Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Vitali set
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{short description|Set of real numbers that is not Lebesgue measurable}} In [[mathematics]], a '''Vitali set''' is an elementary example of a set of [[real number]]s that is not [[Lebesgue measure|Lebesgue measurable]], found by [[Giuseppe Vitali]] in 1905.<ref>{{cite journal|last=Vitali|first=Giuseppe|authorlink=Giuseppe Vitali|year=1905|title= Sul problema della misura dei gruppi di punti di una retta|journal=Bologna, Tip. Gamberini e Parmeggiani}}</ref> The '''Vitali theorem''' is the [[existence theorem]] that there are such sets. Each Vitali set is [[Uncountable set|uncountable]], and there are [[uncountably many]] Vitali sets. The proof of their existence depends on the [[axiom of choice]]. == Measurable sets == Certain sets have a definite 'length' or 'mass'. For instance, the [[interval (mathematics)|interval]] [0, 1] is deemed to have length 1; more generally, an interval [''a'', ''b''], ''a'' ≤ ''b'', is deemed to have length ''b'' − ''a''. If we think of such intervals as metal rods with uniform density, they likewise have well-defined masses. The set [0, 1] ∪ [2, 3] is composed of two intervals of length one, so we take its total length to be 2. In terms of mass, we have two rods of mass 1, so the total mass is 2. There is a natural question here: if ''E'' is an arbitrary subset of the real line, does it have a 'mass' or 'total length'? As an example, we might ask what is the mass of the set of [[rational number]]s between 0 and 1, given that the mass of the interval [0, 1] is 1. The rationals are [[Dense set|dense]] in the reals, so any value between and including 0 and 1 may appear reasonable. However the closest generalization to mass is [[sigma additivity]], which gives rise to the [[Lebesgue measure]]. It assigns a measure of ''b'' − ''a'' to the interval [''a'', ''b''], but will assign a measure of 0 to the set of rational numbers because it is [[countable]]. Any set which has a well-defined Lebesgue measure is said to be "measurable", but the construction of the Lebesgue measure (for instance using [[Carathéodory's extension theorem]]) does not make it obvious whether non-measurable sets exist. The answer to that question involves the [[axiom of choice]]. == Construction and proof == A Vitali set is a subset <math>V</math> of the [[interval (mathematics)|interval]] <math>[0,1]</math> of [[real number]]s such that, for each real number <math>r</math>, there is exactly one number <math>v \in V</math> such that <math>v-r</math> is a [[rational number]]. Vitali sets exist because the rational numbers <math>\mathbb{Q}</math> form a [[normal subgroup]] of the real numbers <math>\mathbb{R}</math> under [[addition]], and this allows the construction of the additive [[quotient group]] <math>\mathbb{R}/\mathbb{Q}</math> of these two groups which is the group formed by the [[coset]]s <math>r+\mathbb{Q}</math> of the rational numbers as a subgroup of the real numbers under addition. This group <math>\mathbb{R}/\mathbb{Q}</math> consists of [[disjoint sets|disjoint]] "shifted copies" of <math>\mathbb{Q}</math> in the sense that each element of this quotient group is a set of the form <math>r+\mathbb{Q}</math> for some <math>r</math> in <math>\mathbb{R}</math>. The [[uncountable set|uncountably many]] elements of <math>\mathbb{R}/\mathbb{Q}</math> [[partition of a set|partition]] <math>\mathbb{R}</math> into disjoint sets, and each element is [[dense set|dense]] in <math>\mathbb{R}</math>. Each element of <math>\mathbb{R}/\mathbb{Q}</math> intersects <math>[0,1]</math>, and the [[axiom of choice]] guarantees the existence of a subset of <math>[0,1]</math> containing exactly one [[representative (mathematics)|representative]] out of each element of <math>\mathbb{R}/\mathbb{Q}</math>. A set formed this way is called a Vitali set. Every Vitali set <math>V</math> is uncountable, and <math>v-u</math> is irrational for any <math>u,v \in V, u \neq v</math>. ===Non-measurability=== [[File:diagonal argument.svg|thumb|A possible enumeration of the positive rational numbers]] A Vitali set is non-measurable. To show this, we assume that <math>V</math> is measurable and we derive a contradiction. Let <math>q_1,q_2,\dots</math> be an enumeration of the rational numbers in <math>[-1,1]</math> (recall that the rational numbers are [[countable]]). From the construction of <math>V</math>, we can show that the translated sets <math>V_k=V+q_k=\{v+q_k : v \in V\}</math>, <math>k=1,2,\dots</math> are pairwise disjoint. (If not, then there exists distinct <math>v,u \in V</math> and <math>k,\ell \in \mathbb{N}</math> such that <math>v+q_k = u + q_{\ell} \implies v-u = q_{\ell}-q_k \in \mathbb{Q}</math>, a contradiction.) Next, note that :<math>[0,1]\subseteq\bigcup_k V_k\subseteq[-1,2].</math> To see the first inclusion, consider any real number <math>r</math> in <math>[0,1]</math> and let <math>v</math> be the representative in <math>V</math> for the equivalence class <math>[r]</math>; then <math>r-v=q_i</math> for some rational number <math>q_i</math> in <math>[-1,1]</math> which implies that <math>r</math> is in <math>V_i</math>. Apply the Lebesgue measure to these inclusions using [[sigma additivity]]: :<math>1 \leq \sum_{k=1}^\infty \lambda(V_k) \leq 3.</math> Because the Lebesgue measure is translation invariant, <math>\lambda(V_k) = \lambda(V)</math> and therefore :<math>1 \leq \sum_{k=1}^\infty \lambda(V) \leq 3.</math> But this is impossible. Summing infinitely many copies of the constant <math>\lambda(V)</math> yields either zero or infinity, according to whether the constant is zero or positive. In neither case is the sum in <math>[1,3]</math>. So <math>V</math> cannot have been measurable after all, i.e., the Lebesgue measure <math>\lambda</math> must not define any value for <math>\lambda(V)</math>. ==Properties== No Vitali set has the [[property of Baire]].<ref>{{citation|title=Measure and Category|volume=2|series=Graduate Texts in Mathematics|first=John C.|last=Oxtoby|edition=2nd|publisher=Springer-Verlag|year=1980|isbn=978-0-387-90508-2}}. ''See page 22.''</ref> By modifying the above proof, one shows that each Vitali set has [[Banach measure]] 0. This does not create any contradictions since Banach measures are not countably additive, but only finitely additive. == Role of the axiom of choice == The construction of Vitali sets given above uses the [[axiom of choice]]. The question arises: is the axiom of choice needed to prove the existence of sets that are not Lebesgue measurable? The answer is yes, provided that [[inaccessible cardinal]]s are consistent with the most common axiomatization of set theory, so-called [[ZFC]]. In 1964, [[Robert M. Solovay|Robert Solovay]] constructed a model of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory without the axiom of choice where all sets of real numbers are Lebesgue measurable. This is known as the [[Solovay model]].<ref>{{Citation |last1=Solovay |first1=Robert M. |title=A model of set-theory in which every set of reals is Lebesgue measurable |journal=[[Annals of Mathematics]] |volume=92 |issue=1 |pages=1–56 |year=1970 |series=Second Series |doi=10.2307/1970696 |issn=0003-486X |jstor=1970696 |mr=0265151 |author1-link=Robert M. Solovay}}</ref> In his proof, Solovay assumed that the existence of inaccessible cardinals is [[Consistency|consistent]] with the other axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory, i.e. that it creates no contradictions. This assumption is widely believed to be true by set theorists, but it cannot be proven in ZFC alone.<ref name="wagon">{{Cite book |last1=Wagon |first1=Stan |title=The Banach-Tarski Paradox |last2=Tomkowicz |first2=Grzegorz |publisher=Cambridge University Press |year=2016 |edition=2nd |pages=296–299}}</ref> In 1980, [[Saharon Shelah]] proved that it is not possible to establish Solovay's result without his assumption on inaccessible cardinals.<ref name=wagon/> ==See also== * {{annotated link|Banach–Tarski paradox}} * {{annotated link|Carathéodory's criterion}} * {{annotated link|Non-measurable set}} * {{annotated link|Outer measure}} * {{annotated link|Infinite parity function}} ==References== {{reflist}} ==Bibliography== * {{cite book|last=Herrlich|first=Horst|authorlink = Horst Herrlich|title=Axiom of Choice|url=https://archive.org/details/axiomchoicelectu00herr_278|url-access=limited|page=[https://archive.org/details/axiomchoicelectu00herr_278/page/n132 120]|publisher=Springer|year=2006|isbn=9783540309895}} * {{cite journal|last=Vitali|first=Giuseppe|authorlink=Giuseppe Vitali|year=1905|title= Sul problema della misura dei gruppi di punti di una retta|journal=Bologna, Tip. Gamberini e Parmeggiani}} {{Measure theory}} {{Real numbers}} [[Category:Sets of real numbers]] [[Category:Measure theory]] [[Category:Articles containing proofs]] [[Category:Axiom of choice]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Annotated link
(
edit
)
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Measure theory
(
edit
)
Template:Real numbers
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)