is the assessment or measurement of value, often employed to compare the benefits of different options to find the most advantageous choice.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rescher|1969|pp=61–62}} | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|pp=636–637}} }}</ref> Evaluative terms are sometimes distinguished from [[Normativity|normative]] or deontic terms. Normative terms, like ''right'', ''wrong'', and ''obligation'', prescribe actions or other states by expressing what ought to be done or what is required.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA8 8–9]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 3. Relation to the Deontic}} }}</ref> Evaluative terms have a wider scope because they are not limited to what people can control or are responsible for. For instance, involuntary events like digestion and earthquakes can have a positive or negative value even if they are not right or wrong in a strict sense.<ref>{{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA357 357–358]}}</ref> Despite the distinction, evaluative and normative concepts are closely related. For example, the value of the consequences of an action may influence its normative status{{em dash}}whether the action is right or wrong.<ref name="auto4">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA8 8–9]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 3. Relation to the Deontic}} | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA357 357–358]}} }}</ref> === Types === ==== Intrinsic and instrumental ==== {{main|Instrumental and intrinsic value}} [[File:Intrinsic and instrumental values.svg|thumb|alt=Diagram with a box labelled "instrumental value" and an arrow pointing to a circle labelled "intrinsic value"|An entity has intrinsic value if it is good in itself. An entity has instrumental value if it leads to other good things.<ref name="auto15">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006a|pp=719–720}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 2.1 Intrinsic Value}} | {{harvnb|Rønnow-Rasmussen|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA29 29–30]}} | {{harvnb|Zimmerman|Bradley|2019|loc=Lead section}} }}</ref>]] [[File:Chain of instrumental values.svg|thumb|alt=Diagram with several boxes and arrows labelled "chain of instrumental values", and a circle labelled "intrinsic value"|Instrumental values can form chains with intrinsic values as their endpoints.<ref name="auto14">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006a|pp=719–720}} | {{harvnb|Zimmerman|Bradley|2019|loc=§ 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?}} }}</ref>]] A thing has intrinsic or final value if it is good in itself or good for its own sake, independent of external factors or outcomes. A thing has extrinsic or instrumental value if it is useful or leads to other good things, serving as a means to bring about a desirable end. For example, tools like microwaves or money have instrumental value due to the useful functions they perform.<ref name="auto15"/> In some cases, the thing produced this way has itself instrumental value, like when using money to buy a microwave. This can result in a chain of instrumentally valuable things in which each link gets its value by causing the following link. Intrinsically valuable things stand at the endpoint of these chains and ground the value of all the preceding links.<ref name="auto14"/> One suggestion to distinguish between intrinsic and instrumental value, proposed by [[G. E. Moore]], relies on a [[thought experiment]] that imagines the valuable thing in isolation from everything else. In such a situation, purely instrumentally valuable things lose their value since they serve no purpose while purely intrinsically valuable things remain valuable.<ref name="auto1">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Zimmerman|Bradley|2019|loc=§ 2. What Is Intrinsic Value?}} | {{harvnb|Rønnow-Rasmussen|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA30 30–31]}} }}</ref>{{efn|Critics of this thought experiment argue that it depends on controversial assumptions about the nature of intrinsic value and is not applicable to all cases.<ref>{{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA31 31–32]}}</ref>}} According to a common view, [[pleasure]] is one of the sources of intrinsic value. Other suggested sources include [[desire]] satisfaction, [[virtue]], [[life]], [[health]], [[beauty]], [[freedom]], and [[knowledge]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Zimmerman|Bradley|2019|loc=§ 1. What Has Intrinsic Value?}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 2.1 Intrinsic Value}} | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA140 140]}} }}</ref> [[File:Intrinsic and instrumental values2.svg|thumb|alt=Diagram with a circle inside a box labelled "intrinsic and instrumental value", an arrow, and another circle labelled "intrinsic value"|A thing can have both intrinsic and instrumental value if it is good in itself and leads to other good things.<ref name="auto16">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schellekens|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=LB4SBwAAQBAJ&pg=PA38 38]}} | {{harvnb|Vilkka|2021|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=2WxPEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA32 32]}} }}</ref>]] [[File:Positive and negative value.svg|thumb|alt=Diagram with a box labelled "instrumental value", two arrows, and two circles labelled "positive intrinsic value" and "negative intrinsic value"|A thing can have both positive and negative consequences. Its total instrumental value is the value balance of all its consequences.<ref name="auto11">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Zimmerman|Bradley|2019|loc=§ 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?}} | {{harvnb|Zimmerman|2001|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=9pqECJM08rkC&pg=PA253 253]}} }}</ref>]] Intrinsic and instrumental value are not exclusive categories. As a result, a thing can have both intrinsic and instrumental value if it is both good in itself while also leading to other good things.<ref name="auto16"/> In a similar sense, a thing can have different instrumental values at the same time, both positive and negative ones. This is the case if some of its consequences are good while others are bad. The total instrumental value of a thing is the value balance of all its consequences.<ref name="auto11"/> Because instrumental value depends on other values, it is an open question whether it should be understood as a value in a strict sense. For example, the overall value of a chain of causes leading to an intrinsically valuable thing remains the same if instrumentally valuable links are added or removed without affecting the intrinsically valuable thing. The observation that the overall value does not change is sometimes used as an argument that the things added or removed do not have value.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Zimmerman|Bradley|2019|loc=§ 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?}} | {{harvnb|Zimmerman|2001|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=9pqECJM08rkC&pg=PA252 252]}} }}</ref> Traditionally, value theorists have used the terms ''intrinsic value'' and ''final value'' interchangeably, just like the terms ''extrinsic value'' and ''instrumental value''. This practice has been questioned in the 20th century based on the idea that they are similar but not identical concepts. According to this view, a thing has intrinsic value if the source of its value is an [[intrinsic property]], meaning that the value does not depend on how the thing is related to other objects. Extrinsic value, by contrast, depends on [[Relation (philosophy)#Internal and external|external relations]]. This view sees instrumental value as one type of extrinsic value based on external [[Causality|causal relations]]. At the same time, it allows that there are other types of non-instrumental extrinsic value that result from external non-causal relations. Final value is understood as what is valued for its own sake, independent of whether intrinsic or extrinsic properties are responsible.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 2.1 Intrinsic Value}} | {{harvnb|Zimmerman|Bradley|2019|loc=§ 3. Is There Such a Thing As Intrinsic Value At All?, § 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?}} | {{harvnb|Rønnow-Rasmussen|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA29 29–30]}} }}</ref>{{efn|In the [[social sciences]], some works rely on the concept of relational value to understand the value of the relationship between humans and nature. According to this view, relational value is a unique type of value that is neither intrinsic nor instrumental.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Chan|Gould|Pascual|2018|pp=A1–A2}} | {{harvnb|Jax|2023|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=j57WEAAAQBAJ&pg=PT38 59–60]}} | {{harvnb|Gupta|2024|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=U9EEEQAAQBAJ&pg=PA11 11]}} }}</ref>}} ==== Absolute and relative ==== Another distinction relies on the contrast between absolute and relative value. Absolute value, also called ''value {{lang|la|simpliciter}}'', is a form of unconditional value. A thing has relative value if its value is relative to other things or limited to certain considerations or viewpoints.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA45 45–46]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 1. Basic Questions}} }}</ref> One form of relative value is restricted to the type of an entity, expressed in sentences like "That is a good knife" or "Jack is a good thief". This form is known as ''[[Attributive expression|attributive]] goodness'' since the word "good" modifies the meaning of another term. To be attributively good as a certain type means to possess qualities characteristic of that type. For instance, a good knife is sharp and a good thief has the skill of stealing without getting caught. Attributive goodness contrasts with [[Predicative expression|predicative]] goodness. The sentence "Pleasure is good" is an example since the word ''good'' is used as a predicate to talk about the unqualified value of pleasure.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA3 3–4]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 1. Basic Questions}} | {{harvnb|Zimmerman|2015|pp=13–14}} }}</ref> Attributive and predicative goodness can accompany each other, but this is not always the case. For instance, being a good thief is not necessarily a good thing.<ref>{{harvnb|Silverstein|2016|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=96qkDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA227 227]}}</ref> Another type of relative value restricts goodness to a specific person. Known as ''personal value'',{{efn|[[Prudential value]] is a closely related concept signifying what is good for a person.<ref>{{harvnb|Tiberius|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA158 158]}}</ref>}} it expresses what benefits a particular person, promotes their [[welfare spending|welfare]], or is in their interest. For example, a poem written by a child may have personal value for the parents even if the poem lacks value for others. Impersonal value, by contrast, is good in general without restriction to any specific person or viewpoint.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA63 63–64]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 1. Basic Questions}} | {{harvnb|Rønnow-Rasmussen|2011|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=b_O3l9_QgNgC&pg=PA1 1–2]}} }}</ref> Some philosophers, like Moore, reject the existence of personal values, holding that all values are impersonal. Others have proposed theories about the relation between personal and impersonal value. The agglomerative theory says that impersonal value is nothing but the sum of all personal values. Another view understands impersonal value as a specific type of personal value taken from the perspective of the universe as a whole.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 1.1.1 Good Simpliciter and Good For}} | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA63 63–65]}} }}</ref> Agent-relative value is sometimes contrasted with personal value as another person-specific limitation of the evaluative outlook. Agent-relative values affect moral considerations about what a person is responsible for or guilty of. For example, if Mei promises to pick Pedro up from the airport then an agent-relative value obligates Mei to drive to the airport. This obligation is in place even if it does not benefit Mei, in which case there is an agent-relative value without a personal value. In [[consequentialism]],{{efn|Consequentialism is a theory in [[normative ethics]]. It says that whether an act is right depends on its consequences.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sinnott-Armstrong|2023|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Haines|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Hooker|2023|loc=§ 1. Utilitarianism}} }}</ref>}} agent-relative values are often discussed in relation to [[ethical dilemmas]]. One dilemma revolves around the question of whether an individual should murder an innocent person if this prevents the murder of two innocent people by a different perpetrator. The agent-neutral perspective tends to affirm this idea since one murder is preferable to two. The agent-relative perspective tends to reject this conclusion, arguing that the initial murder should be avoided since it negatively impacts the agent-relative value of the individual committing it.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA73 73–74]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 3.3 Agent-Relative Value?}} | {{harvnb|Cullity|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA96 96–97]}} }}</ref> Traditionally, most value theorists see absolute value as the main topic of value theory and focus their attention on this type. Nonetheless, some philosophers, like [[Peter Geach]] and [[Philippa Foot]], have argued that the concept of absolute value by itself is meaningless and should be understood as one form of relative value.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA45 45–46, 61]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 1.1.2 Attributive Good}} }}</ref> ==== Other distinctions ==== Other classifications of values have been proposed without a widely accepted main classification.<ref>{{harvnb|Rescher|1969|pp=13–14}}</ref> Some focus on the types of entities that have value. They include distinct categories for entities like things, the environment, individuals, groups, and society. Another subdivision pays attention to the type of benefit involved and encompasses material, economic, moral, social, political, aesthetic, and religious values. Classifications by the beneficiary of the value distinguish between self- and other-oriented values.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Rescher|1969|pp=15–16, 18}} | {{harvnb|Pradhan|2024|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=m4wWEQAAQBAJ&pg=PA142 142]}} | {{harvnb|Hartman|2011|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=1UX7DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA306 306]}} }}</ref> A historically influential approach identifies three spheres of value: [[truth]], goodness, and beauty.{{efn|In [[scholastic philosophy]], they are known as ''[[transcendentals]]'' and considered fundamental aspects of being.<ref>{{harvnb|De Haan|2020|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=a5EHEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA302 302]}}</ref>}} For example, the [[neo-Kantian]] philosopher [[Wilhelm Windelband]] characterizes them as the highest goals of [[consciousness]], with [[thought]] aiming at truth, [[Will (philosophy)|will]] aiming at goodness, and [[emotion]] aiming at beauty. A similar view, proposed by the [[Chinese philosophy|Chinese philosopher]] Zhang Dainian, says that the value of truth belongs to knowledge, the value of goodness belongs to behavior, and the value of beauty belongs to art.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Li|2014|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=W2a4BAAAQBAJ&pg=PA80 80–81]}} | {{harvnb|Ollig|1998|loc=[https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/neo-kantianism/v-1 Lead section]}} | {{harvnb|Martin|2016|pp=3–5, 42–43}} }}</ref> This three-fold distinction also plays a central role in the philosophies of [[Franz Brentano]] and [[Jürgen Habermas]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Martin|2016|pp=4–5}} | {{harvnb|Kriegel|2018|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=3e9IDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA96 96–97, 149, 253, 288]}} }}</ref> Other suggested types of values include objective, subjective, potential, actual, contingent, necessary, inherent, and constitutive values.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA44 44]}} | {{harvnb|Bahm|1993|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jqSRrmtQ_WoC&pg=PA60 60–63]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 2.1.1 What is Intrinsic Value?}} | {{harvnb|Rønnow-Rasmussen|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA39 39–40]}} }}</ref> == Schools of thought == === Realism and anti-realism === Value [[Philosophical realism|realism]] is the view that values have mind-independent existence.<ref name="auto3">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Zagzebski|2004|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=KhqPito92b8C&pg=PA11 11]}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=Lead section}} }}</ref>{{efn|If this position limits itself to the moral realm, it is known as ''[[moral realism]]'', an influential position in [[ethics]].<ref name="auto3"/>}} This means that [[Subjectivity and objectivity (philosophy)|objective]] facts determine what has value, irrespective of subjective beliefs and preferences.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|pp=639–640}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=Lead section}} }}</ref> According to this view, the evaluative statement "That act is bad" is as objectively true or false as the empirical statement "That act causes distress".<ref>{{harvnb|Zagzebski|2004|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=KhqPito92b8C&pg=PA11 11–12]}}</ref> Realists often analyze values as [[Property (philosophy)|properties]] of valuable things.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|pp=639–640}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=Lead section, § Do Value Claims Have Truth Makers?}} | {{harvnb|Oliver|1998}} }}</ref> For example, stating that kindness is good asserts that kindness possesses the property of goodness. Value realists disagree about what type of property is involved. [[Ethical naturalism|Naturalists]] say that value is a natural property. Natural properties, like size and shape, can be known through [[Empirical evidence|empirical observation]] and are studied by the natural sciences. [[Ethical non-naturalism|Non-naturalists]] reject this view but agree that values are real. They say that values differ significantly from empirical properties and belong to another domain of reality. According to one view, they are known through rational or emotional intuition rather than empirical observation.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|pp=639–640}} | {{harvnb|Lutz|2023|loc=Lead section, § 1. What Is Moral Naturalism?}} | {{harvnb|DeLapp|loc=§ 4a. Moral Realisms}} | {{harvnb|FitzPatrick|2011|pp=[https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057/9780230294899_2 7–8]}} | {{harvnb|Ridge|2019|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Oliver|1998}} }}</ref> Another disagreement among realists is about whether the entity carrying the value is a concrete [[Particular|individual]] or a [[State of affairs (philosophy)|state of affairs]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA35 35]}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Bradley|2006|pp=111–112}} | {{harvnb|Oliveira|2016|loc=§ 1. Introduction}} }}</ref> For instance, the name "Bill" refers to an individual while the sentence "Bill is pleased" refers to a state of affairs, which combines the individual "Bill" with the property "pleased". Some value theorists hold that the value is a property directly of Bill while others contend that it is a property of the state of affairs that Bill is pleased.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA35 35]}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Bradley|2006|pp=111–112, 115}} | {{harvnb|Oliveira|2016|loc=§ 1. Introduction}} }}</ref> This distinction affects various disputes in value theory. In some cases, a value is intrinsic according to one view and extrinsic according to the other.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA35 35–36, 130–131]}} | {{harvnb|Bradley|2006|pp=111–112}} }}</ref> Value realism contrasts with [[anti-realism]], which comes in various forms. In its strongest version, anti-realism rejects the existence of values in any form, claiming that value statements are meaningless.<ref>{{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=Lead section, § Are Value Claims Truth Evaluable?, § Value Realism by Degrees: a Flow Chart}}</ref>{{efn|This view is sometimes called ''radical [[nihilism]]''.<ref>{{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=§ Are Value Claims Truth Evaluable?, § Quasi-Realism and Creeping Minimalism}}</ref>}} There are various intermediate views between this position and realism. Some anti-realists accept that value claims have meaning but deny that they have a [[truth value]],{{efn|This means that value statements are neither true nor false.<ref>{{harvnb|HarperCollins|2022a}}</ref>}} a position known as ''[[non-cognitivism]]''. For example, [[Emotivism|emotivists]] say that value claims express emotional attitudes, similar to how exclamations like "Yay!" or "Boo!" express emotions rather than stating facts.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=§ Are Value Claims Truth Evaluable?}} | {{harvnb|Tappolet|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA80 80]}} | {{harvnb|DeNicola|2019|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_sp6DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA267 267]}} | {{harvnb|Oliver|1998}} }}</ref>{{efn|[[Projectivism]] is a closely related view holding that values are projections of emotions onto the world.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Tappolet|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA80 80]}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=§ Quasi-Realism and Creeping Minimalism}} | {{harvnb|Oliver|1998}} }}</ref>}} [[Cognitivism (ethics)|Cognitivists]] contend that value statements have a truth value. Following this view, [[Error theory|error theorists]] defend anti-realism by stating that all value statements are false because there are no values.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=§ Do Value Claims Have Truth Makers?}} | {{harvnb|Sayre-McCord|1988|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=-msmrkE-67IC&pg=PA10 10]}} | {{harvnb|Zagzebski|2004|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=KhqPito92b8C&pg=PA14 14]}} | {{harvnb|Oliver|1998}} }}</ref> Another view accepts the existence of values but denies that they are mind-independent. According to this view, the [[mental state]]s of individuals determine whether an object has value, for instance, because individuals desire it.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=§ Are the Value Facts Mind Independent?}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA60 60–62]}} | {{harvnb|Mander|2016|loc=[https://books.google.com/books?id=f0UFCwAAQBAJ&pg=PT14 § 2.3 An Overview]}} }}</ref> A similar view is defended by [[Existentialism|existentialists]] like [[Jean-Paul Sartre]], who argued that values are human creations that endow the world with meaning.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Onof|loc=§6c. An Ethical Dimension}} | {{harvnb|Landau|2012|pp=1–2}} }}</ref> Subjectivist theories say that values are relative to each subject, whereas more objectivist outlooks hold that values depend on [[mind]] in general rather than on the individual mind.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=§ Are the Value Facts Mind Independent?}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA60 60–62]}} }}</ref> A different position accepts that values are mind-independent but holds that they are reducible to other facts, meaning that they are not a fundamental part of reality. One form of [[reductionism]] maintains that a thing is good if it is fitting to favor this thing, regardless of whether people actually favor it, a position known as the ''fitting-attitude theory of value''. The buck-passing account, a closely related reductive view, argues that a thing is valuable if people have reasons to treat the thing in certain ways. These reasons come from other features of the valuable thing. According to some views, reductionism is a form of realism, but the strongest form of realism says that value is a fundamental part of reality and cannot be reduced to other aspects.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Oddie|2013|loc=Lead section, § Are the Value Facts Irreducible?, § Value Realism by Degrees: a Flow Chart}} | {{harvnb|Oddie|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA67 67–68]}} | {{harvnb|Oliver|1998}} | {{harvnb|Howard|2023|loc=Lead section, § 1.5 Buck Passing}} | {{harvnb|Suikkanen|2009|pp=768–769}} }}</ref> === Sources of value === Various theories about the sources of value have been proposed. They aim to clarify what kinds of things are intrinsically good.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA357 357]}} | {{harvnb|Oliveira|2016|loc=§ 1. Introduction}} | {{harvnb|Kershnar|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=vwMN7WRb2fEC&pg=PA37 37]}} | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA140 140]}} }}</ref> The historically influential theory of [[hedonism]]{{efn|This view is sometimes called ''axiological hedonism'' to distinguish it from related theories under this label.<ref>{{harvnb|de Bres|2014|pp=[https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/abs/cambridge-rawls-lexicon/hedonism/602FBE3D4ACFED4422C43BCCBA3BAB48 336–338]}}</ref>}} states that how people feel is the only source of value. More specifically, it says that [[pleasure]] is the only intrinsic good and [[pain]] is the only intrinsic evil.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA359 359]}} | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA140 140]}} }}</ref> According to this view, everything else only has instrumental value to the extent that it leads to pleasure or pain, including knowledge, health, and justice. Hedonists usually understand the term ''pleasure'' in a broad sense that covers all kinds of enjoyable experiences, including bodily pleasures of food and sex as well as more intellectual or abstract pleasures, like the joy of reading a book or happiness about a friend's promotion. Pleasurable experiences come in degrees, and hedonists usually associate their intensity and duration with the magnitude of value they have.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA359 359–360]}} | {{harvnb|Moore|2019|loc=§ 2. Ethical Hedonism}} }}</ref>{{efn|Qualitative hedonists argue that the quality of pleasure is an additional factor influencing its value besides intensity and duration. Some distinguish higher pleasures of the mind, like enjoying fine art and philosophy, from lower pleasures of the body, like enjoying food and drink.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Tilley|2012|loc=§ III. Axiological Hedonism}} | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2013|loc=§ What Determines the Intrinsic Value of a Pleasure or a Pain?}} }}</ref>}} Many hedonists identify pleasure and pain as symmetric opposites, meaning that the value of pleasure balances out the disvalue of pain if they have the same intensity. However, some hedonists reject this symmetry and give more weight to avoiding pain than to experiencing pleasure.<ref>{{harvnb|Hurka|2006|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA360 360]}}</ref> Although it is widely accepted that pleasure is valuable, the hedonist claim that it is the only source of value is controversial.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA361 361]}} | {{harvnb|Moore|2019|loc=§ 2.3 Other Arguments Against Ethical Hedonism}} }}</ref> [[Welfarism]], a closely related theory, understands [[well-being]] as the only source of value. Well-being is what is ultimately good for a person, which can include other aspects besides pleasure, such as health, [[personal growth]], meaningful [[Interpersonal relationship|relationships]], and a sense of purpose in life.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Crisp|2021|loc=Lead section, § 5.1 Welfarism}} | {{harvnb|Hall|Tiberius|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=zZdGCgAAQBAJ&pg=PA175 175–176]}} | {{harvnb|Nebel|2024|loc=§ Introduction}} | {{harvnb|Hooker|2015|pp=15–16}} }}</ref> Desire theories offer a slightly different account, stating that desire satisfaction{{efn|Some theorists use the terms ''desire satisfaction'' and ''desire fulfillment'' as synonyms while others distinguish between them. According to the latter view, desire satisfaction is a subjective state involving a possibly false belief that a desire is satisfied. Desire fulfillment is an objective state present if the desired outcome actually exists, even if the person does not know about it.<ref>{{harvnb|Oddie|2017|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=OTElDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA49 49]}}</ref>}} is the only source of value.{{efn|Some desire theories aim to explain goodness in general while others restrict themselves to goodness for a person.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA362 362–363]}} | {{harvnb|Scanlon|1993|pp=186–187}} }}</ref>}} This theory overlaps with hedonism because many people desire pleasure and because desire satisfaction is often accompanied by pleasure. Nonetheless, there are important differences: people desire a variety of other things as well, like knowledge, achievement, and respect; additionally, desire satisfaction may not always result in pleasure.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA361 361–362, 364]}} | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA140 140]}} }}</ref> Some desire theorists hold that value is a property of desire satisfaction itself, while others say that it is a property of the objects that satisfy a desire.<ref>{{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA362 362–363]}}</ref> One debate in desire theory concerns whether every desire is a source of value. For example, if a person has a false belief that money makes them happy, it is questionable whether the satisfaction of their desire for money is a source of value. To address this consideration, some desire theorists say that a desire can only provide value if a fully informed and rational person would have it, thereby excluding misguided desires from being a source of value.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA362 362–363]}} | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2016|pp=138–140}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 3.2 Fitting Attitudes}} | {{harvnb|Scanlon|1993|pp=186–187}} }}</ref> [[Perfectionism (philosophy)|Perfectionism]] identifies the realization of [[human nature]] and the cultivation of characteristic human abilities as the source of intrinsic goodness. It covers capacities and character traits belonging to the bodily, emotional, volitional, cognitive, social, artistic, and religious fields. Perfectionists disagree about which human excellences are the most important. Many are pluralistic in recognizing a diverse array of human excellences, such as knowledge, creativity, health, beauty, free agency, and moral virtues like benevolence and courage.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Shea|Kintz|2022|p=461}} | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA364 364–366]}} | {{harvnb|Wall|2021|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA140 140]}} }}</ref> According to one suggestion, there are two main fields of human goods: theoretical abilities responsible for understanding the world and practical abilities responsible for interacting with it.<ref>{{harvnb|Hurka|2006|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA364 364]}}</ref> Some perfectionists provide an ideal characterization of human nature as the goal of human flourishing, holding that human excellences are those aspects that promote the realization of this goal. This view is exemplified in [[Aristotle]]'s focus on [[rationality]] as the nature and ideal state of human beings.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA365 365–366]}} | {{harvnb|Wall|2021|loc=§ 1. Perfectionism and Value Theory}} }}</ref> Non-humanistic versions extend perfectionism to the natural world in general, arguing that excellence as a source of intrinsic value is not limited to the human realm.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wall|2021|loc=§ 1. Perfectionism and Value Theory}} | {{harvnb|Gill|2024|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=VMcFEQAAQBAJ&pg=PA85 85]}} }}</ref> === Monism and pluralism === [[Monism|Monist]] theories of value assert that there is only a single source of intrinsic value. They agree that various things have value but maintain that all fundamentally good things belong to the same type. For example, hedonists hold that nothing but pleasure has intrinsic value, while desire theorists argue that desire satisfaction is the only source of fundamental goodness. [[Pluralism (philosophy)|Pluralists]] reject this view, contending that a simple single-value system is too crude to capture the complexity of the sphere of values. They say that diverse sources of value exist independently of one another, each contributing to the overall value of the world.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA136 136–137, 139–140]}} | {{harvnb|Mason|2023|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 2.2 Monism/Pluralism}} | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA358 358–359]}} }}</ref> One motivation for value pluralism is the observation that people value diverse types of things, including happiness, friendship, success, and knowledge.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Mason|2023|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 2.2 Monism/Pluralism}} | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA145 145–146]}} }}</ref> This diversity becomes particularly prominent when people face difficult decisions between competing values, such as choosing between friendship and career success.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Mason|2023|loc=§ 2. The Attraction of Pluralism}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 2.2 Monism/Pluralism}} }}</ref> In such cases, value pluralists can argue that the different items have different types of values. Since monists accept only one source of intrinsic value, they may provide a different explanation by proposing that some of the valuable items only have instrumental value but lack intrinsic value.<ref>{{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ 2.2.2 Revisionary Commitments?}}</ref> [[File:IsaiahBerlin1983.jpg|thumb|alt=Black-and-white photo of a man with glasses wearing a suit and a bow tie|[[Isaiah Berlin]] argued that conflicts between different types of values, like [[liberty]] and [[Social equality|equality]], cannot always be resolved.<ref>{{harvnb|Mason|2023|loc=§ 4.4 Accepting Incomparability}}</ref>]] Pluralists have proposed various accounts of how their view affects practical decisions. Rational decisions often rely on value comparisons to determine which course of action should be pursued.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Mason|2023|loc=§ 4. Pluralism and Rational Choice}} | {{harvnb|Hsieh|Andersson|2021|loc=Lead section, § 4. Deliberation and Choice}} }}</ref> Some pluralists discuss a hierarchy of values reflecting the relative importance and weight of different value types to help people promote higher values when faced with difficult choices.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kinneging|2011|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=1Qya55bssVQC&pg=PA206 206–207]}} | {{harvnb|Perrin|1991|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=-6ewCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA69 69, 73–74, 76]}} }}</ref> For example, philosopher [[Max Scheler]] ranks values based on how enduring and fulfilling they are into the levels of pleasure, utility, vitality, culture, and holiness. He asserts that people should not promote lower values, like pleasure, if this comes at the expense of higher values.<ref name="auto13">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Perrin|1991|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=-6ewCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA69 69, 73–74, 76–80]}} | {{harvnb|Davis|Steinbock|2024|loc=§ 3. Value Personalism}} }}</ref>{{efn|In some places, Scheler talks about four levels instead of five: sensory, vital, spiritual, and holy.<ref>{{harvnb|Perrin|1991|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=-6ewCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA76 76–80]}}</ref>}} Radical pluralists reject this approach, putting more emphasis on diversity by holding that different types of values are not comparable with each other. This means that each value type is unique, making it impossible to determine which one is superior.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA142 142–143]}} | {{harvnb|Hsieh|Andersson|2021|loc=§ 1.2 Incommensurable or Incomparable?}} }}</ref>{{efn|More specifically, this implies that one value is not better than the other, not worse than the other, and not as good as the other.<ref>{{harvnb|Hsieh|Andersson|2021|loc=§ 1.2 Incommensurable or Incomparable?}}</ref>}} Some value theorists use radical pluralism to argue that value conflicts are inevitable, that the gain of one value cannot always compensate for the loss of another, and that some [[ethical dilemmas]] are irresolvable.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Mason|2023|loc=§ 4.4 Accepting Incomparability}} | {{harvnb|Hsieh|Andersson|2021|loc=§ 3.2 Moral Dilemmas?}} | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA142 142–143]}} }}</ref> For example, philosopher [[Isaiah Berlin]] applied this idea to the values of [[liberty]] and [[Social equality|equality]], arguing that a gain in one cannot make up for a loss in the other. Similarly, philosopher [[Joseph Raz]] said that it is often impossible to compare the values of career paths, like when choosing between becoming a [[lawyer]] or a [[clarinetist]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Mason|2023|loc=§ 4.4 Accepting Incomparability}} | {{harvnb|Hsieh|Andersson|2021|loc=§ 1.2 Incommensurable or Incomparable?}} | {{harvnb|Cherniss|Hardy|2023|loc=§ 4.1 Berlin’s Definition of Value Pluralism}} }}</ref> The terms ''incomparability'' and ''incommensurability'' are often used as synonyms in this context. However, philosophers like [[Ruth Chang]] distinguish them. According to this view, incommensurability means that there is no common measure to quantify values of different types. Incommensurable values may or may not be comparable. If they are, it is possible to say that one value is better than another, but it is not possible to quantify how much better it is.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Mason|2023|loc=§ 4. Pluralism and Rational Choice}} | {{harvnb|Hsieh|Andersson|2021|loc=§ 1.2 Incommensurable or Incomparable?}} }}</ref> === Others === Several controversies surround the question of how the intrinsic value of a [[Mereology|whole]] is determined by the intrinsic values of its parts. According to the additivity principle, the intrinsic value of a whole is simply the sum of the intrinsic values of its parts. For example, if a virtuous person becomes happy then the intrinsic value of the happiness is simply added to the intrinsic value of the virtue, thereby increasing the overall value.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Oddie|2001|pp=313, 318}} | {{harvnb|Dancy|2004|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_78SDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA188 188]}} }}</ref> [[File:1914 George Edward Moore (cropped).jpg|thumb|alt=Black-and-white photo of man wearing a suit with a pipe in his mouth|[[G. E. Moore]] introduced the idea of organic unities to describe entities whose total intrinsic value is not the sum of the intrinsic values of their parts.<ref>{{harvnb|Hurka|2021|loc=§ 4. The Ideal}}</ref>]] Various counterexamples to the additivity principle have been proposed, suggesting that the relation between parts and wholes is more complex. For instance, [[Immanuel Kant]] argued that if a vicious person becomes happy, this happiness, though good in itself, does not increase the overall value. On the contrary, it makes things worse, according to Kant, since viciousness should not be rewarded with happiness. This situation is known as an ''organic unity''{{em dash}}a whole whose intrinsic value differs from the sum of the intrinsic values of its parts.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Oddie|2001|pp=313, 318}} | {{harvnb|Dancy|2004|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_78SDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA176 176–177]}} }}</ref> Another perspective, called ''holism about value'', asserts that the intrinsic value of a thing depends on its context. Holists can argue that happiness has positive intrinsic value in the context of virtue and negative intrinsic value in the context of vice. Atomists reject this view, saying that intrinsic value is context-independent.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA98 98–100]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021a}} | {{harvnb|Dancy|2004|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_78SDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA176 176–177]}} }}</ref> Theories of value aggregation provide concrete principles for calculating the overall value of an outcome based on how positively or negatively each individual is affected by it. For example, if a government implements a new policy that affects some people positively and others negatively, theories of value aggregation can be used to determine whether the overall value of the policy is positive or negative. Axiological [[utilitarianism]] accepts the additivity principle, saying that the total value is simply the sum of all individual values.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Holtug|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA267 267–268]}} | {{harvnb|Peterson|2013|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=KscNwy-F3u8C&pg=PA147 147]}} | {{harvnb|Hirose|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=m-5jBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA25 25–27]}} }}</ref> Axiological [[Egalitarianism|egalitarians]] are not only interested in the sum total of value but also in how the values are distributed. They argue that an outcome with a balanced advantage distribution is better than an outcome where some benefit a lot while others benefit little, even if the two outcomes have the same sum total.<ref name="auto6">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Holtug|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA273 273]}} | {{harvnb|Peterson|2013|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=KscNwy-F3u8C&pg=PA147 147]}} | {{harvnb|Hirose|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=m-5jBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA25 25–27]}} }}</ref> Axiological [[Prioritarianism|prioritarians]] are particularly concerned with the benefits of individuals who are worse off. They say that providing advantages to people in need has more value than providing the same advantages to others.<ref name="auto6"/> Another debate addresses the [[meaning of life]], investigating whether life or existence as a whole has a higher meaning or purpose.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Metz|2023|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Cowan|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA25 25–26]}} | {{harvnb|Groothuis|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA160 160–162]}} }}</ref> [[Ethical naturalism|Naturalist]] views argue that the meaning of life is found within the physical world, either as objective values that are true for everyone or as subjective values that vary according to individual preferences. Suggested fields where humans find meaning include exercising [[freedom]], committing oneself to a cause, practicing [[altruism]], engaging in positive [[social relationships]], or pursuing personal [[happiness]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Metz|2023|loc=§ 3. Naturalism}} | {{harvnb|Cowan|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA25 25–26]}} | {{harvnb|Yalom|2020|pp=431–435}} }}</ref> [[Supernatural]]ists, by contrast, propose that meaning lies beyond the natural world. For example, various religions teach that [[God]] created the world for a higher purpose, imbuing existence with meaning. A related outlook argues that immortal [[soul]]s serve as sources of meaning by being connected to a [[transcendent reality]] and evolving [[Spirituality|spiritually]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Metz|2023|loc=§ 2. Supernaturalism}} | {{harvnb|Groothuis|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA162 162–164]}} | {{harvnb|Seachris|loc=§ 3. Theories of Meaning ''in'' Life}} }}</ref> [[Existential nihilism|Existential nihilists]] reject both naturalist and supernaturalist explanations by asserting that there is no higher purpose. They suggest that life is meaningless, with the consequence that there is no higher reason to continue living and that all efforts, achievements, happiness, and suffering are ultimately pointless.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Metz|2023|loc=4. Nihilism}} | {{harvnb|Pratt|loc=§ 3. Existential Nihilism}} | {{harvnb|Crosby|1998|loc=§ Existential Nihilism}} | {{harvnb|Groothuis|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA165 165–169]}} | {{harvnb|Crosby|1988|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=9VnPgFiW0CIC&pg=PA30 30–32]}} }}</ref> Formal axiology is a theory of value initially developed by philosopher [[Robert S. Hartman]]. This approach treats axiology as a [[formal science]], akin to [[logic]] and [[mathematics]]. It uses [[axiom]]s to give an abstract definition of value, understanding it not as a property of things but as a property of concepts. Value measures the extent to which an entity fulfills its concept. For example, a good car has all the desirable qualities of cars, like a reliable engine and effective brakes, whereas a bad car lacks many. Formal axiology distinguishes between three fundamental value types: intrinsic values apply to people; extrinsic values apply to things, actions, and social roles; systemic values apply to conceptual constructs. Formal axiology examines how these value types form a hierarchy and how they can be measured.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Edwards|2021|pp=2–4}} | {{harvnb|Hartman|2011|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=1UX7DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA104 104–105, 305–306]}} }}</ref> == Methods == Value theorists employ various [[Methodology|methods]] to conduct their inquiries, justify theories, and measure values. [[Ethical intuitionism|Intuitionists]] rely on [[intuition]]s to assess evaluative claims. In this context, an intuition is an immediate apprehension or understanding of a [[self-evident]] claim, meaning that its truth can be assessed without [[Inference|inferring]] it from another observation.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Stratton-Lake|2020|loc=§ 1.1 Intuition}} | {{harvnb|Audi|2004|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=S_RrKGcgSewC&pg=PA2 2, 5]}} | {{harvnb|Martin|2002|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=vNvXkFUbfM8C&pg=PA166 166]}} | {{harvnb|Li|2014|pp=4–5}} | {{harvnb|Dabbagh|2022|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jwuHEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA53 53]}} }}</ref> Value theorists often rely on [[thought experiments]] to gain this type of understanding. Thought experiments are imagined scenarios that exemplify philosophical problems. Philosophers use [[Counterfactual thinking|counterfactual reasoning]] to evaluate possible consequences and gain insight into underlying problems.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Martin|2002|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=vNvXkFUbfM8C&pg=PA166 166]}} | {{harvnb|Zaibert|2018|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=E1FSDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA37 37–38]}} | {{harvnb|Brown|Fehige|2019|loc=Lead Section}} | {{harvnb|Goffi|Roux|2011|pp=165, 168–169}} }}</ref> For example, philosopher [[Robert Nozick]] imagines an [[experience machine]] that can virtually simulate an ideal life. Based on his contention that people would not want to spend the rest of their lives in this pleasurable simulation, Nozick argues against the [[Hedonism|hedonist]] claim that pleasure is the only source of intrinsic value. According to him, the thought experiment shows that the value of an authentic connection to reality is not reducible to pleasure.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA146 146–147]}} | {{harvnb|Tiberius|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA163 163–164]}} }}</ref>{{efn|Moore's isolation test is another influential thought experiment about intrinsic value.<ref name="auto1"/>}} [[Phenomenology (philosophy)|Phenomenologists]] provide a detailed first-person description of the [[experience]] of values. They closely examine emotional experiences, ranging from desire, interest, and preference to feelings in the form of love and hate. However, they do not limit their inquiry to these phenomena, asserting that values permeate experience at large.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Davis|Steinbock|2024|loc=§ 3. Value Personalism}} | {{harvnb|Direk|2014|pp=371–372}} | {{harvnb|Grünberg|1990|pp=199–201}} | {{harvnb|Hart|1997|pp=1–2, 6–7}} }}</ref> A key aspect of the phenomenological method is to [[Epoche|suspend preconceived ideas and judgments]] to understand the essence of experiences as they present themselves to consciousness.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Smith|loc=§ b. Phenomenological Reduction}} | {{harvnb|Staiti|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=TGMPEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA368 368–369]}} }}</ref> The analysis of concepts and [[Ordinary language philosophy|ordinary language]] is another method of inquiry. By examining terms and sentences used to talk about values, value theorists aim to clarify their meanings, uncover crucial distinctions, and formulate arguments for and against axiological theories.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Moritz|1972|pp=[https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-010-2424-2_3 33–46]}} | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=§ Basic Questions}} }}</ref> For instance, a prominent dispute between [[Naturalism (philosophy)|naturalists]] and [[Ethical non-naturalism|non-naturalists]] hinges on the [[conceptual analysis]] of the term ''[[good]]'', in particular, whether its meaning can be analyzed through natural terms, like ''[[pleasure]]''.<ref name="auto5">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Laskowski|Finlay|2017|pp=537–539}} | {{harvnb|Chrisman|2016|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=JiklDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA79 79]}} }}</ref>{{efn|This problem is the main topic of Moore's controversial [[open-question argument]].<ref name="auto5"/>}} [[File:Schwartz theory of basic human values.svg|thumb|alt=Circular diagram showing the relations between different types of values, represented by segments|The [[Theory of basic human values|Schwartz theory of basic human values]] is an instrument to measure value priorities. It arranges different values in a circle, using [[angular distance]] between values to indicate how compatible they are.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schwartz|Cieciuch|2016|pp=109–113}} | {{harvnb|Schwartz|Cieciuch|Vecchione|Davidov|2012|p=669}} }}</ref>]] In the [[social sciences]], value theorists face the challenge of measuring the evaluative outlook of individuals and groups. Specifically, they aim to determine personal value hierarchies, for example, whether a person gives more weight to truth than to moral goodness or beauty.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schwartz|Cieciuch|2016|pp=106, 108}} | {{harvnb|Hiles|2008|p=53}} | {{harvnb|Karp|2000|loc=Lead section}} }}</ref> They distinguish between direct and indirect measurement methods. Direct methods involve asking people straightforward questions about what things they value and which value priorities they have. This approach assumes that people are aware of their evaluative outlook and able to articulate it accurately. Indirect methods do not share this assumption, asserting instead that values guide behavior and choices on an unconscious level. Consequently, they observe how people decide and act, seeking to infer the underlying value attitudes responsible for picking one course of action rather than another.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schwartz|Cieciuch|2016|pp=106–107}} | {{harvnb|Powe|2007|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=QpIgHPHmegsC&pg=PA123 123]}} }}</ref> Various catalogs or [[Values scale|scales of values]] have been proposed to measure value priorities. The [[Rokeach Value Survey]] considers a total of 36 values divided into two groups: instrumental values, like honesty and capability, which serve as means to promote terminal values, such as freedom and family security. It asks participants to rank the values based on their impact on the participants' lives, aiming to understand the relative importance assigned to each of them. The [[Theory of basic human values|Schwartz theory of basic human values]] is a modification of the Rokeach Value Survey that seeks to provide a more cross-cultural and universal assessment. It arranges the values in a circular manner to reflect that neighboring values are compatible with each other, such as openness to change and self-enhancement, while values on opposing sides may conflict with each other, such as openness to change and conservation.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schwartz|Cieciuch|2016|pp=109–113}} | {{harvnb|Karp|2000|loc=§ The Rokeach tradition, § The Schwartz Scale of Values}} }}</ref> == In various fields == === Ethics === {{main|Ethics}} Ethics and value theory are overlapping fields of inquiry. Ethics studies [[Morality|moral]] phenomena, focusing on how people should act or which behaviors are morally right.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Norman|2005|p=622}} | {{harvnb|Nagel|2006|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Crisp|2011|loc=§ 1. Ethics and Metaethics}} }}</ref> Value theory investigates the nature, sources, and types of values in general.<ref name="auto2"/> Some philosophers understand value theory as a subdiscipline of ethics. This is based on the idea that what people should do is affected by value considerations but not necessarily limited to them.<ref name="auto7"/> Another view sees ethics as a subdiscipline of value theory. This outlook follows the idea that ethics is concerned with moral values affecting what people can control, whereas value theory examines a broader range of values, including those beyond anyone's control.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Schroeder|2021|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Orsi|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA6 6–7]}} | {{harvnb|Bahm|1993|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jqSRrmtQ_WoC&pg=PA4 4]}} | {{harvnb|Cowan|2020|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=-2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA4 4]}} | {{harvnb|Hurka|2006|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA357 357–358]}}}}</ref> Some perspectives contrast ethics and value theory, asserting that the [[Normativity|normative]] concepts examined by ethics are distinct from the evaluative concepts examined by value theory.<ref name="auto4"/> [[Axiological ethics]] is a subfield of ethics examining the nature and role of values from a moral perspective, with particular interest in determining which ends are worth pursuing.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Findlay|1970|pp=1–2, 4}} | {{harvnb|Kupperman|2005|pp=73–74}} }}</ref> The ethical theory of [[consequentialism]] combines the perspectives of ethics and value theory, asserting that the rightness of an action depends on the value of its consequences. Consequentialists compare possible courses of action, saying that people should follow the one leading to the best overall consequences.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sinnott-Armstrong|2023|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Crisp|2005|pp=200–201}} | {{harvnb|Alexander|Moore|2021|loc=§ 1. Deontology's Foil: Consequentialism}} }}</ref> The overall consequences of an action are the totality of its effects, or how it impacts the world by starting a causal chain of events that would not have occurred otherwise.<ref>{{harvnb|Dorsey|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=d0D8DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA97 97–98]}}</ref> Distinct versions of consequentialism rely on different theories of the sources of value. [[Classical utilitarianism]], a prominent form of consequentialism, says that moral actions produce the greatest amount of [[pleasure]] for the greatest number of people. It combines a consequentialist outlook on right action with a [[Hedonism|hedonist]] outlook on pleasure as the only source of intrinsic value.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sinnott-Armstrong|2023|loc=§ 1. Classic Utilitarianism}} | {{harvnb|Chenneville|2017|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=yn06DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA5 5]}} | {{harvnb|Hearn|1971|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=0z_z0RYmr38C&pg=PA2 2]}} }}</ref> === Economics === {{main|Economics}} Economics is a [[social science]] studying how goods and services are produced, distributed, and consumed, both from the perspective of individual agents and societal systems.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pape|2000|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=fYzMz3UlyaMC&pg=PA7 7]}} | {{harvnb|Welch|Welch|2009|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=O5i-d3thv-4C&pg=PA4 4]}} | {{harvnb|Mukherjee|Mukherjee|Ghose|2013|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=iVKja7n06iIC&pg=PA17 17]}} }}</ref> Economists view evaluations as a driving force underlying economic activity. They use the notion of [[economic value]] and related evaluative concepts to understand decision-making processes, resource allocation, and the impact of policies. The economic value or benefit of a [[commodity]] is the advantage it provides to an [[economic agent]], often measured in terms of what people are [[Willingness to pay|willing to pay]] for it.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pirgmaier|2021|p=1}} | {{harvnb|Young|Loomis|2014|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=brDcAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA289 289]}} | {{harvnb|Turner|Georgiou|Clark|Brouwer|2004|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=coz0lmhjZAYC&pg=PA50 50]}} }}</ref> Economic theories of value are frameworks to explain how economic value arises and which factors influence it. Prominent frameworks include the classical [[labor theory of value]] and the neo-classical [[marginal theory of value]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pirgmaier|2021|pp=1, 8–9}} | {{harvnb|Ayres|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=GW28EAAAQBAJ&pg=PA104 104]}} }}</ref> The labor theory, initially developed by the economists [[Adam Smith]] and [[David Ricardo]], distinguishes between [[use value]]—the utility or satisfaction a commodity provides—and [[exchange value]]—the proportion at which one commodity can be exchanged with another.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pirgmaier|2021|p=2}} | {{harvnb|Fraser|2009}} | {{harvnb|Rogers|Castree|Kitchin|2013}} }}</ref> It focuses on exchange value, which it says is determined by the [[Socially necessary labour time|amount of labor required to produce the commodity]]. In its simplest form, it directly correlates exchange value to labor time. For example, if the time needed to hunt a deer is twice the time needed to hunt a beaver then one deer is worth two beavers.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pirgmaier|2021|pp=2–3}} | {{harvnb|Ayres|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=GW28EAAAQBAJ&pg=PA104 104]}} }}</ref> The philosopher [[Karl Marx]] extended the labor theory of value in various ways. He introduced the concept of [[surplus value]], which goes beyond the time and resources invested to explain how [[Capitalism|capitalists]] can profit from the labor of their employees.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Moseley|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=43m-EAAAQBAJ&pg=PA48 48]}} | {{harvnb|Pirgmaier|2021|pp=7–8}} }}</ref> The marginal theory of value focuses on consumption rather than production. It says that the utility of a commodity is the source of its value. Specifically, it is interested in [[marginal utility]], the additional satisfaction gained from consuming one more unit of the commodity. Marginal utility often diminishes if many units have already been consumed, leading to a decrease in the exchange value of commodities that are abundantly available.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Pirgmaier|2021|p=3}} | {{harvnb|Black|Hashimzade|Myles|2009}} }}</ref> Both the labor theory and the marginal theory were later challenged by the [[Piero Sraffa#Production of Commodities by Means of Commodities|Sraffian theory of value]].<ref>{{harvnb|Ayres|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=GW28EAAAQBAJ&pg=PA104 104]}}</ref> === Sociology === {{main|Sociology}} Sociology studies social behavior, relationships, institutions, and society at large.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Bhushan|Sachdeva|2012|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=qgZFB3UOuNkC&pg=PA4 4]}} | {{harvnb|Sharma|1996|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=QQ1nBcV_zCMC&pg=PA10 10]}} }}</ref> In their analyses and explanations of these phenomena, some sociologists use the concept of values to understand issues like [[social cohesion]] and [[Social conflict|conflict]], the norms and practices people follow, and [[collective action]]. They usually understand values as subjective attitudes possessed by individuals and shared in social groups. According to this view, values are beliefs or priorities about goals worth pursuing that guide people to act in certain ways. For example, societies that value education may invest substantial resources to ensure high-quality schooling. This subjective conception of values as aspects of individuals and social groups contrasts with the objective conceptions of values more prominent in economics, which understand values as aspects of commodities.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Karp|2000|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=33–34, 37, 39–40}} | {{harvnb|Tormos|2019|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=u8y8DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA11 11]}} }}</ref> Shared values can help unite people in the pursuit of a common cause, fostering social cohesion. Value differences, by contrast, may divide people into antagonistic groups that promote conflicting projects. Some sociologists employ value research to predict how people will behave. Given the observation that someone values the environment, they may conclude that this person is more likely to [[recycle]] or support pro-environmental legislation.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Karp|2000|loc=Lead section, § Social Values}} | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=39–40, 47}} }}</ref> One approach to this type of research uses [[Values scale|value scales]], such as the [[Rokeach Value Survey]] and the [[Theory of basic human values|Schwartz theory of basic human values]], to measure the value outlook of individuals and groups.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Karp|2000|loc=Lead section, § The Rokeach Tradition, § The Schwartz Scale of Values}} | {{harvnb|Tormos|2019|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=u8y8DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA13 13–15]}} }}</ref> === Anthropology === {{main|Anthropology}} Anthropology also studies human behavior and societies but does not limit itself to contemporary social structures, extending its focus to humanity both past and present.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sutton|2021|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=pjAXEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA5 5]}} | {{harvnb|Fluehr-Lobban|2013|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=LUJPAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA158 158]}} }}</ref> Similar to sociologists, many anthropologists understand values as social representations of goals worth pursuing. For them, values are embedded in mental structures associated with culture and ideology about what is desirable. A slightly different approach in anthropology focuses on the practical side of values, holding that values are constantly created through human activity.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Robbins|2023|loc=§ Foundations of Value Theory, § A Third Approach to Value}} | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=53–54, 56, 58}} }}</ref> [[Anthropological theories of value|Anthropological value theorists]] use values to compare cultures.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=3, 55}} | {{harvnb|Robbins|2023|loc=§ Foundations of Value Theory}} | {{harvnb|Sykes|2016|loc=§ Introduction}} }}</ref> They can be employed to examine similarities as universal concerns present in every society. For example, anthropologist [[Clyde Kluckhohn]] and sociologist [[Fred Strodtbeck]] proposed a set of value orientations found in every culture.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|p=54}} | {{harvnb|Robbins|2023|loc=§ Foundations of Value Theory}} }}</ref> Values can also be used to analyze differences between cultures and value changes within a culture. Anthropologist [[Louis Dumont]] followed this idea, suggesting that the cultural meaning systems in distinct societies differ in their value priorities. He argued that values are ordered hierarchically around a set of paramount values that trump all other values. For example, Dumont analyzed the [[Caste system in India|traditional Indian caste system]] as a cultural hierarchy based on the value of purity, extending from the pure [[Brahmins]] to the "[[Untouchability|untouchable]]" [[Dalits]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Robbins|2023|loc=§ Foundations of Value Theory}} | {{harvnb|Sykes|2016|loc=§ Introduction, § General Overviews}} | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=3, 61–62}} }}</ref> The contrast between [[individualism and collectivism]] is an influential topic in cross-cultural value research. Individualism promotes values associated with the [[autonomy]] of individuals, such as [[self-directedness]], independence, and the fulfillment of personal goals. Collectivism gives priority to group-related values, like cooperation, [[conformity]], and foregoing personal advantages for the sake of collective benefits. As a rough simplification, it is often suggested that individualism is more prominent in [[Western culture]]s, whereas collectivism is more commonly observed in [[Eastern culture]]s.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Karp|2000|loc=§ Individualism and Collectivism}} | {{harvnb|Fatehi|Priestley|Taasoobshirazi|2020|pp=7–9}} | {{harvnb|Kim|2002|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Bsr3h16zrkwC&pg=PA22 22]}} | {{harvnb|Serna|Martínez|2022|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=tIedEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA423 423]}} }}</ref> === Psychology === {{main|Psychology}} As the study of [[Mind|mental phenomena]] and behavior, psychology contrasts with sociology and anthropology by focusing more on the perspective of individuals than the broader social and cultural contexts.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|p=4}} | {{harvnb|Woodworth|Marquis|2014|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=IXPpAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA5 5]}} }}</ref> Psychologists tend to understand values as abstract [[Motivation|motivational]] goals or general principles about what matters.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=7–8}} | {{harvnb|Schwartz|Cieciuch|2016|pp=106–107}} }}</ref> From this perspective, values differ from specific plans and [[intention]]s since they are stable evaluative tendencies not bound to concrete situations.<ref>{{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=14, 19–20}}</ref> Various psychological theories of values establish a close link between an individual's evaluative outlook and their [[personality]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=4, 11–12}} | {{harvnb|Schwartz|Cieciuch|2016|p=106}} }}</ref> An early theory, formulated by psychologists [[Philip E. Vernon]] and [[Gordon Allport]], understands personality as a collection of aspects unified by a coherent [[value system]]. It distinguishes between six personality types corresponding to the value spheres of theory, economy, aesthetics, society, politics, and religion. For example, people with theoretical personalities place special importance on the [[value of knowledge]] and the discovery of [[truth]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=11–12}} | {{harvnb|Schwartz|Cieciuch|2016|p=106}} }}</ref> Influenced by Vernon and Allport, psychologist [[Milton Rokeach]] conceptualized values as enduring beliefs about what goals and conduct are preferable. He divided values into the categories of instrumental and terminal values. He thought that a central aspect of personality lies in how people prioritize the values within each category.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=12–13}} | {{harvnb|Schwartz|Cieciuch|2016|pp=106–107}} }}</ref> Psychologist [[Shalom Schwartz]] refined this approach by linking values to emotion and motivation. He explored how value rankings affect decisions in which the values of different options conflict.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Steinert|2023|pp=13–15}} | {{harvnb|Schwartz|Cieciuch|2016|pp=107–108}} }}</ref> == History == The origin of value theory lies in the [[ancient period]], with early reflections on the good life and the ends worth pursuing.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|pp=636–637}} | {{harvnb|Li|2014|p=3}} | {{harvnb|Chang|2001|pp=68–69}} }}</ref> [[Socrates]] ({{circa|469–399 BCE}})<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=178}}</ref> identified the highest good as the right combination of [[knowledge]], [[pleasure]], and [[virtue]], holding that active inquiry is associated with pleasure while knowledge of the Good leads to virtuous action.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sharma|1991|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=5tSOV8W1aCUC&pg=PA27 27–28]}} | {{harvnb|Devettere|2002|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=sPwqJHoBD5EC&pg=PA33 33–34]}} | {{harvnb|Heinaman|2016|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jEYlDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA123 123–124]}} | {{harvnb|Heathwood|2015|p=153}} }}</ref> [[Plato]] ({{circa|428–347 BCE|lk=no}})<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=156}}</ref> conceived [[the Good]] as a universal and changeless idea. It is the highest form in his [[theory of forms]], acting as the source of all other forms and the foundation of reality and knowledge.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Honderich|2005|p=349}} | {{harvnb|Bahm|1993|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jqSRrmtQ_WoC&pg=PA112 112]}} }}</ref> [[Aristotle]] (384–322 BCE)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=13}}</ref> saw [[eudaimonia]] as the highest good and ultimate goal of human life. He understood eudaimonia as a form of happiness or flourishing achieved through the exercise of virtues in accordance with [[reason]], leading to the full realization of human potential.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hiles|2008|pp=52–53}} | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|p=639}} | {{harvnb|Crisp|2005a|p=349}} }}</ref> [[Epicurus]] ({{circa|341–271 BCE|lk=no}}) proposed a nuanced [[egoistic]] hedonism, stating that personal pleasure is the greatest good while recommending moderation to avoid the negative effects of excessive desires and anxiety about the future.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|O'Keefe|loc=§ 5. Ethics}} | {{harvnb|Gaskin|2005|p=258}} | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|p=639}} }}</ref> According to the [[Stoicism|Stoics]], a virtuous life following nature and reason is the highest good. They thought that self-mastery and [[rationality]] lead to a pleasant [[Apatheia|equanimity]] independent of external circumstances.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Durand|Shogry|Baltzly|2023|loc=§ 4. Ethics}} | {{harvnb|Pigliucci|loc=§ 3. The Third Topos: Ethics, § 4. Apatheia and the Stoic Treatment of Emotions}} | {{harvnb|McDonald|2021|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Z5JOEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA38 38]}} }}</ref> Influenced by Plato, [[Plotinus]] ({{circa|204/5–270 CE|lk=no}}) held that the Good is the ultimate principle of reality from which everything emanates. For him, [[evil]] is not a distinct opposing principle but merely a deficiency or absence of [[being]] resulting from a missing connection to the Good.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Bahm|1993|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jqSRrmtQ_WoC&pg=PA103 103]}} | {{harvnb|Darr|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=HgvYEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA108 108]}} | {{harvnb|Emilsson|1998|loc=Lead section}} }}</ref> [[File:Half Portraits of the Great Sage and Virtuous Men of Old - Confucius.jpg|thumb|upright=.7|alt=Painting of a man with a long beard and mustache wearing traditional Chinese scholarly robes|[[Confucius]] viewed [[Ren (philosophy)|general benevolence towards humanity]] as the supreme virtue.<ref name="auto10">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Ebrey|2010|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=vr81YoYK0c4C&pg=PA43 43]}} | {{harvnb|Sim|2015|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=0WLABgAAQBAJ&pg=PA64 64, 74]}} | {{harvnb|Richey|loc=§ 6. Self-cultivation}} | {{harvnb|Littlejohn|loc=§ 1b. Confucius (551-479 B.C.E.) of the Analects}} }}</ref>]] In ancient [[Indian philosophy]], the idea that people are trapped in a [[Samsara|cycle of rebirths]] arose around 600 BCE.<ref>{{harvnb|Borgolte|2019|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=8cy8DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA97 97]}}</ref> Many traditions adopted it, arguing that liberation from this cycle is the highest good.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sharma|1999|p=230}} | {{harvnb|Bartley|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=t28xEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA37 37–38, 136]}} }}</ref> [[Hindu philosophy]] distinguishes the [[Puruṣārtha|four fundamental values]] of [[dharma|duty]], [[artha|economic wealth]], [[kāma|sensory pleasure]], and [[mokṣa|liberation]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Ranganathan|loc=§ 1a.iii. Puruṣārthas : dharma, artha, kāma and mokṣa}} | {{harvnb|Sharma|1999|pp=223–225, 230}} | {{harvnb|Bailey|2011}} }}</ref> Many [[Āstika|Hindu schools of thought]] prioritize the value of liberation.<ref>{{harvnb|Sharma|1999|p=230}}</ref> A similar outlook is found in ancient [[Buddhist philosophy]], starting between the sixth and the fifth centuries BCE, where the cessation of [[Duḥkha|suffering]] through the attainment of [[Nirvana]] is considered the ultimate goal.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wilson|2010}} | {{harvnb|Lougheed|2020|pp=243–244 }} | {{harvnb|Prasad|2007|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=6GPxDwAAQBAJ&pg=PR13 xiii–xiv, 21, 23]}}}}</ref> In [[ancient China]], [[Confucius]] ({{circa|551–479 BCE|lk=no}})<ref>{{harvnb|Littlejohn|loc=§ 1b. Confucius (551-479 B.C.E.) of the Analects}}</ref> explored the role of [[self-cultivation]] in leading a virtuous life, viewing [[Ren (philosophy)|general benevolence towards humanity]] as the supreme virtue.<ref name="auto10"/> In comparing the highest virtue to water, [[Laozi]] (6th century BCE){{efn|This period is given in traditional sources. Some contemporary scholars have suggested later dates or questioned whether there was a single person by that name.<ref>{{harvnb|Chan|2018|loc=Lead section, § 2. Date and Authorship of the ''Laozi''}}</ref>}} emphasized the importance of living in harmony with the [[Tao|natural order of the universe]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Assandri|2021|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=Ui5CEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA70 70–71]}} | {{harvnb|Slingerland|2007|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=gSReaja3V3IC&pg=PA77 77]}} | {{harvnb|Chan|2018|loc=Lead section}} | {{harvnb|Lobel|2017|p=297}} }}</ref> Religious teachings influenced value theory in the [[medieval period]]. Early [[Christian philosophy|Christian thinkers]], such as [[Augustine of Hippo]] (354–430 CE),<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=16}}</ref> adapted the theories of Plato and Plotinus into a religious framework. They identified God as the ultimate source of existence and goodness, seeing evil as a mere lack or privation of good.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Bahm|1993|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=jqSRrmtQ_WoC&pg=PA112 112]}} | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|p=639}} | {{harvnb|Darr|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=HgvYEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA108 108]}} }}</ref> Drawing on [[Aristotelianism]], Christian philosopher [[Thomas Aquinas]] (1224–1274 CE)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=185}}</ref> said that communion with the divine, achieved through a [[beatific vision]] of God, is the [[Summum bonum|highest end]] of humans.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Wieland|2002|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=PtLyH02x60MC&pg=PA59 59]}} | {{harvnb|Zagzebski|2004a|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=GbcuCf9TlDgC&pg=PA350 350]}} | {{harvnb|Peterson|2008|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=C6u8kXWTjwwC&pg=PA235 235]}} }}</ref> In [[Islamic philosophy|Arabic–Persian philosophy]], [[Avicenna]] (980–1037 CE)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=19}}</ref> regarded the intellect as the highest human faculty. He thought that a contemplative life prepares humans for the greatest good, which is only attained in the afterlife when humans are free from bodily distractions.<ref>{{harvnb|McGinnis|2010|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=M28EjkCdFecC&pg=PA209 209–210]}}</ref> In Chinese thought, the early [[neo-Confucian]] philosopher [[Han Yu]] (768–824 CE) identified the sage as an ideal role model who, through self-cultivation, achieves personal integrity expressed in harmony between theory and action in daily life.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Berthrong|loc=§ 3. The Emergence of Neo-Confucianism}} | {{harvnb|Hartman|1998}} }}</ref> In the [[Early modern philosophy|early modern period]], [[Thomas Hobbes]] (1588–1679)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=88}}</ref> understood values as subjective phenomena that depend on a person's interests and examined mutual interests and benefits as a key principle of political decisions.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hardin|2009|pp=6–7, 12, 16, 173, 177–179}} | {{harvnb|Abelson|Nielsen|2006|loc=§ Hobbes}} | {{harvnb|Cowan|2020|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=-2jDDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA197 197, 210–211, 220]}} }}</ref> [[David Hume]] (1711–1776)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=91}}</ref> agreed with Hobbes's subjectivism, exploring [[Is–ought problem|how values differ from objective facts]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hardin|2009|pp=29, 51, 173, 177}} | {{harvnb|Li|2014|p=3}} }}</ref> [[Immanuel Kant]] (1724–1804)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=105}}</ref> asserted that the highest good is happiness in proportion to moral virtue. He emphasized the primacy of virtue by respecting the moral law and the inherent value of people, adding that moral virtue is ideally, but not always, accompanied by personal happiness.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Engstrom|1992|p=747}} | {{harvnb|Johnson|Cureton|2024|loc=§ 1. Aims and Methods of Moral Philosophy, § 2. Good Will, Moral Worth and Duty}} | {{harvnb|Direk|2014|pp=373–374}} }}</ref> [[Jeremy Bentham]] (1748–1832)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=25}}</ref> and [[John Stuart Mill]] (1806–1873)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=132}}</ref> formulated [[classical utilitarianism]], combining a [[hedonist]] theory about value with a [[consequentialist]] theory about right action.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|p=639}} | {{harvnb|Sinnott-Armstrong|2023|loc=§ 1. Classic Utilitarianism}} | {{harvnb|Chenneville|2017|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=yn06DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA5 5]}} | {{harvnb|Hearn|1971|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=0z_z0RYmr38C&pg=PA2 2]}} }}</ref> [[Hermann Lotze]] (1817–1881)<ref>{{harvnb|Woodward|2015|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=L4dsCQAAQBAJ&pg=PR1 i]}}</ref> developed a philosophy of values, holding that values make the world meaningful as an ordered whole centered around goodness.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Sullivan|2023|loc=§ 5.3 Value Theory}} | {{harvnb|Li|2014|p=3}} | {{harvnb|Sullivan|1998|loc=§ 4. Metaphysics}} | {{harvnb|Milkov|loc=§ 3a. Ethics}} | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|p=636}} }}</ref> Influenced by Lotze, the [[neo-Kantian]] philosopher [[Wilhelm Windelband]] (1848–1915)<ref>{{harvnb|Dafermos|2018|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=uC1bDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA20 20]}}</ref> understood philosophy as a theory of values, claiming that universal values determine the principles that all subjects should follow, including the norms of knowledge and action.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Heis|2018|loc=§ 3.1 Conception of Philosophy: Philosophy as Theory of Value}} | {{harvnb|Kinzel|2024|loc=§ 2. From Kant to the Philosophy of Values}} | {{harvnb|Hiles|2008|p=52}} }}</ref> [[Friedrich Nietzsche]] (1844–1900)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=144}}</ref> held that values are human creations. He criticized traditional values in general and Christian values in particular, calling for a [[Transvaluation of values|revaluation of all values]] centered on life-affirmation, power, and excellence.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|pp=636, 639}} | {{harvnb|Li|2014|p=4}} | {{harvnb|Anderson|2024|loc=§ 3. Value Creation}} | {{harvnb|Hiles|2008|p=52}} | {{harvnb|Direk|2014|pp=374, 378}} }}</ref> [[File:G-H-von-Wright-1961 (cropped).jpg|thumb|upright=.7|alt=Black-and-white photo of a man with combed hair wearing a knit sweater over a dark shirt|[[G. H. von Wright]] analyzed and compared diverse types of goodness.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|pp=637–638}} | {{harvnb|Ylirisku|Arvola|2018|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=ed1ODwAAQBAJ&pg=PA53 53]}} }}</ref>]] In the early 20th century, [[Pragmatism|Pragmatist]] philosopher [[John Dewey]] (1859–1952)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=52}}</ref> defended axiological [[Naturalism (philosophy)|naturalism]]. He distinguished values from value judgments, adding that the skill of correct value assessment must be learned through experience.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hart|1971|pp=36–38}} | {{harvnb|Marcum|2008|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=1arGI9NZcAkC&pg=PA192 192]}} }}</ref>{{efn|[[Clarence Irving Lewis]] (1883–1964) accepted and further elaborated many of Dewey's insights.<ref>{{harvnb|Hart|1971|pp=37–38}}</ref>}} [[G. E. Moore]] (1873–1958)<ref>{{harvnb|Bunnin|Yu|2009|p=443}}</ref> developed and refined various axiological concepts, such as organic unity and the contrast between intrinsic and extrinsic value. He defended [[Ethical non-naturalism|non-naturalism]] about the nature of values and [[Ethical intuitionism|intuitionism]] about the knowledge of values.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Findlay|1970|pp=2, 37–38, 41}} | {{harvnb|Dancy|2004|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=_78SDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA165 165]}} | {{harvnb|Hart|1971|p=33}} }}</ref> [[W. D. Ross]] (1877–1971)<ref>{{harvnb|Kunnan|2020|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=IwgLEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA86 86]}}</ref> accepted and further elaborated on Moore's intuitionism, using it to formulate an axiological pluralism.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Mason|2023|loc=§ 1.1 Foundational and Non-foundational Pluralism}} | {{harvnb|Simpson|loc=Lead section, § 6. Ross’s Ethical Theory: Main Components and Principles}} | {{harvnb|Findlay|1970|p=2}} }}</ref>{{efn|Ross is primarily known for his deontological pluralism about different types of [[prima facie duties|''prima facie'' duties]], which is related but not identical to his axiological pluralism about different types of values.<ref>{{harvnb|Mason|2023|loc=§ 1.1 Foundational and Non-foundational Pluralism}}</ref>}} [[R. B. Perry]] (1876–1957)<ref>{{harvnb|Anderson|2013|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=SFVhEAAAQBAJ&pg=RA1-PA222 222]}}</ref> and [[David Prall|D. W. Prall]] (1886–1940)<ref>{{harvnb|Townsend|2006|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=GGgAAwAAQBAJ&pg=PR16 xvi]}}</ref> articulated systematic theories of value based on the idea that values originate in affective states such as interest and liking.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Hart|1971|p=31}} | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|p=637}} }}</ref> [[Robert S. Hartman]] (1910–1973)<ref>{{harvnb|Edwards|Hartman|2023|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=y8rAEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA173 173]}}</ref> developed formal axiology, saying that values measure the level to which a thing embodies its ideal concept.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Edwards|2021|pp=3–4}} | {{harvnb|Hartman|2011|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=1UX7DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA105 105–106]}} }}</ref> [[A. J. Ayer]] (1910–1989)<ref>{{harvnb|Tuboly|2021|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=R-oEEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA2 2]}}</ref> proposed anti-realism about values, arguing that [[Expressivism|value statements merely express]] the speaker's approval or disapproval.<ref>{{harvnb|Hart|1971|pp=34–35}}</ref> A different type of anti-realism, introduced by [[J. L. Mackie]] (1917–1981),<ref>{{harvnb|Bunnin|Yu|2009|p=406}}</ref> suggests that [[Error theory|all value assertions are false]] since no values exist.<ref>{{harvnb|Sayre-McCord|1988|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=-msmrkE-67IC&pg=PA11 11–12]}}</ref> [[G. H. von Wright]] (1916–2003)<ref>{{harvnb|Rosenkrantz|Hoffman|2011|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=DQW9nyBCClMC&pg=PA332 332]}}</ref> provided a [[conceptual analysis]] of the term ''good'' by distinguishing different meanings or varieties of goodness, such as the technical goodness of a good driver and the hedonic goodness of a good meal.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|pp=637–638}} | {{harvnb|Ylirisku|Arvola|2018|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=ed1ODwAAQBAJ&pg=PA53 53]}} }}</ref> In [[continental philosophy]], [[Franz Brentano]] (1838–1917)<ref>{{harvnb|Kriegel|2018|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=3e9IDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA2 2]}}</ref> formulated an early version of the fitting-attitude theory of value, saying that a thing is good if it is fitting to have a positive attitude towards it, such as love.<ref name="auto9">{{multiref | {{harvnb|Kriegel|2018|pp=[https://books.google.com/books?id=3e9IDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA10 10–11, 218, 221–222]}} | {{harvnb|Kriegel|2017|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=4kUlDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA12 12]}} }}</ref> In the 1890s, his students [[Alexius Meinong]] (1853–1920)<ref name="auto">{{harvnb|Kuijper|2022|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=2-FZEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA298 298]}}</ref> and [[Christian von Ehrenfels]] (1859–1932)<ref>{{harvnb|Zimmer|2017|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=wkQrDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA135 135]}}</ref> conceived the idea of a general theory of values.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|p=637}} | {{harvnb|Hart|1971|pp=30–31}} }}</ref> [[Edmund Husserl]] (1859–1938),<ref name="auto"/> another of Brentano's students, developed [[Phenomenology (philosophy)|phenomenology]] and applied this approach to the study of values.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|p=637}} | {{harvnb|Direk|2014|pp=371–372}} }}</ref> Following Husserl's approach, [[Max Scheler]] (1874–1928) and [[Nicolai Hartmann]] (1882–1950) each proposed a comprehensive system of [[axiological ethics]].<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|p=637}} | {{harvnb|Findlay|1970|p=2}} | {{harvnb|Hart|1971|p=32}} | {{harvnb|Direk|2014|pp=371–372}} | {{harvnb|Løgstrup|2020|p=[https://books.google.com/books?id=aurkDwAAQBAJ&pg=PR141 105]}} }}</ref> Asserting that values have objective reality, they explored how different value types form a hierarchy and examined the problems of value conflicts and right decisions from this hierarchical perspective.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Frankena|2006|pp=637–639}} | {{harvnb|Findlay|1970|p=2}} | {{harvnb|Hart|1971|p=32}} }}</ref> [[Martin Heidegger]] (1889–1976)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=83}}</ref> criticized value theory, claiming that it rests on a mistaken [[metaphysical]] perspective by understanding values as aspects of things.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Direk|2014|pp=372–373, 384–386}} | {{harvnb|Findlay|1970|pp=2–3}} | {{harvnb|Sullivan|2023|loc=§ 5.3 Value Theory}} }}</ref> [[Existentialist]] philosopher [[Jean-Paul Sartre]] (1905–1980)<ref>{{harvnb|Dehsen|2013|p=168}}</ref> suggested that values do not exist by themselves but are actively created, emphasizing the role of human [[freedom]], responsibility, and [[Authenticity (philosophy)|authenticity]] in the process.<ref>{{multiref | {{harvnb|Abelson|Nielsen|2006|pp=426–428}} | {{harvnb|Direk|2014|pp=384–385}} }}</ref> == References == === Notes === {{notelist}} === Citations === {{reflist}} === Sources === {{refbegin|30em}} * {{cite book |last1=Abelson |first1=Raziel |last2=Nielsen |first2=Kai |editor1-last=Borchert |editor1-first=Donald M. |title=Encyclopedia of Philosophy |volume=3 |date=2006 |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0-02-866072-1 |edition=2nd |chapter=Ethics, History of |pages=394–433 }} * {{cite web |last1=Alexander |first1=Larry |last2=Moore |first2=Michael |title=Deontological Ethics |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-deontological/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=30 December 2023 |date=2021 |archive-date=June 20, 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230620084241/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-deontological/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Anderson |first1=Douglas R. |editor1-last=Schrift |editor1-first=Alan D. |title=The History of Continental Philosophy |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-74049-2 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=SFVhEAAAQBAJ&pg=RA1-PA222 |language=en |chapter=Peirce: Pragmatism and Nature after Hegel |volume=2 |date=2013 |pages=217–238 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Anderson |first1=R. Lanier |title=Friedrich Nietzsche |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nietzsche/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=18 September 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=4 September 2018 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180904231138/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/nietzsche/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Arneson |first1=Pat |chapter=Axiology |editor-last1=Littlejohn |editor-first1=Stephen W. |editor-last2=Foss |editor-first2=Karen A. |title=Encyclopedia of Communication Theory |date=2009 |publisher=Sage |isbn=978-1-4129-5937-7 |language=en |pages=69–73 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Assandri |first1=Friederike |title=The Daode Jing Commentary of Cheng Xuanying: Daoism, Buddhism, and the Laozi in the Tang Dynasty |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-087645-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Ui5CEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA70 |language=en |date=2021 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Audi |first1=Robert |title=The Good in the Right: A Theory of Intuition and Intrinsic Value |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=978-1-4008-2607-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=S_RrKGcgSewC&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2004 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Ayres |first1=Robert U. |title=The History and Future of Economics |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-031-26208-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GW28EAAAQBAJ&pg=PA104 |language=en |date=2023 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Bahm |first1=Archie J. |title=Axiology: The Science of Values |publisher=Rodopi |isbn=978-90-5183-519-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=jqSRrmtQ_WoC&pg=PA104 |language=en |date=1993 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Bailey |first1=Greg |title=Puruṣārthas |url=https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195399318/obo-9780195399318-0044.xml |website=Oxford Bibliographies |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=20 September 2024 |language=en |doi=10.1093/obo/9780195399318-0044 |date=2011 |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922163611/https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195399318/obo-9780195399318-0044.xml |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Bartley |first1=Christopher |title=Indian Philosophy A–Z |publisher=Edinburgh University Press |isbn=978-0-7486-8084-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=t28xEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA37 |language=en |date=2020 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Berthrong |first1=John H. |title=Neo-Confucian Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/neo-confucian-philosophy/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=17 September 2024 |archive-date=6 February 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240206021859/https://iep.utm.edu/neo-confucian-philosophy/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Bhushan |first1=Vidya |last2=Sachdeva |first2=D. R. |title=Fundamentals of Sociology |publisher=Pearson Education India |isbn=978-81-317-9967-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=qgZFB3UOuNkC&pg=PA4 |language=en |date=2012 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Black |first1=John |last2=Hashimzade |first2=Nigar |last3=Myles |first3=Gareth |title=A Dictionary of Economics |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-923704-3 |url=https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/oi/authority.20110803100133867 |language=en |chapter=Marginal Utility |date=2009 |access-date=2024-09-14 |archive-date=2024-09-12 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240912090555/https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/oi/authority.20110803100133867 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Borgolte |first1=Michael |title=World History as the History of Foundations, 3000 BCE to 1500 CE |publisher=Brill |isbn=978-90-04-41508-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=8cy8DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA97 |language=en |date=2019 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite journal |last1=Bradley |first1=Ben |title=Two Concepts of Intrinsic Value |journal=Ethical Theory and Moral Practice |volume=9 |issue=2 |doi=10.1007/s10677-006-9009-7 |date=2006 |pages=111–130 }} * {{cite web |last1=Brown |first1=James Robert |last2=Fehige |first2=Yiftach |title=Thought Experiments |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/ |website=Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=29 October 2021 |date=2019 |archive-date=21 November 2017 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20171121022040/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/thought-experiment/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Bunnin |first1=Nicholas |last2=Yu |first2=Jiyuan |title=The Blackwell Dictionary of Western Philosophy |date=2009 |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-1-4051-9112-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=M7ZFEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA134 |language=en |access-date=January 3, 2024 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Chan |first1=Alan |title=Laozi |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/laozi/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=20 September 2024 |date=2018 |archive-date=23 May 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230523173756/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/laozi/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite journal |last1=Chan |first1=Kai MA |last2=Gould |first2=Rachelle K |last3=Pascual |first3=Unai |title=Editorial overview: Relational Values: What Are They, and What's the Fuss about? |journal=Current Opinion in Environmental Sustainability |volume=35 |doi=10.1016/j.cosust.2018.11.003 |date=2018 |pages=A1–A7 |bibcode=2018COES...35A...1C |hdl=10810/47635 |hdl-access=free }} * {{cite book |last1=Chang |first1=Jiang |title=The Future of Value Inquiry |publisher=Brill |isbn=978-90-04-49451-0 |url=https://brill.com/display/book/9789004494510/B9789004494510_s011.xml |language=en |chapter=Axiology and Ethics: Past, Present, and Future |date=2001 |access-date=2024-09-21 |archive-date=2024-04-15 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240415171436/https://brill.com/display/book/9789004494510/B9789004494510_s011.xml |url-status=live |pages=67–73 }} * {{cite book |last1=Chappell |first1=Timothy |editor1-last=Kirchin |editor1-first=Simon |title=Thick concepts |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-967234-9 |edition=1st |chapter=10. There Are No Thin Concepts |date=2013 |pages=182–196 }} * {{cite book |last1=Chenneville |first1=Tiffany |editor1-last=Liston |editor1-first=Delores D. |editor2-last=Rahimi |editor2-first=Regina |title=Promoting Social Justice through the Scholarship of Teaching and Learning |publisher=Indiana University Press |isbn=978-0-253-03132-7 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=yn06DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA5 |language=en |chapter=Ethics and Social Justice: A Review of Theoretical Frameworks and Pedagogical Considerations |date=2017 |pages=3–14}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Cherniss |first1=Joshua |last2=Hardy |first2=Henry |title=Isaiah Berlin |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/berlin/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=9 September 2024 |date=2023 |archive-date=29 June 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230629031649/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/berlin/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Chrisman |first1=Matthew |title=What is this Thing Called Metaethics? |publisher=Taylor & Francis |isbn=978-1-315-43832-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=JiklDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA79 |language=en |date=2016 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Cowan |first1=Steven B. |editor1-last=Cowan |editor1-first=Steven B. |title=Problems in Value Theory: An Introduction to Contemporary Debates |publisher=Bloomsbury Publishing |isbn=978-1-350-14741-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=_2jDDwAAQBAJ |language=en |date=2020 |chapter=Introduction to Part One |pages=17–27}} * {{cite book |last1=Crisp |first1=Roger |chapter=Deontological Ethics |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |pages=200–201}} * {{cite book |last1=Crisp |first1=Roger |chapter=Good, Greatest |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005a |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |page=349}} * {{cite book |last1=Crisp |first1=Roger |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |date=2011 |publisher=Routledge |url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/overview/ethics/v-2 |language=en |chapter=Ethics |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-L132-2 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |access-date=January 7, 2024 |archive-date=August 1, 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230801214524/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/overview/ethics/v-2 |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |last1=Crisp |first1=Roger |title=Well-Being |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/well-being/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=15 December 2024 |date=2021 }} * {{cite book |last1=Crosby |first1=Donald A. |title=The Specter of the Absurd: Sources and Criticisms of Modern Nihilism |publisher=SUNY Press |isbn=978-0-88706-719-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9VnPgFiW0CIC&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=1988 }} * {{cite book |last1=Crosby |first1=Donald A. |chapter=Nihilism |chapter-url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/nihilism/v-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |language=en |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-N037-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 }} * {{cite book |last1=Cullity |first1=Garrett |editor1-last=Hirose |editor1-first=Iwao |editor2-last=Olson |editor2-first=Jonas |title=The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-022143-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=Neutral and Relative Value |date=2015 |pages=96–116}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Dabbagh |first1=Hossein |title=The Moral Epistemology of Intuitionism: Neuroethics and Seeming States |publisher=Bloomsbury Publishing |isbn=978-1-350-29758-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=jwuHEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA53 |language=en |date=2022 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Dafermos |first1=Manolis |title=Rethinking Cultural-Historical Theory: A Dialectical Perspective to Vygotsky |publisher=Springer Nature Singapore |isbn=978-981-13-0191-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uC1bDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA20 |language=en |date=2018 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Dancy |first1=Jonathan |title=Ethics Without Principles |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-927002-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=_78SDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2004 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Darr |first1=Ryan |title=The Best Effect: Theology and the Origins of Consequentialism |publisher=University of Chicago Press |isbn=978-0-226-82999-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=HgvYEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA108 |language=en |date=2023 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Davis |first1=Zachary |last2=Steinbock |first2=Anthony |title=Max Scheler |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scheler/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=8 September 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922163537/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scheler/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=de Bres |first1=Helena |editor1-last=Mandle |editor1-first=Jon |editor2-last=Reidy |editor2-first=David A. |title=The Cambridge Rawls Lexicon |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-19294-1 |url=https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/abs/cambridge-rawls-lexicon/hedonism/602FBE3D4ACFED4422C43BCCBA3BAB48 |chapter=Hedonism |date=2014 |access-date=2024-09-09 |archive-date=2024-09-22 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164642/https://www.cambridge.org/core/books/abs/cambridge-rawls-lexicon/hedonism/602FBE3D4ACFED4422C43BCCBA3BAB48 |url-status=live |pages=336–338 }} * {{cite book |last1=De Haan |first1=Daniel D. |editor1-last=Ramos |editor1-first=Alice M. |title=Beauty and the Good: Recovering the Classical Tradition from Plato to Duns Scotus |publisher=CUA Press |isbn=978-0-8132-3353-6 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=a5EHEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA302 |language=en |chapter=Beauty and Aesthetic Perception in Thomas Aquinas |date=2020 |pages=288–318 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Dehsen |first1=Christian von |title=Philosophers and Religious Leaders |date=2013 |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-135-95102-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=cU7cAAAAQBAJ |language=en }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=DeLapp |first1=Kevin M. |title=Metaethics |url=https://iep.utm.edu/metaethi/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=19 December 2023 |archive-date=January 23, 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240123102700/https://iep.utm.edu/metaethi/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=DeNicola |first1=Daniel R. |title=Moral Philosophy: A Contemporary Introduction |publisher=Broadview Press |isbn=978-1-77048-704-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=_sp6DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA267 |language=en |date=2019 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Devettere |first1=Raymond J. |title=Introduction to Virtue Ethics: Insights of the Ancient Greeks |publisher=Georgetown University Press |isbn=978-1-58901-817-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=sPwqJHoBD5EC&pg=PA33 |language=en |date=2002 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite journal |last1=Direk |first1=Zeynep |title=Phenomenology and Ethics: From Value Theory to an Ethics of Responsibility |journal=Studia Phaenomenologica |volume=14 |doi=10.5840/studphaen20141418 |date=2014 |pages=371–393 |url=http://cdm21054.contentdm.oclc.org/cdm/ref/collection/IR/id/5653 |access-date=2024-09-22 |archive-date=2024-09-22 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922163541/https://cdm21054.contentdm.oclc.org/digital/collection/IR/id/5653 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Dorsey |first1=Dale |editor1-last=Portmore |editor1-first=Douglas W. |title=The Oxford Handbook of Consequentialism |date=2020 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-090534-7 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=d0D8DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA95 |language=en |chapter=Consequences |access-date=January 3, 2024 |pages=93–112}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Durand |first1=Marion |last2=Shogry |first2=Simon |last3=Baltzly |first3=Dirk |title=Stoicism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/stoicism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=20 September 2024 |date=2023 |archive-date=29 September 2018 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180929031321/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/stoicism/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Ebrey |first1=Patricia Buckley |title=The Cambridge Illustrated History of China |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-12433-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vr81YoYK0c4C&pg=PA43 |language=en |date=2010 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Edwards |first1=Rem B. |title=Formal Axiology and Its Critics |publisher=Brill |isbn=978-90-04-49596-8 |url=https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1163/j.ctv20dsb9p.5 |language=en |chapter=1. Introduction |date=2021 |pages=1–8 |jstor=10.1163/j.ctv20dsb9p.5 |access-date=2024-09-09 |archive-date=2024-09-08 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240908084452/https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1163/j.ctv20dsb9p.5 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Edwards |first1=Rem |last2=Hartman |first2=Robert S. |editor1-last=Poff |editor1-first=Deborah C. |editor2-last=Michalos |editor2-first=Alex C. |title=Encyclopedia of Business and Professional Ethics |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-030-22767-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=y8rAEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA173 |language=en |date=2023 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Emilsson |first1=Eyjólfur Kjalar |chapter=Plotinus (AD 204/5–70) |url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/biographical/plotinus-ad-204-5-70/v-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=20 September 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-A090-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 }} * {{cite journal |last1=Engstrom |first1=Stephen |title=The Concept of the Highest Good in Kant's Moral Theory |journal=Philosophy and Phenomenological Research |volume=52 |issue=4 |doi=10.2307/2107910 |date=1992 |pages=747–780 |jstor=2107910 }} * {{cite journal |last1=Fatehi |first1=Kamal |last2=Priestley |first2=Jennifer L |last3=Taasoobshirazi |first3=Gita |title=The Expanded View of Individualism and Collectivism: One, Two, or Four Dimensions? |journal=International Journal of Cross Cultural Management |volume=20 |issue=1 |doi=10.1177/1470595820913077 |date=2020 |pages=7–24 }} * {{cite book |last1=Findlay |first1=John Niemeyer |title=Axiological Ethics |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0-333-00269-8 |language=en |date=1970 }} * {{cite book |last1=FitzPatrick |first1=William J. |editor1-last=Brady |editor1-first=Michael |title=New Waves in Metaethics |date=2011 |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |isbn=978-0-230-29489-9 |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057/9780230294899_2 |language=en |chapter=Ethical Non-Naturalism and Normative Properties |pages=7–35 |doi=10.1057/9780230294899_2 |access-date=December 22, 2023 |archive-date=February 1, 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240201103435/https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057/9780230294899_2 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Fluehr-Lobban |first1=Carolyn |title=Ethics and Anthropology: Ideas and Practice |publisher=AltaMira Press |isbn=978-0-7591-2188-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LUJPAQAAQBAJ&pg=PA158 |language=en |date=2013 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Frankena |first1=William K. |editor1-last=Borchert |editor1-first=Donald M. |title=Encyclopedia of Philosophy |volume=9 |date=2006 |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0-02-865789-9 |edition=2nd |chapter=Value and Valuation |pages=636–641}} * {{cite book |last1=Fraser |first1=Ian |title=The Concise Oxford Dictionary of Politics |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-920780-0 |url=https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/oi/authority.20110803095803703 |language=en |chapter=Exchange Value |date=2009 |access-date=2024-09-14 |archive-date=2024-09-22 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922163703/https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/oi/authority.20110803095803703 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Gaskin |first1=J. C. A. |chapter=Epicurus |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |page=258}} * {{cite book |last1=Gill |first1=Robin |title=Human Perfection, Transfiguration and Christian Ethics |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-009-47674-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=VMcFEQAAQBAJ&pg=PA85 |language=en |date=2024 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite journal |last1=Goffi |first1=Jean-Yves |last2=Roux |first2=Sophie |author2-link=Sophie Roux |title=On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment |journal=Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts |date=2011 |pages=165–191 |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/GOFOTV |publisher=Brill |doi=10.1163/ej.9789004201767.i-233.35 |isbn=978-90-04-20177-4 |s2cid=260640180 |access-date=18 April 2022 |archive-date=30 October 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20211030152653/https://philpapers.org/rec/GOFOTV |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Grenz |first1=Stanley J. |last2=Guretzki |first2=David |last3=Nordling |first3=Cherith Fee |title=Pocket Dictionary of Theological Terms |publisher=InterVarsity Press |isbn=978-0-8308-6707-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Iv-LCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA18 |language=en |date=2010 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Groothuis |first1=Douglas |editor1-last=Cowan |editor1-first=Steven B. |title=Problems in Value Theory: An Introduction to Contemporary Debates |publisher=Bloomsbury Publishing |isbn=978-1-350-14741-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=_2jDDwAAQBAJ |language=en |date=2020 |chapter=The Meaning of Life Is Found in God |pages=160–170}} * {{cite book |last1=Grünberg |first1=Ludwig |editor1-last=Tymieniecka |editor1-first=Anna-Teresa |title=The Moral Sense and its Foundational Significance: Self, Person, Historicity, Community: Phenomenological Praxeology and Psychiatry |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-009-0555-9 |language=en |chapter=The Phenomenology of Value and the Value of Phenomenology |date=1990 |pages=199–206}} * {{cite book |last1=Grünberg |first1=Ludwig |title=The Mystery of Values: Studies in Axiology |publisher=Rodopi |isbn=978-90-420-0670-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=cFsiNrHfN1AC&pg=PA11 |language=en |date=2000 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Gupta |first1=Abhik |title=Many Layers of Ecocentrism: Revering Life, Revering the Earth |publisher=Taylor & Francis |isbn=978-1-040-03034-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=U9EEEQAAQBAJ&pg=PA11 |language=en |date=2024 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Haines |first1=William |title=Consequentialism and Utilitarianism |url=https://iep.utm.edu/consequentialism-utilitarianism/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=28 December 2023 |archive-date=December 24, 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231224224334/https://iep.utm.edu/consequentialism-utilitarianism/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Hall |first1=Alicia |last2=Tiberius |first2=Valerie |editor1-last=Fletcher |editor1-first=Guy |title=The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-317-40265-7 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=zZdGCgAAQBAJ |language=en |chapter=Well-Being and Subject Dependence |date=2015 |pages=175–186}} * {{cite book |last1=Hardin |first1=Russell |title=David Hume: Moral and Political Theorist |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-161013-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=hud0ZH-heB0C&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2009 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |author1=HarperCollins |title=Value |url=https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=value&submit.x=58&submit.y=14 |website=The American Heritage Dictionary entry |publisher=HarperCollins |access-date=28 August 2024 |date=2022 |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164050/https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=value&submit.x=58&submit.y=14 |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |author1=HarperCollins |title=Truth Value |url=https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=truth+value&submit.x=58&submit.y=14 |website=The American Heritage Dictionary |publisher=HarperCollins |access-date=8 September 2024 |date=2022a |archive-date=8 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240908165435/https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=truth%20value&submit.x=58&submit.y=14 |url-status=live }} * {{cite journal |last1=Hart |first1=Samuel L. |title=Axiology - Theory of Values |journal=Philosophy and Phenomenological Research |volume=32 |issue=1 |doi=10.2307/2105883 |date=1971 |pages=29–41 |jstor=2105883 }} * {{cite book |last1=Hart |first1=James G. |editor-last1=Hart |editor-first1=James G. |editor-last2=Embree |editor-first2=Lester |title=Phenomenology of Values and Valuing |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-017-2608-5 |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-017-2608-5_1 |language=en |chapter=Introduction |series=Contributions to Phenomenology |date=1997 |volume=28 |pages=1–9 |doi=10.1007/978-94-017-2608-5_1 |access-date=2024-09-16 |archive-date=2024-09-15 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240915091912/https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-017-2608-5_1 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Hartman |first1=Charles |chapter=Han Yu (768–824) |url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/biographical/han-yu-768-824/v-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=17 September 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-G034-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=3 March 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240303091011/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/biographical/han-yu-768-824/v-1 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Hartman |first1=Robert S. |title=The Structure of Value: Foundations of Scientific Axiology |publisher=Wipf and Stock Publishers |isbn=978-1-7252-3067-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1UX7DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA104 |language=en |date=2011 |orig-date=1967 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Hearn |first1=Thomas K. |title=Studies in Utilitarianism |publisher=Appleton-Century-Crofts |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0z_z0RYmr38C&pg=PA2 |language=en |chapter=Introduction |date=1971 |oclc=149211 |pages=1–14}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Heathwood |first1=Chris |title=The International Encyclopedia of Ethics |publisher=Wiley |isbn=978-1-4051-8641-4 |edition=1st |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee780 |language=en |chapter=Hedonism |date=2013 |doi=10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee780 }} * {{cite book |last1=Heathwood |first1=Chris |editor1-last=Hirose |editor1-first=Iwao |editor2-last=Olson |editor2-first=Jonas |title=The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-022143-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=Monism and Pluralism about Value |date=2015 |pages=136–157 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Heathwood |first1=Chris |editor1-last=Fletcher |editor1-first=Guy |title=The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy of Well-Being |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-317-40264-0 |language=en |chapter=11. Desire-fulfillment Theory |date=2016 |pages=135–147}} * {{cite book |last1=Heinaman |first1=Robert |title=Plato and Aristotle's Ethics |publisher=Taylor & Francis |isbn=978-1-351-91076-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=jEYlDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA123 |language=en |date=2016 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Heis |first1=Jeremy |title=Neo-Kantianism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/neo-kantianism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=18 September 2024 |date=2018 |archive-date=6 August 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190806135557/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/neo-kantianism/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Hiles |first1=David R. |editor1-last=Given |editor1-first=Lisa M. |title=The Sage Encyclopedia of Qualitative Research Methods: A-L |volume=1 |publisher=Sage |isbn=978-1-4129-4163-1 |language=en |chapter=Axiology |date=2008 |pages=52–56}} * {{cite book |last1=Hirose |first1=Iwao |title=Moral Aggregation |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-993368-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=m-5jBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA25 |language=en |date=2015 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Hirose |first1=Iwao |last2=Olson |first2=Jonas |editor1-last=Hirose |editor1-first=Iwao |editor2-last=Olson |editor2-first=Jonas |title=The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-022143-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=Introduction to Value Theory |date=2015 |pages=1–12}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Holtug |first1=Nils |editor1-last=Hirose |editor1-first=Iwao |editor2-last=Olson |editor2-first=Jonas |title=The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-022143-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=Theories of Value Aggregation: Utilitarianism, Egalitarianism, Prioritarianism |date=2015 |pages=267–284}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Honderich |first1=Ingrid Coggin |chapter=Good, Form of the |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |page=349}} * {{cite journal |last1=Hooker |first1=Brad |title=The Elements of Well-Being |journal=Journal of Practical Ethics |volume=3 |issue=1 |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/HOOTEO-8 |date=2015 |ssrn=2624595 }} * {{cite web |last1=Hooker |first1=Brad |title=Rule Consequentialism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism-rule/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=29 December 2023 |date=2023 |archive-date=February 1, 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240201103315/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism-rule/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |last1=Howard |first1=Christopher |title=Fitting Attitude Theories of Value |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fitting-attitude-theories/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=25 April 2025 |date=2023 }} * {{cite web |last1=Hsieh |first1=Nien-hê |last2=Andersson |first2=Henrik |title=Incommensurable Values |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-incommensurable/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=6 September 2024 |date=2021 |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164111/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-incommensurable/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Hurka |first1=Thomas |editor1-last=Copp |editor1-first=David |title=The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-514779-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=K44RDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=13. Value Theory |date=2006 |pages=357–379}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Hurka |first1=Thomas |editor1-last=Borchert |editor1-first=Donald M. |title=Encyclopedia of Philosophy |volume=4 |date=2006a |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0-02-866072-1 |edition=2nd |chapter=Intrinsic Value |pages=719–720}} * {{cite web |last1=Hurka |first1=Thomas |title=Moore's Moral Philosophy |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moore-moral/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=21 September 2024 |date=2021 |archive-date=22 March 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230322203953/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moore-moral/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Jax |first1=Kurt |title=Conservation Concepts: Rethinking Human–Nature Relationships |publisher=Taylor & Francis |isbn=978-1-000-99354-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=j57WEAAAQBAJ&pg=PT38 |language=en |date=2023 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Johnson |first1=Robert |last2=Cureton |first2=Adam |title=Kant's Moral Philosophy |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-moral/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=18 September 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=1 February 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240201103437/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-moral/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Karp |first1=David R. |editor1-last=Borgatta |editor1-first=Edgar F. |editor2-last=Montgomery |editor2-first=Rhonda J. V. |title=Encyclopedia of Sociology |publisher=Macmillan |isbn=978-0-02-864853-8 |edition=2nd |chapter=Values Theory and Research |date=2000 |url=https://www.encyclopedia.com/social-sciences/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/values-theory-and-research |access-date=2024-09-14 |archive-date=2024-09-12 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240912122025/https://www.encyclopedia.com/social-sciences/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/values-theory-and-research |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Kershnar |first1=Stephen |title=Desert and Virtue: A Theory of Intrinsic Value |publisher=Rowman & Littlefield |isbn=978-0-7391-3936-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vwMN7WRb2fEC&pg=PA37 |language=en |date=2010 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Kim |first1=Min-Sun |title=Non-Western Perspectives on Human Communication: Implications for Theory and Practice |publisher=Sage |isbn=978-0-7619-2351-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Bsr3h16zrkwC&pg=PA22 |language=en |date=2002 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Kinneging |first1=Andreas |editor1-last=Poli |editor1-first=Roberto |editor2-last=Scognamiglio |editor2-first=Carlo |editor3-last=Tremblay |editor3-first=Frederic |title=The Philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann |publisher=Walter de Gruyter |isbn=978-3-11-025418-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1Qya55bssVQC&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=Hartmann's Platonic Ethics |date=2011 |pages=195–220}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Kinzel |first1=Katherina |title=Wilhelm Windelband |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/wilhelm-windelband/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=18 September 2024 |date=2024 |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164047/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/wilhelm-windelband/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Kriegel |first1=Uriah |title=The Routledge Handbook of Franz Brentano and the Brentano School |publisher=Taylor & Francis |isbn=978-1-317-69055-9 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=4kUlDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA12 |language=en |chapter=Introduction |date=2017 |pages=1–14}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Kriegel |first1=Uriah |title=Brentano's Philosophical System: Mind, Being, Value |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-879148-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=3e9IDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2018 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Kuijper |first1=Hans |title=Comprehending the Complexity of Countries: The Way Ahead |publisher=Springer Nature Singapore |isbn=978-981-16-4709-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2-FZEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA298 |language=en |date=2022 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Kunnan |first1=Antony John |editor1-last=Ockey |editor1-first=Gary J. |editor2-last=Green |editor2-first=Brent A. |title=Another Generation of Fundamental Considerations in Language Assessment: A Festschrift in Honor of Lyle F. Bachman |publisher=Springer Nature Singapore |isbn=978-981-15-8952-2 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=IwgLEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA86 |language=en |chapter=A Case for an Ethics-Based Approach to Evaluate Language |date=2020 |pages=77–94}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Kupperman |first1=Joel J. |chapter=Axiological Ethics |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |pages=73–74}} * {{cite journal |last1=Landau |first1=Iddo |title=Foundationless Freedom and Meaninglessness of Life in Sartre's: Being and Nothingness |journal=Sartre Studies International |volume=18 |issue=1 |doi=10.3167/ssi.2012.180101 |date=2012 |pages=1–8 |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/LANFFA-2 }} * {{cite book |last1=Laskowski |first1=Nicholas |last2=Finlay |first2=Stephen |editor1-last=McPherson |editor1-first=Tristram |editor2-last=Plunkett |editor2-first=David |title=The Routledge Handbook of Metaethics |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-351-81791-2 |url=https://philarchive.org/archive/LASCAI |language=en |chapter=34. Conceptual Analysis in Metaethics |date=2017 |pages=536–551 }} * {{cite book |last1=Li |first1=Deshun |title=Value Theory: A Research into Subjectivity |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-642-25617-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=W2a4BAAAQBAJ&pg=PA67 |language=en |date=2014 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Littlejohn |first1=Ronnie |title=Chinese Philosophy: Overview of History |url=https://iep.utm.edu/chinese-philosophy-overview-of-history/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=20 September 2024 |archive-date=1 June 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230601185554/https://iep.utm.edu/chinese-philosophy-overview-of-history/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Lobel |first1=Diana |title=Philosophies of Happiness: A Comparative Introduction to the Flourishing Life |publisher=Columbia University Press |isbn=978-0-231-54532-7 |language=en |date=2017 }} * {{cite book |last1=Lougheed |first1=Kirk |title=The Axiological Status of Theism and Other Worldviews |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-030-54820-9 |language=en |date=2020 }} * {{cite web |last1=Lutz |first1=Matthew |title=Moral Naturalism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/naturalism-moral/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=20 December 2023 |date=2023 |archive-date=October 2, 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20191002234858/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/naturalism-moral/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Løgstrup |first1=K. E. |title=Ethical Concepts and Problems |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-260282-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=aurkDwAAQBAJ&pg=PR141 |language=en |date=2020 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Mander |first1=W. J. |title=Idealist Ethics |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-106570-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=f0UFCwAAQBAJ&pg=PT14 |language=en |date=2016 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Marcum |first1=James A. |title=An Introductory Philosophy of Medicine: Humanizing Modern Medicine |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-4020-6797-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=1arGI9NZcAkC&pg=PA192 |language=en |date=2008 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Martin |first1=Robert M. |title=The Philosopher's Dictionary |edition=3rd |publisher=Broadview Press |isbn=978-1-55111-494-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=vNvXkFUbfM8C&pg=PA166 |language=en |date=2002 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite journal |last1=Martin |first1=John Levi |title=The Birth of the True, the Good, and the Beautiful: Toward an Investigation of the Structures of Social Thought |journal=Current Perspectives in Social Theory |volume=35 |doi=10.1108/S0278-120420160000035001 |date=2016 |pages=3–56 |isbn=978-1-78635-470-9 }} * {{cite web |last1=Mason |first1=Elinor |title=Value Pluralism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-pluralism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=6 September 2024 |date=2023 |archive-date=23 June 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230623192513/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-pluralism/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=McDonald |first1=Hugh P. |title=Radical Axiology: A First Philosophy of Values |publisher=Brill |isbn=978-90-04-49581-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=Z5JOEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA38 |language=en |date=2021 }} * {{cite book |last1=McGinnis |first1=Jon |title=Avicenna |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-533147-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=M28EjkCdFecC&pg=PA209 |language=en |date=2010 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Metz |first1=Thaddeus |title=The Meaning of Life |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/life-meaning/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=12 February 2025 |date=2023 }} * {{cite web |last1=Milkov |first1=Nikolay |title=Lotze, Rudolph Hermann |url=https://iep.utm.edu/lotze/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=18 September 2024 |archive-date=19 July 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190719040656/https://www.iep.utm.edu/lotze/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |last1=Moore |first1=Andrew |title=Hedonism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hedonism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=8 September 2024 |date=2019 |archive-date=18 September 2018 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180918065934/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hedonism/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Moritz |first1=Manfred |editor-last1=Kuypers |editor-first1=K. |title=Human Sciences and the Problem of Values / Les Sciences Humaines et le Problème des Valeurs |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-94-010-2424-2 |chapter-url=https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-010-2424-2_3 |language=en |chapter=Axiology and Analysis |date=1972 |pages=33–46 |doi=10.1007/978-94-010-2424-2_3 |access-date=2024-09-16 |archive-date=2024-09-15 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240915124611/https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1007/978-94-010-2424-2_3 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Moseley |first1=Fred |title=Marx's Theory of Value in Chapter 1 of Capital: A Critique of Heinrich's Value-Form Interpretation |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |isbn=978-3-031-13210-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=43m-EAAAQBAJ&pg=PA48 |language=en |date=2023 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Mukherjee |first1=Sampat |last2=Mukherjee |first2=Mallinath |last3=Ghose |first3=Amitava |title=Microeconomics |publisher=Prentice-Hall of India |isbn=978-81-203-2318-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=iVKja7n06iIC&pg=PA17 |language=en |date=2013 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Nagel |first1=Thomas |chapter=Ethics |editor1-last=Borchert |editor1-first=Donald |title=Encyclopedia of Philosophy |edition=2nd |volume=3 |date=2006 |publisher=Macmillan |url=https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/ethics |isbn=978-0-02-865790-5 |access-date=January 7, 2024 |archive-date=August 24, 2018 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20180824071808/https://www.encyclopedia.com/philosophy-and-religion/philosophy/philosophy-terms-and-concepts/ethics |url-status=live |pages=379–394}} * {{cite journal |last1=Nebel |first1=Jacob M. |title=A Choice-Functional Characterization of Welfarism |journal=Journal of Economic Theory |volume=222 |doi=10.1016/j.jet.2024.105918 |date=2024 |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/NEBACC }} * {{cite book |last1=Norman |first1=Richard |chapter=Moral Philosophy, History of |editor1-last=Honderich |editor1-first=Ted |title=The Oxford Companion to Philosophy |date=2005 |publisher=Oxford University Press |url=https://philpapers.org/rec/HONTOC-2 |isbn=978-0-19-926479-7 |access-date=December 19, 2023 |archive-date=January 29, 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210129082636/https://philpapers.org/rec/HONTOC-2 |url-status=live |pages=622–627}} * {{cite journal |last1=Oddie |first1=G. |title=Axiological Atomism |journal=Australasian Journal of Philosophy |volume=79 |issue=3 |doi=10.1080/713659262 |date=2001 |pages=313–332 }} * {{cite book |last1=Oddie |first1=Graham |title=The International Encyclopedia of Ethics |publisher=Wiley |isbn=978-1-4051-8641-4 |edition=1st |url=https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee588 |language=en |chapter=Value Realism |doi=10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee588 |date=2013 |access-date=2024-09-09 |archive-date=2024-09-22 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164154/https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/abs/10.1002/9781444367072.wbiee588 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Oddie |first1=Graham |editor1-last=Hirose |editor1-first=Iwao |editor2-last=Olson |editor2-first=Jonas |title=The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-022143-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=Value and Desire |date=2015 |pages=60–79}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Oddie |first1=Graham |editor1-last=Lauria |editor1-first=Federico |editor2-last=Deonna |editor2-first=Julien A. |title=The Nature of Desire |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-067961-3 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=OTElDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA49 |language=en |chapter=Desire and the Good: In Search of the Right Fit |date=2017 |pages=29–56}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=O'Keefe |first1=Tim |title=Epicurus |url=https://iep.utm.edu/epicur/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=19 September 2024 |archive-date=19 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240919114110/https://iep.utm.edu/epicur/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite journal |last1=Oliveira |first1=Luis R. G. |title=Rossian totalism about intrinsic value |journal=Philosophical Studies |volume=173 |issue=8 |doi=10.1007/s11098-015-0597-8 |date=2016 |pages=2069–2086 |url=https://philarchive.org/rec/OLIRTA-2 }} * {{cite book |last1=Oliver |first1=Alex |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |chapter=Value, Ontological Status of |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-N066-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 }} * {{cite book |last1=Ollig |first1=Hans-Ludwig |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/neo-kantianism/v-1 |chapter=Neo-Kantianism |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-DC055-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |access-date=2024-09-02 |archive-date=2024-03-02 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240302232431/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/neo-kantianism/v-1 |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |last1=Onof |first1=Christian J. |title=Sartre, Jean Paul: Existentialism |url=https://iep.utm.edu/sartre-ex/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=5 September 2024 |archive-date=26 June 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240626150853/https://iep.utm.edu/sartre-ex/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Orsi |first1=Francesco |title=Value Theory |publisher=Bloomsbury Publishing |isbn=978-1-4725-2408-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=cc3cBAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2015 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Pape |first1=John |title=Economics: An Introduction for South African Learners |publisher=Juta and Company Ltd |isbn=978-0-7021-5206-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=fYzMz3UlyaMC&pg=PA7 |language=en |date=2000 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Perrin |first1=Ron |title=Max Scheler's Concept of the Person: An Ethics Of Humanism |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-1-349-21399-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-6ewCwAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=1991 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Peterson |first1=John |title=Aquinas: A New Introduction |publisher=University Press of America |isbn=978-0-7618-4180-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=C6u8kXWTjwwC&pg=PA235 |language=en |date=2008 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Peterson |first1=Martin |title=The Dimensions of Consequentialism: Ethics, Equality and Risk |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-107-03303-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=KscNwy-F3u8C&pg=PA147 |language=en |date=2013 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Pigliucci |first1=Massimo |title=Stoicism |url=https://iep.utm.edu/stoicism/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=20 September 2024 |archive-date=24 June 2021 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20210624205455/https://iep.utm.edu/stoicism/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite journal |last1=Pirgmaier |first1=Elke |title=The Value of Value Theory for Ecological Economics |journal=Ecological Economics |volume=179 |doi=10.1016/j.ecolecon.2020.106790 |date=2021 |pmid=32863580 |pmc=7445139 |bibcode=2021EcoEc.17906790P }} * {{cite book |last1=Powe |first1=Neil A. |title=Redesigning Environmental Valuation: Mixing Methods Within Stated Preference Techniques |publisher=Edward Elgar Publishing |isbn=978-1-84720-711-1 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=QpIgHPHmegsC&pg=PA123 |language=en |date=2007 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Pradhan |first1=Ramesh Chandra |title=Ethics, Self and the World: Exploring Metaphysical Foundations in Moral Philosophy |publisher=Springer Nature Singapore |isbn=978-981-97-3496-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=m4wWEQAAQBAJ&pg=PA142 |language=en |date=2024 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Prasad |first1=Hari Shankar |title=The Centrality of Ethics in Buddhism: Exploratory Essays |publisher=Motilal Banarsidass |isbn=978-81-208-3239-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=6GPxDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA21 |language=en |date=2007 }} * {{cite web |last1=Pratt |first1=Alan |title=Nihilism |url=https://iep.utm.edu/nihilism/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=7 February 2025}} * {{cite web |last1=Ranganathan |first1=Shyam |title=Hindu Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/hindu-ph/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=17 September 2024 |archive-date=30 June 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240630215826/https://iep.utm.edu/hindu-ph/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Rescher |first1=Nicholas |title=Introduction to Value Theory |publisher=Prentice-Hall |oclc=1070925450 |language=en |date=1969 }} * {{cite web |last1=Richey |first1=Jeff |title=Confucius |url=https://iep.utm.edu/confucius/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=17 September 2024 |archive-date=29 September 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230929040158/https://iep.utm.edu/confucius/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |last1=Ridge |first1=Michael |title=Moral Non-Naturalism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-non-naturalism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=20 December 2023 |date=2019 |archive-date=24 February 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240224195405/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-non-naturalism/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |last1=Robbins |first1=Joel |title=Values |url=https://www.anthroencyclopedia.com/entry/values |website=The Open Encyclopedia of Anthropology |publisher=Cambridge University Press |date=2023 |access-date=2024-09-14 |archive-date=2024-09-12 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240912171457/https://www.anthroencyclopedia.com/entry/values |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Rogers |first1=Alisdair |last2=Castree |first2=Noel |last3=Kitchin |first3=Rob |title=A Dictionary of Human Geography |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-959986-8 |url=https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/acref/9780199599868.001.0001/acref-9780199599868-e-1987 |language=en |chapter=Use Value |date=2013 |access-date=2024-09-14 |archive-date=2024-09-22 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164053/https://www.oxfordreference.com/display/10.1093/acref/9780199599868.001.0001/acref-9780199599868-e-1987 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Rosenkrantz |first1=Gary S. |last2=Hoffman |first2=Joshua |title=Historical Dictionary of Metaphysics |publisher=Scarecrow Press |isbn=978-0-8108-5950-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=DQW9nyBCClMC&pg=PA332 |language=en |date=2011 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Rønnow-Rasmussen |first1=Toni |title=Personal Value |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-960378-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=b_O3l9_QgNgC&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2011 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Rønnow-Rasmussen |first1=Toni |editor1-last=Hirose |editor1-first=Iwao |editor2-last=Olson |editor2-first=Jonas |title=The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-022143-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=Intrinsic and Extrinsic Value |date=2015 |pages=29–43}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Sayre-McCord |first1=Geoffrey |editor1-last=Sayre-McCord |editor1-first=Geoffrey |title=Essays on Moral Realism |publisher=Cornell University Press |isbn=978-0-8014-9541-0 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=-msmrkE-67IC&pg=PA10 |language=en |chapter=Introduction: The Many Moral Realisms |date=1988 |pages=1–26}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Scanlon |first1=Thomas |editor1-last=Nussbaum |editor1-first=Martha |editor2-last=Sen |editor2-first=Amartya |title=The Quality of Life |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-152136-2 |language=en |chapter=Value, Desire, and Quality of Life |doi=10.1093/0198287976.003.0015 |date=1993 |pages=185–200 }} * {{cite book |last1=Schellekens |first1=Elisabeth |title=Aesthetics and Morality |publisher=Bloomsbury Publishing |isbn=978-1-4411-2298-8 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=LB4SBwAAQBAJ&pg=PA38 |language=en |date=2010 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Schroeder |first1=Mark |title=Value Theory |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-theory/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=26 August 2024 |date=2021 |archive-date=27 June 2013 |archive-url=https://archive.today/20130627021351/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-theory/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |last1=Schroeder |first1=Mark |title=Supplement to Value Theory: Atomism/Holism about Value |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-theory/supplement2.html |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=26 August 2024 |date=2021a |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164202/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-theory/supplement2.html |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Schwartz |first1=S. H. |last2=Cieciuch |first2=J. |editor1-last=Leong |editor1-first=F. T. L. |editor2-last=Bartram |editor2-first=D. |editor3-last=Cheung |editor3-first=F. M. |editor4-last=Geisinger |editor4-first=K. F. |editor5-last=Iliescu |editor5-first=D. |title=The ITC International Handbook of Testing and Assessment |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-935694-2 |language=en |chapter=Values |date=2016 }} * {{cite journal |last1=Schwartz |first1=Shalom H. |last2=Cieciuch |first2=Jan |last3=Vecchione |first3=Michele |last4=Davidov |first4=Eldad |last5=Fischer |first5=Ronald |last6=Beierlein |first6=Constanze |last7=Ramos |first7=Alice |last8=Verkasalo |first8=Markku |last9=Lönnqvist |first9=Jan-Erik |last10=Demirutku |first10=Kursad |last11=Dirilen-Gumus |first11=Ozlem |last12=Konty |first12=Mark |title=Refining the Theory of Basic Individual Values |journal=Journal of Personality and Social Psychology |volume=103 |issue=4 |doi=10.1037/a0029393 |date=2012 |pages=663–688}} * {{cite web |last1=Seachris |first1=Joshua |title=The Meaning of Life: Contemporary Analytic Perspectives |url=https://iep.utm.edu/mean-ana/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=12 February 2025}} * {{cite book |last1=Serna |first1=Cristina |last2=Martínez |first2=Isabel |editor1-last=Selin |editor1-first=Helaine |title=Parenting Across Cultures: Childrearing, Motherhood and Fatherhood in Non-Western Cultures |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-031-15359-4 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=tIedEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA423 |language=en |chapter=Parenting and Adolescent Technological Addictions |date=2022 |pages=417–436}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite journal |last1=Sharma |first1=Arvind |title=The Purusārthas: An Axiological Exploration of Hinduism |journal=Journal of Religious Ethics |volume=27 |issue=2 |doi=10.1111/0384-9694.00016 |date=1999 |pages=223–256 }} * {{cite book |last1=Sharma |first1=Rajendra Kumar |title=Fundamentals of Sociology |publisher=Atlantic Publishers & Distributors |isbn=978-81-7156-645-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=QQ1nBcV_zCMC&pg=PA10 |language=en |date=1996 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Sharma |first1=Ram Nath |title=Plato: An Interdisciplinary Perspective |publisher=Atlantic Publishers & Distributors |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=5tSOV8W1aCUC&pg=PA27 |language=en |date=1991 |isbn=978-81-7156-166-7 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite journal |last1=Shea |first1=Matthew |last2=Kintz |first2=James |title=A Thomistic Solution to the Deep Problem for Perfectionism |journal=Utilitas |volume=34 |issue=4 |doi=10.1017/S0953820822000346 |date=2022 |pages=461–477 |doi-access=free }} * {{cite book |last1=Silverstein |first1=Matthew |editor1-last=Shafer-Landau |editor1-first=Russ |title=Oxford Studies in Metaethics 11 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-878464-7 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=96qkDAAAQBAJ&pg=PA227 |language=en |chapter=Teleology and Normativity |date=2016 |pages=214–240}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Sim |first1=May |editor1-last=Besser-Jones |editor1-first=Lorraine |editor2-last=Slote |editor2-first=Michael |title=The Routledge Companion to Virtue Ethics |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-135-09669-4 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=0WLABgAAQBAJ&pg=PA64 |language=en |chapter=Why Confucius' Ethics Is a Virtue Ethics |date=2015 |pages=63–76}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Simpson |first1=David L. |title=Ross, William David |url=https://iep.utm.edu/ross-wd/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=19 September 2024 |archive-date=20 June 2019 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20190620123622/https://www.iep.utm.edu/ross-wd/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |last1=Sinnott-Armstrong |first1=Walter |title=Consequentialism |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=28 December 2023 |date=2023 |archive-date=June 18, 2023 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20230618171402/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/consequentialism/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Slingerland |first1=Edward |title=Effortless Action: Wu-wei as Conceptual Metaphor and Spiritual Ideal in Early China |date=2007 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-987457-6 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=gSReaja3V3IC&pg=PA77 |language=en |access-date=December 19, 2023 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Smith |first1=Joel |title=Phenomenology |url=https://iep.utm.edu/phenom/ |website=Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |access-date=15 September 2024 |archive-date=25 May 2020 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20200525234910/https://www.iep.utm.edu/phenom/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Smith |first1=Barry |last2=Thomas |first2=Alan |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-L120-1 |url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/axiology/v-1 |chapter=Axiology |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |access-date=2024-08-27 |archive-date=2023-11-30 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20231130132059/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/thematic/axiology/v-1 |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Staiti |first1=Andrea |editor1-last=Santis |editor1-first=Daniele De |editor2-last=Hopkins |editor2-first=Burt C. |editor3-last=Majolino |editor3-first=Claudio |title=The Routledge Handbook of Phenomenology and Phenomenological Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-000-17042-9 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=TGMPEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA368 |language=en |chapter=Reduction |date=2020 |pages=368–375}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Steinert |first1=Steffen |title=Interdisciplinary Value Theory |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-031-10733-7 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ADG4EAAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2023 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Stratton-Lake |first1=Philip |title=Intuitionism in Ethics |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/intuitionism-ethics/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=14 September 2024 |date=2020 |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164053/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/intuitionism-ethics/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite journal |last1=Suikkanen |first1=Jussi |title=Buck‐Passing Accounts of Value |journal=Philosophy Compass |volume=4 |issue=5 |doi=10.1111/j.1747-9991.2009.00253.x |date=2009 |pages=768–779 }} * {{cite book |last1=Sullivan |first1=David |chapter=Lotze, Rudolph Hermann (1817–81) |url=https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/biographical/lotze-rudolph-hermann-1817-81/v-1 |title=Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Routledge |access-date=18 September 2024 |doi=10.4324/9780415249126-DC049-1 |date=1998 |isbn=978-0-415-25069-6 |archive-date=5 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240905090539/https://www.rep.routledge.com/articles/biographical/lotze-rudolph-hermann-1817-81/v-1 |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |last1=Sullivan |first1=David |title=Hermann Lotze |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hermann-lotze/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=18 September 2024 |date=2023 |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164054/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hermann-lotze/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Sutton |first1=Mark Q. |title=Archaeology: The Science of the Human Past |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-000-35113-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=pjAXEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA5 |language=en |date=2021 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Sykes |first1=Karen |title=Value |url=https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780199766567/obo-9780199766567-0138.xml |website=Oxford Bibliographies |access-date=13 September 2024 |language=en |doi=10.1093/obo/9780199766567-0138 |date=2016 |archive-date=16 March 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240316025315/https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780199766567/obo-9780199766567-0138.xml |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Taliaferro |first1=Charles |title=A Dictionary of Philosophy of Religion |publisher=Bloomsbury Publishing |isbn=978-1-4411-8504-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=CfWoAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA25 |language=en |date=2010 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Tappolet |first1=Christine |editor1-last=Hirose |editor1-first=Iwao |editor2-last=Olson |editor2-first=Jonas |title=The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-022143-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=Values and Emotions |date=2015 |pages=80–95}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Tiberius |first1=Valerie |editor1-last=Hirose |editor1-first=Iwao |editor2-last=Olson |editor2-first=Jonas |title=The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-022143-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=Prudential Value |date=2015 |pages=158–174}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Tilley |first1=John J. |title=Encyclopedia of Applied Ethics |publisher=Academic Press |isbn=978-0-12-373932-2 |language=en |chapter=Hedonism |date=2012 |url=https://philpapers.org/archive/TILH.pdf |editor-last1=Chadwick |editor-first1=Ruth }} * {{cite book |last1=Tormos |first1=Raül |title=The Rhythm of Modernization: How Values Change over Time |publisher=Brill |isbn=978-90-04-41191-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=u8y8DwAAQBAJ&pg=PA11 |language=en |date=2019 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Townsend |first1=Dabney |title=Historical Dictionary of Aesthetics |publisher=Scarecrow Press |isbn=978-0-8108-6483-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GGgAAwAAQBAJ&pg=PR16 |language=en |date=2006 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Tuboly |first1=Adam Tamas |title=The Historical and Philosophical Significance of Ayer's Language, Truth and Logic |publisher=Palgrave Macmillan |isbn=978-3-030-50884-5 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=R-oEEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA2 |language=en |chapter=Introduction: From Spying to Canonizing—Ayer and His Language, Truth and Logic |date=2021 |pages=1–38}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Turner |first1=R. Kerry |last2=Georgiou |first2=Stavros |last3=Clark |first3=Rebecca |last4=Brouwer |first4=Roy |last5=Burke |first5=Jacob |title=Economic Valuation of Water Resources in Agriculture: From the Sectoral to a Functional Perspective of Natural Resource Management |publisher=Food & Agriculture Organization of the United Nations |isbn=978-92-5-105190-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=coz0lmhjZAYC&pg=PA50 |language=en |date=2004 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Vilkka |first1=Leena |title=The Intrinsic Value of Nature |publisher=Brill |isbn=978-90-04-49510-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=2WxPEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA32 |language=en |date=2021 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Wall |first1=Steven |title=Perfectionism in Moral and Political Philosophy |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/perfectionism-moral/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=6 September 2024 |date=2021 |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164651/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/perfectionism-moral/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Welch |first1=Patrick J. |last2=Welch |first2=Gerry F. |title=Economics: Theory and Practice |publisher=John Wiley & Sons |isbn=978-0-470-45009-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=O5i-d3thv-4C&pg=PA4 |language=en |date=2009 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Wieland |first1=Georg |editor1-last=Pope |editor1-first=Stephen J. |title=The Ethics of Aquinas |publisher=Georgetown University Press |isbn=978-0-87840-888-7 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=PtLyH02x60MC&pg=PA59 |language=en |chapter=Happiness (Ia IIae, qq. 1–5) |translator-last1=Kaplan |translator-first1=Grant |date=2002 |pages=57–68}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Wiland |first1=Eric |last2=Driver |first2=Julia |title=Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/anscombe/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=22 September 2024 |date=2022 |archive-date=23 March 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240323105623/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/anscombe/ |url-status=live }} * {{cite web |last1=Wilson |first1=Jeff |title=Saṃsāra and Rebirth |url=https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195393521/obo-9780195393521-0141.xml |website=Oxford Bibliographies |publisher=Oxford University Press |access-date=20 September 2024 |language=en |doi=10.1093/obo/9780195393521-0141 |date=2010 |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164546/https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/display/document/obo-9780195393521/obo-9780195393521-0141.xml |url-status=live }} * {{cite book |last1=Woodward |first1=William R. |title=Hermann Lotze |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-41848-5 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=L4dsCQAAQBAJ&pg=PR1 |language=en |date=2015 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Woodworth |first1=Robert |last2=Marquis |first2=Donald |title=Psychology: A Study of Mental Life |publisher=Psychology Press |isbn=978-1-317-66144-3 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=IXPpAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA5 |language=en |date=2014 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Yalom |first1=Irvin D. |title=Existential Psychotherapy |publisher=Basic Books |isbn=978-1-5416-4744-2 |language=en |date=2020 }} * {{cite book |last1=Ylirisku |first1=Salu |last2=Arvola |first2=Mattias |editor1-last=Vermaas |editor1-first=Pieter E. |editor2-last=Vial |editor2-first=Stéphane |title=Advancements in the Philosophy of Design |publisher=Springer |isbn=978-3-319-73302-9 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=ed1ODwAAQBAJ&pg=PA53 |language=en |chapter=The Varieties of Good Design |date=2018 |pages=51–70}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Young |first1=Robert A. |last2=Loomis |first2=John B. |title=Determining the Economic Value of Water: Concepts and Methods |publisher=Routledge |isbn=978-1-135-04052-9 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=brDcAwAAQBAJ&pg=PA289 |language=en |date=2014 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Zagzebski |first1=Linda |title=Divine Motivation Theory |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-0-521-53576-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=KhqPito92b8C&pg=PA11 |language=en |date=2004 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Zagzebski |first1=Linda |editor1-last=Wainwright |editor1-first=William |title=The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Religion |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-803158-1 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=GbcuCf9TlDgC&pg=PA350 |language=en |chapter=Morality and Religion |date=2004a |pages=344–365}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Zaibert |first1=Leo |title=Rethinking Punishment |publisher=Cambridge University Press |isbn=978-1-108-58261-2 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=E1FSDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA37 |language=en |date=2018 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Zimmer |first1=Alfred |editor1-last=Albertazzi |editor1-first=Liliana |editor2-last=Jacquette |editor2-first=Dale |title=The School of Alexius Meinong |publisher=Taylor & Francis |isbn=978-1-351-88226-2 |chapter-url=https://books.google.com/books?id=wkQrDwAAQBAJ&pg=PA135 |language=en |chapter=Christian von Ehrenfels (1859–1932) |date=2017 }}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Zimmerman |first1=Michael J. |title=The Nature of Intrinsic Value |publisher=Rowman & Littlefield |isbn=978-0-7425-1263-4 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=9pqECJM08rkC&pg=PA1 |language=en |date=2001 |pages=135–144}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite book |last1=Zimmerman |first1=Michael J. |editor1-last=Hirose |editor1-first=Iwao |editor2-last=Olson |editor2-first=Jonas |title=The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-022143-0 |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA1 |language=en |chapter=Value and Normativity |date=2015 |pages=13–28}}{{cbignore}} * {{cite web |last1=Zimmerman |first1=Michael J. |last2=Bradley |first2=Ben |title=Intrinsic vs. Extrinsic Value |url=https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-intrinsic-extrinsic/ |website=The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy |publisher=Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University |access-date=29 August 2024 |date=2019 |archive-date=22 September 2024 |archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20240922164656/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-intrinsic-extrinsic/ |url-status=live }} {{refend}} {{DEFAULTSORT:Value Theory}} [[Category:Axiology]] {{Philosophy topics}} {{Good and evil}}
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Cbignore
(
edit
)
Template:Circa
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:Distinguish
(
edit
)
Template:Efn
(
edit
)
Template:Em dash
(
edit
)
Template:Gloss
(
edit
)
Template:Good and evil
(
edit
)
Template:Good article
(
edit
)
Template:Harvnb
(
edit
)
Template:Lang
(
edit
)
Template:Main
(
edit
)
Template:Multiref
(
edit
)
Template:Notelist
(
edit
)
Template:Philosophy topics
(
edit
)
Template:Refbegin
(
edit
)
Template:Refend
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Transliteration
(
edit
)
Template:Use American English
(
edit
)