Square of opposition

Revision as of 02:23, 4 March 2025 by imported>Remsense (whatever this is, it doesn't go here)
(diff) ← Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

Template:Short description Template:Refimprove

File:Square of opposition, set diagrams.svg
Square of opposition. The lower case letters (a, e, i, o) are used instead of the upper case letters (A, E, I, O) here in order to be visually distinguished from the surrounding upper case letters S (Subject term) and P (Predicate term). In the Venn diagrams, black areas are empty and red areas are nonempty. White areas may or may not be empty. The faded arrows and faded red areas apply in traditional logic assuming the existence of things stated as Template:Mvar (or things satisfying a statement Template:Mvar in modern logic). In modern logic, this is not assumed so the faded ones do not hold. (There can be no element in the faded red areas in the modern logic.)
File:Johannesmagistris-square.jpg
Depiction from the 15th century

In term logic (a branch of philosophical logic), the square of opposition is a diagram representing the relations between the four basic categorical propositions. The origin of the square can be traced back to Aristotle's tractate On Interpretation and its distinction between two oppositions: contradiction and contrariety. However, Aristotle did not draw any diagram; this was done several centuries later by Boethius.

SummaryEdit

In traditional logic, a proposition (Latin: propositio) is a spoken assertion (oratio enunciativa), not the meaning of an assertion, as in modern philosophy of language and logic. A categorical proposition is a simple proposition containing two terms, subject (Template:Mvar) and predicate (Template:Mvar), in which the predicate is either asserted or denied of the subject.

Every categorical proposition can be reduced to one of four logical forms, named Template:Mvar, Template:Mvar, Template:Mvar, and Template:Mvar based on the Latin {{#invoke:Lang|lang}} (I affirm), for the affirmative propositions Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar, and {{#invoke:Lang|lang}} (I deny), for the negative propositions Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar. These are:

In tabular form:

The four Aristotelian propositions
Name Symbol Latin English* Mnemonic Modern form<ref>Per The Traditional Square of Opposition: 1.1 The Modern Revision of the Square in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy</ref>
Universal affirmative Template:Mvar Omne Template:Mvar est Template:Mvar. Every Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar.
(Template:Mvar is always Template:Mvar.)
lang}}
(I affirm)
<math>\forall x (Sx \rightarrow Px)</math>
Universal negative Template:Mvar Nullum Template:Mvar est Template:Mvar. No Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar.
(Template:Mvar is never Template:Mvar.)
lang}}
(I deny)
<math>\forall x (Sx \rightarrow \neg Px)</math>
Particular affirmative Template:Mvar Quoddam Template:Mvar est Template:Mvar. Some Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar.
(Template:Mvar is sometimes Template:Mvar.)
lang}}
(I affirm)
<math>\exist x (Sx \land Px)</math>
Particular negative Template:Mvar Quoddam Template:Mvar nōn est Template:Mvar. Some Template:Mvar is not Template:Mvar.
(Template:Mvar is not always Template:Mvar.)
lang}}
(I deny)
<math>\exist x (Sx \land \neg Px)</math>

*Proposition Template:Mvar may be stated as "All Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar." However, Proposition Template:Mvar when stated correspondingly as "All Template:Mvar is not Template:Mvar." is ambiguous<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> because it can be either an Template:Mvar or Template:Mvar proposition, thus requiring a context to determine the form; the standard form "No Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar" is unambiguous, so it is preferred. Proposition Template:Mvar also takes the forms "Sometimes Template:Mvar is not Template:Mvar." and "A certain Template:Mvar is not Template:Mvar." (literally the Latin 'Quoddam Template:Mvar nōn est Template:Mvar.')

** <math>Sx</math> in the modern forms means that a statement <math>S</math> applies on an object <math>x</math>. It may be simply interpreted as "<math>x</math> is <math>S</math>" in many cases. <math>Sx</math> can be also written as <math>S(x)</math>.

Aristotle states (in chapters six and seven of the Peri hermēneias (Περὶ Ἑρμηνείας, Latin De Interpretatione, English 'On Interpretation')), that there are certain logical relationships between these four kinds of proposition. He says that to every affirmation there corresponds exactly one negation, and that every affirmation and its negation are 'opposed' such that always one of them must be true, and the other false. A pair of an affirmative statement and its negation is, he calls, a 'contradiction' (in medieval Latin, contradictio). Examples of contradictories are 'every man is white' and 'not every man is white' (also read as 'some men are not white'), 'no man is white' and 'some man is white'.

The below relations, contrary, subcontrary, subalternation, and superalternation, do hold based on the traditional logic assumption that things stated as Template:Mvar (or things satisfying a statement Template:Mvar in modern logic) exist. If this assumption is taken out, then these relations do not hold.

'Contrary' (medieval: contrariae) statements, are such that both statements cannot be true at the same time. Examples of these are the universal affirmative 'every man is white', and the universal negative 'no man is white'. These cannot be true at the same time. However, these are not contradictories because both of them may be false. For example, it is false that every man is white, since some men are not white. Yet it is also false that no man is white, since there are some white men.

Since every statement has the contradictory opposite (its negation), and since a contradicting statement is true when its opposite is false, it follows that the opposites of contraries (which the medievals called subcontraries, subcontrariae) can both be true, but they cannot both be false. Since subcontraries are negations of universal statements, they were called 'particular' statements by the medieval logicians.

Another logical relation implied by this, though not mentioned explicitly by Aristotle, is 'alternation' (alternatio), consisting of 'subalternation' and 'superalternation'. Subalternation is a relation between the particular statement and the universal statement of the same quality (affirmative or negative) such that the particular is implied by the universal, while superalternation is a relation between them such that the falsity of the universal (equivalently the negation of the universal) is implied by the falsity of the particular (equivalently the negation of the particular).<ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref> (The superalternation is the contrapositive of the subalternation.) In these relations, the particular is the subaltern of the universal, which is the particular's superaltern. For example, if 'every man is white' is true, its contrary 'no man is white' is false. Therefore, the contradictory 'some man is white' is true. Similarly the universal 'no man is white' implies the particular 'not every man is white'.<ref>Parry & Hacker, Aristotelian Logic (SUNY Press, 1990), p. 158.</ref><ref>Cohen & Nagel, Introduction to Logic Second Edition (Hackett Publishing, 1993), p. 55.</ref>

In summary:

These relationships became the basis of a diagram originating with Boethius and used by medieval logicians to classify the logical relationships. The propositions are placed in the four corners of a square, and the relations represented as lines drawn between them, whence the name 'The Square of Opposition'. Therefore, the following cases can be made:<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>

  1. If Template:Mvar is true, then Template:Mvar is false, Template:Mvar is true, Template:Mvar is false;
  2. If Template:Mvar is true, then Template:Mvar is false, Template:Mvar is false, Template:Mvar is true;
  3. If Template:Mvar is true, then Template:Mvar is false, Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar are indeterminate;
  4. If Template:Mvar is true, then Template:Mvar is false, Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar are indeterminate;
  5. If Template:Mvar is false, then Template:Mvar is true, Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar are indeterminate;
  6. If Template:Mvar is false, then Template:Mvar is true, Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar are indeterminate;
  7. If Template:Mvar is false, then Template:Mvar is false, Template:Mvar is true, Template:Mvar is true;
  8. If Template:Mvar is false, then Template:Mvar is true, Template:Mvar is false, Template:Mvar is true.

To memorize them, the medievals invented the following Latin rhyme:<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>

Template:Mvar adfirmat, negat Template:Mvar, sed universaliter ambae;
Template:Mvar firmat, negat Template:Mvar, sed particulariter ambae.

It affirms that Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar are not neither both true nor both false in each of the above cases. The same applies to Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar. While the first two are universal statements, the couple Template:Mvar / Template:Mvar refers to particular ones.

The Square of Oppositions was used for the categorical inferences described by the Greek philosopher Aristotle: conversion, obversion and contraposition. Each of those three types of categorical inference was applied to the four Boethian logical forms: Template:Mvar, Template:Mvar, Template:Mvar, and Template:Mvar.

The problem of existential importEdit

{{#invoke:Labelled list hatnote|labelledList|Main article|Main articles|Main page|Main pages}} Subcontraries (Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar), which medieval logicians represented in the form 'quoddam Template:Mvar est Template:Mvar' (some particular Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar) and 'quoddam Template:Mvar non est Template:Mvar' (some particular Template:Mvar is not Template:Mvar) cannot both be false, since their universal contradictory statements (no Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar / every Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar) cannot both be true. This leads to a difficulty firstly identified by Peter Abelard (1079 – 21 April 1142). 'Some Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar' seems to imply 'something is Template:Mvar', in other words, there exists something that is Template:Mvar. For example, 'Some man is white' seems to imply that at least one thing that exists is a man, namely the man who has to be white, if 'some man is white' is true. But, 'some man is not white' also implies that something as a man exists, namely the man who is not white, if the statement 'some man is not white' is true. But Aristotelian logic requires that, necessarily, one of these statements (more generally 'some particular Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar' and 'some particular Template:Mvar is not Template:Mvar') is true, i.e., they cannot both be false. Therefore, since both statements imply the presence of at least one thing that is a man, the presence of a man or men is followed. But, as Abelard points out in the Dialectica, surely men might not exist?<ref>In his Dialectica, and in his commentary on the De Interpretatione.</ref>

For with absolutely no man existing, neither the proposition 'every man is a man' is true nor 'some man is not a man'.<ref>Re enim hominis prorsus non existente neque ea vera est quae ait: omnis homo est homo, nec ea quae proponit: quidam homo non est homo.</ref>

Abelard also points out that subcontraries containing subject terms denoting nothing, such as 'a man who is a stone', are both false.

If 'every stone-man is a stone' is true, also its conversion per accidens is true ('some stones are stone-men'). But no stone is a stone-man, because neither this man nor that man etc. is a stone. But also this 'a certain stone-man is not a stone' is false by necessity, since it is impossible to suppose it is true.<ref>Si enim vera est: Omnis homo qui lapis est, est lapis, et eius conversa per accidens vera est: Quidam lapis est homo qui est lapis. Sed nullus lapis est homo qui est lapis, quia neque hic neque ille etc. Sed et illam: Quidam homo qui est lapis, non est lapis, falsam esse necesse est, cum impossibile ponat.</ref>

Terence Parsons (born 1939) argues that ancient philosophers did not experience the problem of existential import as only the A (universal affirmative) and I (particular affirmative) forms had existential import. (If a statement includes a term such that the statement is false if the term has no instances, i.e., no thing associated with the term exists, then the statement is said to have existential import with respect to that term.)

Affirmatives have existential import, and negatives do not. The ancients thus did not see the incoherence of the square as formulated by Aristotle because there was no incoherence to see.<ref>Template:Citation.</ref>

He goes on to cite a medieval philosopher William of Ockham (1215–35 – Template:Circa),

In affirmative propositions a term is always asserted to supposit for something. Thus, if it supposits for nothing the proposition is false. However, in negative propositions the assertion is either that the term does not supposit for something or that it supposits for something of which the predicate is truly denied. Thus a negative proposition has two causes of truth.<ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation

|CitationClass=web }}</ref>

And points to Boethius' translation of Aristotle's work as giving rise to the mistaken notion that the Template:Mvar form has existential import.

But when Boethius (477 – 524 AD) comments on this text he illustrates Aristotle's doctrine with the now-famous diagram, and he uses the wording 'Some man is not just'. So this must have seemed to him to be a natural equivalent in Latin. It looks odd to us in English, but he wasn't bothered by it.<ref>Template:Citation.</ref>

Modern squares of oppositionEdit

File:Frege-gegensätze.png
Frege's square of opposition
The conträr below is an erratum:
It should read subconträr.

In the 19th century, George Boole (November 1815 – 8 December 1864) argued for requiring existential import on both terms in particular claims (Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar), but allowing all terms of universal claims (Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar) to lack existential import. This decision made Venn diagrams particularly easy to use for term logic. The square of opposition, under this Boolean set of assumptions, is often called the modern square of opposition. In the modern square of opposition, Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar claims are contradictories, as are Template:Mvar and Template:Mvar, but all other forms of opposition cease to hold; there are no contraries, subcontraries, subalternations, and superalternations. Thus, from a modern point of view, it often makes sense to talk about 'the' opposition of a claim, rather than insisting, as older logicians did, that a claim has several different opposites, which are in different kinds of opposition with the claim.

Gottlob Frege (8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925)'s Begriffsschrift also presents a square of oppositions, organised in an almost identical manner to the classical square, showing the contradictories, subalternates and contraries between four formulae constructed from universal quantification, negation and implication.

Algirdas Julien Greimas (9 March 1917 – 27 February 1992)' semiotic square was derived from Aristotle's work.

The traditional square of opposition is now often compared with squares based on inner- and outer-negation.<ref>Westerståhl, 'Classical vs. modern squares of opposition, and beyond', in Beziau and Payette (eds.), The Square of Opposition: A General Framework for Cognition, Peter Lang, Bern, 195-229.</ref>

Logical hexagons and other bi-simplexesEdit

{{#invoke:Labelled list hatnote|labelledList|Main article|Main articles|Main page|Main pages}}

The square of opposition has been extended to a logical hexagon which includes the relationships of six statements. It was discovered independently by both Augustin Sesmat (April 7, 1885 – December 12, 1957) and Robert Blanché (1898–1975).<ref>N-Opposition Theory Logical hexagon</ref> It has been proven that both the square and the hexagon, followed by a "logical cube", belong to a regular series of n-dimensional objects called "logical bi-simplexes of dimension Template:Mvar." The pattern also goes even beyond this.<ref>Moretti, Pellissier</ref>

Square of opposition (or logical square) and modal logicEdit

The logical square, also called square of opposition or square of Apuleius, has its origin in the four marked sentences to be employed in syllogistic reasoning: "Every man is bad," the universal affirmative - The negation of the universal affirmative "Not every man is bad" (or "Some men are not bad") - "Some men are bad," the particular affirmative - and finally, the negation of the particular affirmative "No man is bad". Robert Blanché published with Vrin his Structures intellectuelles in 1966 and since then many scholars think that the logical square or square of opposition representing four values should be replaced by the logical hexagon which by representing six values is a more potent figure because it has the power to explain more things about logic and natural language.

Set-theoretical interpretation of categorical statementsEdit

In modern mathematical logic, statements containing words "all", "some" and "no", can be stated in terms of set theory if we assume a set-like domain of discourse. If the set of all Template:Mvar's is labeled as <math>s(A)</math> and the set of all Template:Mvar's as <math>s(B)</math>, then:

  • "All Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar" (AaB) is equivalent to "<math>s(A)</math> is a subset of <math>s(B)</math>", or <math>s(A) \subseteq s(B)</math>.
  • "No Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar" (AeB) is equivalent to "The intersection of <math>s(A)</math> and <math>s(B)</math> is empty", or <math>s(A) \cap s(B) = \empty</math>.
  • "Some Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar" (AiB) is equivalent to "The intersection of <math>s(A)</math> and <math>s(B)</math> is not empty", or <math>s(A) \cap s(B) \neq \empty</math>.
  • "Some Template:Mvar is not Template:Mvar" (AoB) is equivalent to "<math>s(A)</math> is not a subset of <math>s(B)</math>", or <math>s(A) \nsubseteq s(B)</math>.

By definition, the empty set <math>\empty</math> is a subset of all sets. From this fact it follows that, according to this mathematical convention, if there are no Template:Mvar's, then the statements "All Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar" and "No Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar" are always true whereas the statements "Some Template:Mvar is Template:Mvar" and "Some Template:Mvar is not Template:Mvar" are always false. This also implies that AaB does not entail AiB, and some of the syllogisms mentioned above are not valid when there are no Template:Mvar's (<math>s(A) = \empty</math>).

See alsoEdit

ReferencesEdit

Template:Reflist

External linksEdit

Template:Sister project

Template:Aristotelian logicTemplate:Mathematical logic Template:Diagrams in logic