Open main menu
Home
Random
Recent changes
Special pages
Community portal
Preferences
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Incubator escapee wiki
Search
User menu
Talk
Dark mode
Contributions
Create account
Log in
Editing
Zermelo set theory
Warning:
You are not logged in. Your IP address will be publicly visible if you make any edits. If you
log in
or
create an account
, your edits will be attributed to your username, along with other benefits.
Anti-spam check. Do
not
fill this in!
{{Short description|System of mathematical set theory}} {{more footnotes|date=April 2018}} '''Zermelo set theory''' (sometimes denoted by '''Z'''<sup>'''-'''</sup>), as set out in a seminal paper in 1908 by [[Ernst Zermelo]], is the ancestor of modern [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]] (ZF) and its extensions, such as [[von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory]] (NBG). It bears certain differences from its descendants, which are not always understood, and are frequently misquoted. This article sets out the original [[axiom]]s, with the original text (translated into English) and original numbering. == The axioms of Zermelo set theory == {{Unreferenced section|date=April 2024}} The [[axiom]]s of Zermelo set theory are stated for objects, some of which (but not necessarily all) are sets, and the remaining objects are [[urelements]] and not sets. Zermelo's language implicitly includes a membership relation ∈, an equality relation = (if it is not included in the underlying logic), and a unary predicate saying whether an object is a set. Later versions of set theory often assume that all objects are sets so there are no urelements and there is no need for the unary predicate. # AXIOM I. [[Axiom of extensionality]] (''Axiom der Bestimmtheit'') "If every element of a set ''M'' is also an element of ''N'' and vice versa ... then ''M'' <math>\equiv</math> ''N''. Briefly, every set is determined by its elements." # AXIOM II. Axiom of elementary sets (''Axiom der Elementarmengen'') "There exists a set, the null set, ∅, that contains no element at all. If ''a'' is any object of the domain, there exists a set {''a''} containing ''a'' and only ''a'' as an element. If ''a'' and ''b'' are any two objects of the domain, there always exists a set {''a'', ''b''} containing as elements ''a'' and ''b'' but no object ''x'' distinct from them both." See [[Axiom of pairing|Axiom of pairs]]. # AXIOM III. [[Axiom of separation]] (''Axiom der Aussonderung'') "Whenever the [[propositional function]] –(''x'') is defined for all elements of a set ''M'', ''M'' possesses a subset ''M' '' containing as elements precisely those elements ''x'' of ''M'' for which –(''x'') is true." # AXIOM IV. [[Axiom of power set|Axiom of the power set]] (''Axiom der Potenzmenge'') "To every set ''T'' there corresponds a set ''T' '', the [[power set]] of ''T'', that contains as elements precisely all subsets of ''T'' ." # AXIOM V. [[Axiom of union|Axiom of the union]] (''Axiom der Vereinigung'') "To every set ''T'' there corresponds a set ''∪T'', the union of ''T'', that contains as elements precisely all elements of the elements of ''T'' ." # AXIOM VI. [[Axiom of choice]] (''Axiom der Auswahl'') "If ''T'' is a set whose elements all are sets that are different from ∅ and mutually disjoint, its union ''∪T'' includes at least one subset ''S''<sub>1</sub> having one and only one element in common with each element of ''T'' ." # AXIOM VII. [[Axiom of infinity]] (''Axiom des Unendlichen'') "There exists in the domain at least one set ''Z'' that contains the null set as an element and is so constituted that to each of its elements ''a'' there corresponds a further element of the form {''a''}, in other words, that with each of its elements ''a'' it also contains the corresponding set {''a''} as element." == Connection with standard set theory == The most widely used and accepted set theory is known as ZFC, which consists of [[Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory]] including the [[axiom of choice]] (AC). The links show where the axioms of Zermelo's theory correspond. There is no exact match for "elementary sets". (It was later shown that the singleton set could be derived from what is now called the "Axiom of pairs". If ''a'' exists, ''a'' and ''a'' exist, thus {''a'',''a''} exists, and so by extensionality {''a'',''a''} = {''a''}.) The empty set axiom is already assumed by axiom of infinity, and is now included as part of it. Zermelo set theory does not include the axioms of [[axiom of replacement|replacement]] and [[axiom of regularity|regularity]]. The axiom of replacement was first published in 1922 by [[Abraham Fraenkel]] and [[Thoralf Skolem]], who had independently discovered that Zermelo's axioms cannot prove the existence of the set {''Z''<sub>0</sub>, ''Z''<sub>1</sub>, ''Z''<sub>2</sub>, ...} where ''Z''<sub>0</sub> is the set of [[natural number]]s and ''Z''<sub>''n''+1</sub> is the [[power set]] of ''Z''<sub>''n''</sub>. They both realized that the axiom of replacement is needed to prove this. The following year, [[John von Neumann]] pointed out that the axiom of regularity is necessary to build [[von Neumann ordinal|his theory of ordinals]]. The axiom of regularity was stated by von Neumann in 1925.{{sfn|Ferreirós|2007|pp=369, 371}} In the modern ZFC system, the "propositional function" referred to in the axiom of separation is interpreted as "any property definable by a first-order [[Well-formed formula|formula]] with parameters", so the separation axiom is replaced by an [[axiom schema]]. The notion of "first order formula" was not known in 1908 when Zermelo published his axiom system, and he later rejected this interpretation as being too restrictive. Zermelo set theory is usually taken to be a first-order theory with the separation axiom replaced by an axiom scheme with an axiom for each first-order formula. It can also be considered as a theory in [[second-order logic]], where now the separation axiom is just a single axiom. The second-order interpretation of Zermelo set theory is probably closer to Zermelo's own conception of it, and is stronger than the first-order interpretation. Since <math>(V_\lambda , V_{\lambda + 1})</math>—where <math>V_\alpha</math> is the rank-<math>\alpha</math> set in the [[Von Neumann universe|cumulative hierarchy]]—forms a model of second-order Zermelo set theory within ZFC whenever <math>\lambda</math> is a [[limit ordinal]] greater than the smallest infinite ordinal <math>\omega</math>, it follows that the consistency of second-order Zermelo set theory (and therefore also that of first-order Zermelo set theory) is a theorem of ZFC. If we let <math>\lambda = \omega \cdot 2</math>, the existence of an [[uncountable]] [[strong limit cardinal]] is not satisfied in such a model; thus the existence of [[Beth number|''ℶ<sub>ω</sub>'']] (the smallest uncountable strong limit cardinal) cannot be proved in second-order Zermelo set theory. Similarly, the set <math>V_{\omega \cdot 2} \cap L</math> (where ''L'' is the [[constructible universe]]) forms a model of first-order Zermelo set theory wherein the existence of an uncountable weak limit cardinal is not satisfied, showing that first-order Zermelo set theory cannot even prove the existence of the smallest [[singular cardinal]], <math>\aleph_\omega</math>. Within such a model, the only infinite cardinals are the [[aleph numbers]] restricted to finite index ordinals. The [[axiom of infinity]] is usually now modified to assert the existence of the first infinite von Neumann [[ordinal number|ordinal]] <math>\omega</math>; the original Zermelo axioms cannot prove the existence of this set, nor can the modified Zermelo axioms prove Zermelo's axiom of infinity.<ref>{{cite journal |last1=Drabbe |first1=Jean |title=Les axiomes de l'infini dans la théorie des ensembles sans axiome de substitution |journal=Comptes Rendus de l'Académie des Sciences de Paris |date=20 January 1969 |volume=268 |pages=137–138 |url=https://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k480296q/f140.item |access-date=8 September 2024}}</ref> Zermelo's axioms (original or modified) cannot prove the existence of <math>V_{\omega}</math> as a set nor of any rank of the cumulative hierarchy of sets with infinite index. In any formulation, Zermelo set theory cannot prove the existence of the von Neumann ordinal <math>\omega \cdot 2</math>, despite proving the existence of such an order type; thus the von Neumann definition of ordinals is not employed for Zermelo set theory. Zermelo allowed for the existence of [[urelements]] that are not sets and contain no elements; these are now usually omitted from set theories. == Mac Lane set theory == Mac Lane set theory, introduced by {{harvs|txt|last=Mac Lane|year=1986|authorlink=Saunders Mac Lane}}, is Zermelo set theory with the axiom of separation restricted to first-order formulas in which every quantifier is bounded. Mac Lane set theory is similar in strength to [[topos theory]] with a [[natural number object]], or to the system in [[Principia mathematica]]. It is strong enough to carry out almost all ordinary mathematics not directly connected with set theory or logic. == The aim of Zermelo's paper == The introduction states that the very existence of the discipline of set theory "seems to be threatened by certain contradictions or "antinomies", that can be derived from its principles – principles necessarily governing our thinking, it seems – and to which no entirely satisfactory solution has yet been found". Zermelo is of course referring to the "[[Russell's paradox|Russell antinomy]]". He says he wants to show how the original theory of [[Georg Cantor]] and [[Richard Dedekind]] can be reduced to a few definitions and seven principles or axioms. He says he has ''not'' been able to prove that the axioms are consistent. A non-constructivist argument for their consistency goes as follows. Define ''V''<sub>α</sub> for α one of the [[Ordinal number|ordinals]] 0, 1, 2, ...,ω, ω+1, ω+2,..., ω·2 as follows: * V<sub>0</sub> is the empty set. * For α a successor of the form β+1, ''V''<sub>α</sub> is defined to be the collection of all subsets of ''V''<sub>β</sub>. * For α a limit (e.g. ω, ω·2) then ''V''<sub>α</sub> is defined to be the union of ''V''<sub>β</sub> for β<α. Then the axioms of Zermelo set theory are consistent because they are true in the model ''V''<sub>ω·2</sub>. While a non-constructivist might regard this as a valid argument, a constructivist would probably not: while there are no problems with the construction of the sets up to ''V''<sub>ω</sub>, the construction of ''V''<sub>ω+1</sub> is less clear because one cannot constructively define every subset of ''V''<sub>ω</sub>. This argument can be turned into a valid proof with the addition of a single new axiom of infinity to Zermelo set theory, simply that ''V''<sub>ω·2</sub> ''exists''. This is presumably not convincing for a constructivist, but it shows that the consistency of Zermelo set theory can be proved with a theory which is not very different from Zermelo theory itself, only a little more powerful. == The axiom of separation == Zermelo comments that Axiom III of his system is the one responsible for eliminating the antinomies. It differs from the original definition by Cantor, as follows. Sets cannot be independently defined by any arbitrary logically definable notion. They must be constructed in some way from previously constructed sets. For example, they can be constructed by taking powersets, or they can be ''separated'' as subsets of sets already "given". This, he says, eliminates contradictory ideas like "the set of all sets" or "the set of all ordinal numbers". He disposes of the [[Russell paradox]] by means of this Theorem: "Every set <math>M</math> possesses at least one subset <math>M_0</math> that is not an element of <math>M</math> ". Let <math>M_0</math> be the subset of <math>M</math> which, by AXIOM III, is separated out by the notion "<math>x \notin x</math>". Then <math>M_0</math> cannot be in <math>M</math>. For # If <math>M_0</math> is in <math>M_0</math>, then <math>M_0</math> contains an element ''x'' for which ''x'' is in ''x'' (i.e. <math>M_0</math> itself), which would contradict the definition of <math>M_0</math>. # If <math>M_0</math> is not in <math>M_0</math>, and assuming <math>M_0</math> is an element of ''M'', then <math>M_0</math> is an element of ''M'' that satisfies the definition "<math>x \notin x</math>", and so is in <math>M_0</math> which is a contradiction. Therefore, the assumption that <math>M_0</math> is in <math>M</math> is wrong, proving the theorem. Hence not all objects of the universal domain ''B'' can be elements of one and the same set. "This disposes of the Russell [[antinomy]] as far as we are concerned". This left the problem of "the domain ''B''" which seems to refer to something. This led to the idea of a [[proper class]]. == Cantor's theorem == Zermelo's paper may be the first to mention the name "[[Cantor's theorem]]". Cantor's theorem: "If ''M'' is an arbitrary set, then always ''M'' < P(''M'') [the power set of ''M'']. Every set is of lower cardinality than the set of its subsets". Zermelo proves this by considering a function φ: ''M'' → P(''M''). By Axiom III this defines the following set ''M' '': :''M' '' = {''m'': ''m'' ∉ φ(''m'')}. But no element ''m' '' of ''M '' could correspond to ''M' '', i.e. such that φ(''m' '') = ''M' ''. Otherwise we can construct a contradiction: # If ''m' '' is in ''M' '' then by definition ''m' '' ∉ φ(''m' '') = ''M' '', which is the first part of the contradiction # If ''m' '' is not in ''M' '' but in ''M '' then by definition ''m' '' ∉ ''M' '' = φ(''m' '') which by definition implies that ''m' '' is in ''M' '', which is the second part of the contradiction. so by contradiction ''m' '' does not exist. Note the close resemblance of this proof to the way Zermelo disposes of Russell's paradox. == See also == * [[S (set theory)]] == References == {{Reflist}} === Works cited === * {{citation |last=Ferreirós|first=José|year=2007|title=Labyrinth of Thought: A History of Set Theory and Its Role in Mathematical Thought|publisher=Birkhäuser|isbn=978-3-7643-8349-7}}. === General references === *{{citation|mr=0816347|last=Mac Lane|first= Saunders|author-link=Saunders Mac Lane|title=Mathematics, form and function|publisher= Springer-Verlag|place= New York|year= 1986|isbn= 0-387-96217-4|doi=10.1007/978-1-4612-4872-9}}. *{{citation|author-link=Ernst Zermelo|first=Ernst|last= Zermelo|year=1908|title=Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I|journal=Mathematische Annalen |volume=65|issue=2|pages= 261–281|url = https://zenodo.org/records/1428264/files/article.pdf|doi=10.1007/bf01449999|s2cid=120085563}}. English translation: {{citation|author-link=Jean van Heijenoort|first=Jean van|last= Heijenoort |year=1967 |title= From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879-1931 |series=Source Books in the History of the Sciences |chapter=Investigations in the foundations of set theory|publisher=Harvard Univ. Press|pages=199–215|isbn= 978-0-674-32449-7}}. {{Set theory}} [[Category:Systems of set theory]]
Edit summary
(Briefly describe your changes)
By publishing changes, you agree to the
Terms of Use
, and you irrevocably agree to release your contribution under the
CC BY-SA 4.0 License
and the
GFDL
. You agree that a hyperlink or URL is sufficient attribution under the Creative Commons license.
Cancel
Editing help
(opens in new window)
Pages transcluded onto the current version of this page
(
help
)
:
Template:Citation
(
edit
)
Template:Cite journal
(
edit
)
Template:Harvs
(
edit
)
Template:More footnotes
(
edit
)
Template:Reflist
(
edit
)
Template:Set theory
(
edit
)
Template:Sfn
(
edit
)
Template:Short description
(
edit
)
Template:Unreferenced section
(
edit
)