Intransitivity

Revision as of 14:15, 20 February 2025 by imported>Jochen Burghardt (→‎top: both forms are discourage, per MOS:NOTE)
(diff) ← Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

Template:About Template:Short description In mathematics, intransitivity (sometimes called nontransitivity) is a property of binary relations that are not transitive relations. That is, we can find three values <math>a</math>, <math>b</math>, and <math>c</math> where the transitive condition does not hold.

Antitransitivity is a stronger property which describes a relation where, for any three values, the transitivity condition never holds.

Some authors use the term Template:Em to refer to antitransitivity.<ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref><ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref>

IntransitivityEdit

A relation is transitive if, whenever it relates some A to some B, and that B to some C, it also relates that A to that C. A relation is Template:Em if it is not transitive. Assuming the relation is named <math>R</math>, it is intransitive if:

<math display=block>\lnot\left(\forall a, b, c: a R b \land b R c \implies a R c\right).</math>

This statement is equivalent to <math display=block>\exists a,b,c : a R b \land b R c \land \lnot(a R c).</math>

For example, the inequality relation, <math>\neq</math>, is intransitive. This can be demonstrated by replacing <math>R</math> with <math>\neq</math> and choosing <math>a=1</math>, <math>b=2</math>, and <math>c=1</math>. We have <math>1\neq 2</math> and <math>2\neq 1</math> and it is not true that <math>1\neq 1</math>.

Notice that, for a relation to be intransitive, the transitivity condition just has to be not true at some <math>a</math>, <math>b</math>, and <math>c</math>. It can still hold for others. For example, it holds when <math>a=1</math>, <math>b=2</math>, and <math>c=3</math>, then <math>1\neq 2</math> and <math>2\neq 3</math> and it is true that <math>1\neq 3</math>.

For a more complicated example of intransitivity, consider the relation R on the integers such that a R b if and only if a is a multiple of b or a divisor of b. This relation is intransitive since, for example, 2 R 6 (2 is a divisor of 6) and 6 R 3 (6 is a multiple of 3), but 2 is neither a multiple nor a divisor of 3. This does not imply that the relation is Template:Em (see below); for example, 2 R 6, 6 R 12, and 2 R 12 as well.

An example in biology comes from the food chain. Wolves feed on deer, and deer feed on grass, but wolves do not feed on grass.<ref>Wolves do in fact eat grass – see Template:Cite book.</ref> Thus, the Template:Em relation among life forms is intransitive, in this sense.

AntitransitivityEdit

Antitransitivity for a relation says that the transitive condition does not hold for any three values.

In the example above, the Template:Em relation is not transitive, but it still contains some transitivity: for instance, humans feed on rabbits, rabbits feed on carrots, and humans also feed on carrots.

A relation is Template:Em if this never occurs at all. The formal definition is: <math display=block>\forall a, b, c: a R b \land b R c \implies \lnot (a R c).</math>

For example, the relation R on the integers, such that a R b if and only if a + b is odd, is intransitive. If a R b and b R c, then either a and c are both odd and b is even, or vice-versa. In either case, a + c is even.

A second example of an antitransitive relation: the defeated relation in knockout tournaments. If player A defeated player B and player B defeated player C, A can have never played C, and therefore, A has not defeated C.

By transposition, each of the following formulas is equivalent to antitransitivity of R: <math display=block>\begin{align}

 &\forall a, b, c: a R b \land a R c \implies \lnot (b R c) \\[3pt]
 &\forall a, b, c: a R c \land b R c \implies \lnot (a R b)

\end{align}</math>

PropertiesEdit

  • An antitransitive relation is always irreflexive.
  • An antitransitive relation on a set of ≥4 elements is never connex. On a 3-element set, the depicted cycle has both properties.
  • An irreflexive and left- (or right-) unique relation is always anti-transitive.<ref>If aRb, bRc, and aRc would hold for some a, b, c, then Template:Math by left uniqueness, contradicting aRb by irreflexivity.</ref> An example of the former is the mother relation. If A is the mother of B, and B the mother of C, then A cannot be the mother of C.
  • If a relation R is antitransitive, so is each subset of R.

CyclesEdit

File:Three-part cycle diagram.png
Sometimes, when people are asked their preferences through a series of binary questions, they will give logically impossible responses: 1 is better than 2, and 2 is better than 3, but 3 is better than 1.

The term Template:Em is often used when speaking of scenarios in which a relation describes the relative preferences between pairs of options, and weighing several options produces a "loop" of preference:

  • A is preferred to B
  • B is preferred to C
  • C is preferred to A

Rock, paper, scissors; intransitive dice; and Penney's game are examples. Real combative relations of competing species,<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref> strategies of individual animals,<ref>Leutwyler, K. (2000). Mating Lizards Play a Game of Rock-Paper-Scissors. Scientific American.</ref> and fights of remote-controlled vehicles in BattleBots shows ("robot Darwinism")<ref>Atherton, K. D. (2013). A brief history of the demise of battle bots.</ref> can be cyclic as well.

Assuming no option is preferred to itself i.e. the relation is irreflexive, a preference relation with a loop is not transitive. For if it is, each option in the loop is preferred to each option, including itself. This can be illustrated for this example of a loop among A, B, and C. Assume the relation is transitive. Then, since A is preferred to B and B is preferred to C, also A is preferred to C. But then, since C is preferred to A, also A is preferred to A.

Therefore such a preference loop (or Template:Em) is known as an Template:Em.

Notice that a cycle is neither necessary nor sufficient for a binary relation to be not transitive. For example, an equivalence relation possesses cycles but is transitive. Now, consider the relation "is an enemy of" and suppose that the relation is symmetric and satisfies the condition that for any country, any enemy of an enemy of the country is not itself an enemy of the country. This is an example of an antitransitive relation that does not have any cycles. In particular, by virtue of being antitransitive the relation is not transitive.

The game of rock, paper, scissors is an example. The relation over rock, paper, and scissors is "defeats", and the standard rules of the game are such that rock defeats scissors, scissors defeats paper, and paper defeats rock. Furthermore, it is also true that scissors does not defeat rock, paper does not defeat scissors, and rock does not defeat paper. Finally, it is also true that no option defeats itself. This information can be depicted in a table:

rock scissors paper
rock 0 1 0
scissors 0 0 1
paper 1 0 0

The first argument of the relation is a row and the second one is a column. Ones indicate the relation holds, zero indicates that it does not hold. Now, notice that the following statement is true for any pair of elements x and y drawn (with replacement) from the set {rock, scissors, paper}: If x defeats y, and y defeats z, then x does not defeat z. Hence the relation is antitransitive.

Thus, a cycle is neither necessary nor sufficient for a binary relation to be antitransitive.

Occurrences in preferencesEdit

LikelihoodEdit

It has been suggested that Condorcet voting tends to eliminate "intransitive loops" when large numbers of voters participate because the overall assessment criteria for voters balances out. For instance, voters may prefer candidates on several different units of measure such as by order of social consciousness or by order of most fiscally conservative.

In such cases intransitivity reduces to a broader equation of numbers of people and the weights of their units of measure in assessing candidates.

Such as:

  • 30% favor 60/40 weighting between social consciousness and fiscal conservatism
  • 50% favor 50/50 weighting between social consciousness and fiscal conservatism
  • 20% favor a 40/60 weighting between social consciousness and fiscal conservatism

While each voter may not assess the units of measure identically, the trend then becomes a single vector on which the consensus agrees is a preferred balance of candidate criteria.

ReferencesEdit

Template:Reflist Template:Reflist

Further readingEdit