Probability axioms

Revision as of 04:30, 19 April 2025 by imported>RJFJR (→‎Proof of monotonicity: move ref out of heading)
(diff) ← Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

Template:Short description Template:Probability fundamentals The standard probability axioms are the foundations of probability theory introduced by Russian mathematician Andrey Kolmogorov in 1933.<ref name=":0">Template:Cite book</ref> These axioms remain central and have direct contributions to mathematics, the physical sciences, and real-world probability cases.<ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref>

There are several other (equivalent) approaches to formalising probability. Bayesians will often motivate the Kolmogorov axioms by invoking Cox's theorem or the Dutch book arguments instead.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite book</ref>

Kolmogorov axiomsEdit

The assumptions as to setting up the axioms can be summarised as follows: Let <math>(\Omega, F, P)</math> be a measure space such that <math>P(E)</math> is the probability of some event <math>E</math>, and <math>P(\Omega) = 1</math>. Then <math>(\Omega, F, P)</math> is a probability space, with sample space <math>\Omega</math>, event space <math>F</math> and probability measure <math>P</math>.<ref name=":0" />

Template:AnchorFirst axiomEdit

The probability of an event is a non-negative real number:

<math>P(E)\in\mathbb{R}, P(E)\geq 0 \qquad \forall E \in F</math>

where <math>F</math> is the event space. It follows (when combined with the second axiom) that <math>P(E)</math> is always finite, in contrast with more general measure theory. Theories which assign negative probability relax the first axiom.

Template:AnchorSecond axiomEdit

This is the assumption of unit measure: that the probability that at least one of the elementary events in the entire sample space will occur is 1.

<math>P(\Omega) = 1</math>

Template:AnchorThird axiomEdit

This is the assumption of σ-additivity:

Any countable sequence of disjoint sets (synonymous with mutually exclusive events) <math>E_1, E_2, \ldots</math> satisfies
<math>P\left(\bigcup_{i = 1}^\infty E_i\right) = \sum_{i=1}^\infty P(E_i).</math>

Some authors consider merely finitely additive probability spaces, in which case one just needs an algebra of sets, rather than a σ-algebra.<ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref> Quasiprobability distributions in general relax the third axiom.

ConsequencesEdit

From the Kolmogorov axioms, one can deduce other useful rules for studying probabilities. The proofs<ref name=":1">Template:Cite book</ref><ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref><ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref> of these rules are a very insightful procedure that illustrates the power of the third axiom, and its interaction with the prior two axioms. Four of the immediate corollaries and their proofs are shown below:

MonotonicityEdit

<math>\quad\text{if}\quad A\subseteq B\quad\text{then}\quad P(A)\leq P(B).</math>

If A is a subset of, or equal to B, then the probability of A is less than, or equal to the probability of B.

Proof of monotonicityEdit

Source:<ref name=":1" />

In order to verify the monotonicity property, we set <math>E_1=A</math> and <math>E_2=B\setminus A</math>, where <math>A\subseteq B</math> and <math>E_i=\varnothing</math> for <math>i\geq 3</math>. From the properties of the empty set (<math>\varnothing</math>), it is easy to see that the sets <math>E_i</math> are pairwise disjoint and <math>E_1\cup E_2\cup\cdots=B</math>. Hence, we obtain from the third axiom that

<math>P(A)+P(B\setminus A)+\sum_{i=3}^\infty P(E_i)=P(B).</math>

Since, by the first axiom, the left-hand side of this equation is a series of non-negative numbers, and since it converges to <math>P(B)</math> which is finite, we obtain both <math>P(A)\leq P(B)</math> and <math>P(\varnothing)=0</math>.

The probability of the empty setEdit

<math>P(\varnothing)=0.</math>

In many cases, <math>\varnothing</math> is not the only event with probability 0.

Proof of the probability of the empty setEdit

<math>P(\varnothing \cup \varnothing) = P(\varnothing)</math> since <math>\varnothing \cup \varnothing = \varnothing</math>,

<math>P(\varnothing)+P(\varnothing) = P(\varnothing)</math> by applying the third axiom to the left-hand side (note <math>\varnothing</math> is disjoint with itself), and so

<math>P(\varnothing) = 0</math> by subtracting <math>P(\varnothing)</math> from each side of the equation.

The complement ruleEdit

<math>P\left(A^{\complement}\right) = P(\Omega-A) = 1 - P(A)</math>

Proof of the complement ruleEdit

Given <math>A</math> and <math>A^{\complement}</math> are mutually exclusive and that <math>A \cup A^\complement = \Omega </math>:

<math>P(A \cup A^\complement)=P(A)+P(A^\complement) </math> ... (by axiom 3)

and, <math> P(A \cup A^\complement)=P(\Omega)=1 </math> ... (by axiom 2)

<math> \Rightarrow P(A)+P(A^\complement)=1 </math>

<math>\therefore P(A^\complement)=1-P(A) </math>

The numeric boundEdit

It immediately follows from the monotonicity property that

<math>0\leq P(E)\leq 1\qquad \forall E\in F.</math>

Proof of the numeric boundEdit

Given the complement rule <math>P(E^c)=1-P(E) </math> and axiom 1 <math>P(E^c)\geq0 </math>:

<math>1-P(E) \geq 0 </math>

<math>\Rightarrow 1 \geq P(E) </math>

<math>\therefore 0\leq P(E)\leq 1</math>

Further consequencesEdit

Another important property is:

<math>P(A \cup B) = P(A) + P(B) - P(A \cap B).</math>

This is called the addition law of probability, or the sum rule. That is, the probability that an event in A or B will happen is the sum of the probability of an event in A and the probability of an event in B, minus the probability of an event that is in both A and B. The proof of this is as follows:

Firstly,

<math>P(A\cup B) = P(A) + P(B\setminus A)</math>. (by Axiom 3)

So,

<math>P(A \cup B) = P(A) + P(B\setminus (A \cap B))</math> (by <math>B \setminus A = B\setminus (A \cap B)</math>).

Also,

<math>P(B) = P(B\setminus (A \cap B)) + P(A \cap B)</math>

and eliminating <math>P(B\setminus (A \cap B))</math> from both equations gives us the desired result.

An extension of the addition law to any number of sets is the inclusion–exclusion principle.

Setting B to the complement Ac of A in the addition law gives

<math>P\left(A^{c}\right) = P(\Omega\setminus A) = 1 - P(A)</math>

That is, the probability that any event will not happen (or the event's complement) is 1 minus the probability that it will.

Simple example: coin tossEdit

Consider a single coin-toss, and assume that the coin will either land heads (H) or tails (T) (but not both). No assumption is made as to whether the coin is fair or as to whether or not any bias depends on how the coin is tossed.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>

We may define:

<math>\Omega = \{H,T\}</math>
<math>F = \{\varnothing, \{H\}, \{T\}, \{H,T\}\}</math>

Kolmogorov's axioms imply that:

<math>P(\varnothing) = 0</math>

The probability of neither heads nor tails, is 0.

<math>P(\{H,T\}^c) = 0</math>

The probability of either heads or tails, is 1.

<math>P(\{H\}) + P(\{T\}) = 1</math>

The sum of the probability of heads and the probability of tails, is 1.

See alsoEdit

ReferencesEdit

Template:Reflist

Further readingEdit