Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Well-founded relation
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|Type of binary relation}} {{Redirect|Noetherian induction|the use in topology|Noetherian topological space}} {{stack|{{Binary relations}}}} In [[mathematics]], a [[binary relation]] {{mvar|R}} is called '''well-founded''' (or '''wellfounded''' or '''foundational'''<ref>See Definition 6.21 in {{cite book|last1=Zaring W.M.|first1= G. Takeuti|title=Introduction to axiomatic set theory|date=1971|publisher=Springer-Verlag|location=New York|isbn=0387900241|edition=2nd, rev.}}</ref>) on a [[set (mathematics)|set]] or, more generally, a [[Class (set theory)|class]] {{mvar|X}} if every [[non-empty]] [[subset]] {{math|''S'' ⊆ ''X''}} has a [[minimal element]] with respect to {{mvar|R}}; that is, there exists an {{math|''m'' ∈ ''S''}} such that, for every {{math|''s'' ∈ ''S''}}, one does not have {{math|''s'' ''R'' ''m''}}. In other words, a relation is well-founded if: <math display=block>(\forall S \subseteq X)\; [S \neq \varnothing \implies (\exists m \in S) (\forall s \in S) \lnot(s \mathrel{R} m)].</math> Some authors include an extra condition that {{mvar|R}} is [[Set-like relation|set-like]], i.e., that the elements less than any given element form a set. Equivalently, assuming the [[axiom of dependent choice]], a relation is well-founded when it contains no [[infinite descending chain]]s, meaning there is no infinite sequence {{math|''x''<sub>0</sub>, ''x''<sub>1</sub>, ''x''<sub>2</sub>, ...}} of elements of {{mvar|X}} such that {{math|''x''<sub>''n''+1</sub> ''R'' ''x''<sub>''n''</sub>}} for every natural number {{mvar|n}}.<ref>{{cite web |title=Infinite Sequence Property of Strictly Well-Founded Relation |url=https://proofwiki.org/wiki/Infinite_Sequence_Property_of_Strictly_Well-Founded_Relation |website=ProofWiki |access-date=10 May 2021}}</ref><ref>{{cite book |last1=Fraisse |first1=R. |author1-link=Roland Fraïssé |title=Theory of Relations, Volume 145 - 1st Edition |date=15 December 2000 |publisher=Elsevier |isbn=9780444505422 |page=46 |edition=1st |url=https://www.elsevier.com/books/theory-of-relations/fraisse/978-0-444-50542-2 |access-date=20 February 2019}}</ref> In [[order theory]], a [[partial order]] is called well-founded if the corresponding [[strict order]] is a well-founded relation. If the order is a [[total order]] then it is called a [[well-order]]. In [[set theory]], a set {{mvar|x}} is called a '''well-founded set''' if the [[element (mathematics)|set membership]] relation is well-founded on the [[Transitive closure (set)|transitive closure]] of {{mvar|x}}. The [[axiom of regularity]], which is one of the axioms of [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]], asserts that all sets are well-founded. A relation {{mvar|R}} is '''converse well-founded''', '''upwards well-founded''' or '''Noetherian''' on {{mvar|X}}, if the [[converse relation]] {{math|''R''<sup>−1</sup>}} is well-founded on {{mvar|X}}. In this case {{mvar|R}} is also said to satisfy the [[ascending chain condition]]. In the context of [[rewriting]] systems, a Noetherian relation is also called '''terminating'''. ==Induction and recursion== An important reason that well-founded relations are interesting is because a version of [[transfinite induction]] can be used on them: if ({{math|''X'', ''R''}}) is a well-founded relation, {{math|''P''(''x'')}} is some property of elements of {{mvar|X}}, and we want to show that :{{math|''P''(''x'')}} holds for all elements {{mvar|x}} of {{mvar|X}}, it suffices to show that: : If {{mvar|x}} is an element of {{mvar|X}} and {{math|''P''(''y'')}} is true for all {{mvar|y}} such that {{math|''y'' ''R'' ''x''}}, then {{math|''P''(''x'')}} must also be true. That is, <math display=block>(\forall x \in X)\;[(\forall y \in X)\;[y\mathrel{R}x \implies P(y)] \implies P(x)]\quad\text{implies}\quad(\forall x \in X)\,P(x).</math> Well-founded induction is sometimes called Noetherian induction,<ref>[[Nicolas Bourbaki|Bourbaki, N.]] (1972) ''Elements of mathematics. Commutative algebra'', Addison-Wesley.</ref> after [[Emmy Noether]]. On par with induction, well-founded relations also support construction of objects by [[transfinite recursion]]. Let {{math|(''X'', ''R'')}} be a [[binary relation#Relations over a set|set-like]] well-founded relation and {{mvar|F}} a function that assigns an object {{math|''F''(''x'', ''g'')}} to each pair of an element {{math|''x'' ∈ ''X''}} and a function {{mvar|g}} on the [[initial segment]] {{math|{{(}}''y'': ''y'' ''R'' ''x''{{)}}}} of {{mvar|X}}. Then there is a unique function {{mvar|G}} such that for every {{math|''x'' ∈ ''X''}}, <math display=block>G(x) = F\left(x, G\vert_{\left\{y:\, y\mathrel{R}x\right\}}\right).</math> That is, if we want to construct a function {{mvar|G}} on {{mvar|X}}, we may define {{math|''G''(''x'')}} using the values of {{math|''G''(''y'')}} for {{math|''y'' ''R'' ''x''}}. As an example, consider the well-founded relation {{math|('''N''', ''S'')}}, where {{math|'''N'''}} is the set of all [[natural numbers]], and {{mvar|S}} is the graph of the successor function {{math|''x'' ↦ ''x''+1}}. Then induction on {{mvar|S}} is the usual [[mathematical induction]], and recursion on {{mvar|S}} gives [[primitive recursive functions|primitive recursion]]. If we consider the order relation {{math|('''N''', <)}}, we obtain [[complete induction]], and [[course-of-values recursion]]. The statement that {{math|('''N''', <)}} is well-founded is also known as the [[well-ordering principle]]. There are other interesting special cases of well-founded induction. When the well-founded relation is the usual ordering on the class of all [[ordinal numbers]], the technique is called [[transfinite induction]]. When the well-founded set is a set of recursively-defined data structures, the technique is called [[structural induction]]. When the well-founded relation is set membership on the universal class, the technique is known as [[∈-induction]]. See those articles for more details. ==Examples== Well-founded relations that are not totally ordered include: * The positive [[integer]]s {{math|{{(}}1, 2, 3, ...{{)}}}}, with the order defined by {{math|''a'' < ''b''}} [[if and only if]] {{mvar|a}} [[divisor|divides]] {{mvar|b}} and {{math|''a'' ≠ ''b''}}. * The set of all finite [[string (computer science)|strings]] over a fixed alphabet, with the order defined by {{math|''s'' < ''t''}} if and only if {{mvar|s}} is a proper substring of {{mvar|t}}. * The set {{math|'''N''' × '''N'''}} of [[Cartesian product|pairs]] of [[natural number]]s, ordered by {{math|(''n''<sub>1</sub>, ''n''<sub>2</sub>) < (''m''<sub>1</sub>, ''m''<sub>2</sub>)}} if and only if {{math|''n''<sub>1</sub> < ''m''<sub>1</sub>}} and {{math|''n''<sub>2</sub> < ''m''<sub>2</sub>}}. * Every class whose elements are sets, with the relation ∈ ("is an element of"). This is the [[axiom of regularity]]. * The nodes of any finite [[directed acyclic graph]], with the relation {{mvar|R}} defined such that {{math|''a'' ''R'' ''b''}} if and only if there is an edge from {{mvar|a}} to {{mvar|b}}. Examples of relations that are not well-founded include: * The negative integers {{math|{{(}}−1, −2, −3, ...{{)}}}}, with the usual order, since any unbounded subset has no least element. * The set of strings over a finite alphabet with more than one element, under the usual ([[lexicographic ordering|lexicographic]]) order, since the sequence {{nowrap|"B" > "AB" > "AAB" > "AAAB" > ...}} is an infinite descending chain. This relation fails to be well-founded even though the entire set has a minimum element, namely the empty string. * The set of non-negative [[rational number]]s (or [[real numbers|reals]]) under the standard ordering, since, for example, the subset of positive rationals (or reals) lacks a minimum. ==Other properties== If {{math|(''X'', <)}} is a well-founded relation and {{mvar|x}} is an element of {{mvar|X}}, then the descending chains starting at {{mvar|x}} are all finite, but this does not mean that their lengths are necessarily bounded. Consider the following example: Let {{mvar|X}} be the union of the positive integers with a new element ω that is bigger than any integer. Then {{mvar|X}} is a well-founded set, but there are descending chains starting at ω of arbitrary great (finite) length; the chain {{math|ω, ''n'' − 1, ''n'' − 2, ..., 2, 1}} has length {{mvar|n}} for any {{mvar|n}}. The [[Mostowski collapse|Mostowski collapse lemma]] implies that set membership is a universal among the extensional well-founded relations: for any set-like well-founded relation {{mvar|R}} on a class {{mvar|X}} that is extensional, there exists a class {{mvar|C}} such that {{math|(''X'', ''R'')}} is isomorphic to {{math|(''C'', ∈)}}. ==Reflexivity== A relation {{mvar|R}} is said to be [[reflexive relation|reflexive]] if {{math|''a'' ''R'' ''a''}} holds for every {{mvar|a}} in the domain of the relation. Every reflexive relation on a nonempty domain has infinite descending chains, because any constant sequence is a descending chain. For example, in the natural numbers with their usual order ≤, we have {{nowrap|1 ≥ 1 ≥ 1 ≥ ...}}. To avoid these trivial descending sequences, when working with a partial order ≤, it is common to apply the definition of well foundedness (perhaps implicitly) to the alternate relation < defined such that {{math|''a'' < ''b''}} if and only if {{math|''a'' ≤ ''b''}} and {{math|''a'' ≠ ''b''}}. More generally, when working with a [[preorder]] ≤, it is common to use the relation < defined such that {{math|''a'' < ''b''}} if and only if {{math|''a'' ≤ ''b''}} and {{math|''b'' ≰ ''a''}}. In the context of the natural numbers, this means that the relation <, which is well-founded, is used instead of the relation ≤, which is not. In some texts, the definition of a well-founded relation is changed from the definition above to include these conventions. ==References== {{reflist}} * Just, Winfried and Weese, Martin (1998) ''Discovering Modern Set Theory. I'', [[American Mathematical Society]] {{isbn|0-8218-0266-6}}. * [[Karel Hrbáček]] & [[Thomas Jech]] (1999) ''Introduction to Set Theory'', 3rd edition, "Well-founded relations", pages 251–5, [[Marcel Dekker]] {{ISBN|0-8247-7915-0}} {{Mathematical logic}} {{Order theory}} [[Category:Wellfoundedness| ]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Cite book
(
edit
)
Template:Cite web
(
edit
)
Template:ISBN
(
edit
)
Template:Isbn
(
edit
)
Template:Math
(
edit
)
Template:Mathematical logic
(
edit
)
Template:Mvar
(
edit
)
Template:Nowrap
(
edit
)
Template:Order theory
(
edit
)
Template:Redirect
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Stack
(
edit
)