Projectively extended real line

Revision as of 01:21, 19 May 2025 by imported>Beland (custom spacing in math formulas (via WP:JWB))
(diff) ← Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

Template:Short description Template:About

Template:More cn

File:Real projective line.svg
The projectively extended real line can be visualized as the real number line wrapped around a circle (by some form of stereographic projection) with an additional point at infinity.

In real analysis, the projectively extended real line (also called the one-point compactification of the real line), is the extension of the set of the real numbers, <math>\mathbb{R}</math>, by a point denoted Template:Math.<ref name=":0">Template:Cite book</ref> It is thus the set <math>\mathbb{R}\cup\{\infty\}</math> with the standard arithmetic operations extended where possible,<ref name=":0" /> and is sometimes denoted by <math>\mathbb{R}^*</math><ref name=":1">{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref> or <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}.</math> The added point is called the point at infinity, because it is considered as a neighbour of both ends of the real line. More precisely, the point at infinity is the limit of every sequence of real numbers whose absolute values are increasing and unbounded.

The projectively extended real line may be identified with a real projective line in which three points have been assigned the specific values Template:Math, Template:Math and Template:Math. The projectively extended real number line is distinct from the affinely extended real number line, in which Template:Math and Template:Math are distinct.

Dividing by zeroEdit

Unlike most mathematical models of numbers, this structure allows division by zero:

<math>\frac{a}{0} = \infty</math>

for nonzero a. In particular, Template:Math and Template:Math, making the reciprocal function Template:Math a total function in this structure.<ref name=":0" /> The structure, however, is not a field, and none of the binary arithmetic operations are total – for example, Template:Math is undefined, even though the reciprocal is total.<ref name=":0" /> It has usable interpretations, however – for example, in geometry, the slope of a vertical line is Template:Math.<ref name=":0" />

Extensions of the real lineEdit

The projectively extended real line extends the field of real numbers in the same way that the Riemann sphere extends the field of complex numbers, by adding a single point called conventionally Template:Math.

In contrast, the affinely extended real number line (also called the two-point compactification of the real line) distinguishes between Template:Math and Template:Math.

OrderEdit

The order relation cannot be extended to <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> in a meaningful way. Given a number Template:Math, there is no convincing argument to define either Template:Math or that Template:Math. Since Template:Math can't be compared with any of the other elements, there's no point in retaining this relation on <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>.<ref name=":1" /> However, order on <math>\mathbb{R}</math> is used in definitions in <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>.

GeometryEdit

Fundamental to the idea that Template:Math is a point no different from any other is the way the real projective line is a homogeneous space, in fact homeomorphic to a circle. For example the general linear group of 2 × 2 real invertible matrices has a transitive action on it. The group action may be expressed by Möbius transformations (also called linear fractional transformations), with the understanding that when the denominator of the linear fractional transformation is Template:Math, the image is Template:Math.

The detailed analysis of the action shows that for any three distinct points P, Q and R, there is a linear fractional transformation taking P to 0, Q to 1, and R to Template:Math that is, the group of linear fractional transformations is triply transitive on the real projective line. This cannot be extended to 4-tuples of points, because the cross-ratio is invariant.

The terminology projective line is appropriate, because the points are in 1-to-1 correspondence with one-dimensional linear subspaces of <math>\mathbb{R}^2</math>.

Arithmetic operationsEdit

Motivation for arithmetic operationsEdit

The arithmetic operations on this space are an extension of the same operations on reals. A motivation for the new definitions is the limits of functions of real numbers.

Arithmetic operations that are definedEdit

In addition to the standard operations on the subset <math>\mathbb{R}</math> of <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>, the following operations are defined for <math>a \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>, with exceptions as indicated:<ref>Template:Cite book</ref><ref name=":1" />

<math>\begin{align}

a + \infty = \infty + a & = \infty, & a \neq \infty \\ a - \infty = \infty - a & = \infty, & a \neq \infty \\ a / \infty = a \cdot 0 = 0 \cdot a & = 0, & a \neq \infty \\ \infty / a & = \infty, & a \neq \infty \\ a / 0 = a \cdot \infty = \infty \cdot a & = \infty, & a \neq 0 \\ 0 / a & = 0, & a \neq 0 \end{align}</math>

Arithmetic operations that are left undefinedEdit

The following expressions cannot be motivated by considering limits of real functions, and no definition of them allows the statement of the standard algebraic properties to be retained unchanged in form for all defined cases.Template:Efn</math>, resolve to the standard rules: see Wheel theory.}} Consequently, they are left undefined:

<math>\begin{align}

& \infty + \infty \\ & \infty - \infty \\ & \infty \cdot 0 \\ & 0 \cdot \infty \\ & \infty / \infty \\ & 0 / 0 \end{align}</math> The exponential function <math>e^x</math> cannot be extended to <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>.<ref name=":1" />

Algebraic propertiesEdit

The following equalities mean: Either both sides are undefined, or both sides are defined and equal. This is true for any <math>a, b, c \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}}.</math>

<math>\begin{align}

(a + b) + c & = a + (b + c) \\ a + b & = b + a \\ (a \cdot b) \cdot c & = a \cdot (b \cdot c) \\ a \cdot b & = b \cdot a \\ a \cdot \infty & = \frac{a}{0} \\ \end{align}</math> The following is true whenever expressions involved are defined, for any <math>a, b, c \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}}.</math>

<math>

\begin{align} a \cdot (b + c) & = a \cdot b + a \cdot c \\ a & = \left(\frac{a}{b}\right) \cdot b & = \,\,& \frac{(a \cdot b)}{b} \\ a & = (a + b) - b & = \,\,& (a - b) + b \end{align} </math> In general, all laws of arithmetic that are valid for <math>\mathbb{R}</math> are also valid for <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> whenever all the occurring expressions are defined.

Intervals and topologyEdit

The concept of an interval can be extended to <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>. However, since it is not an ordered set, the interval has a slightly different meaning. The definitions for closed intervals are as follows (it is assumed that <math>a, b \in \mathbb{R}, a < b</math>):<ref name=":1" />Template:Additional citations needed

<math>\begin{align}

\left[a, b\right] & = \lbrace x \mid x \in \mathbb{R}, a \leq x \leq b \rbrace \\ \left[a, \infty\right] & = \lbrace x \mid x \in \mathbb{R}, a \leq x \rbrace \cup \lbrace \infty \rbrace \\ \left[b, a\right] & = \lbrace x \mid x \in \mathbb{R}, b \leq x \rbrace \cup \lbrace \infty \rbrace \cup \lbrace x \mid x \in \mathbb{R}, x \leq a \rbrace \\ \left[\infty, a\right] & = \lbrace \infty \rbrace \cup \lbrace x \mid x \in \mathbb{R}, x \leq a \rbrace \\ \left[a, a\right] & = \{ a \} \\ \left[\infty, \infty\right] & = \lbrace \infty \rbrace \end{align}</math>

With the exception of when the end-points are equal, the corresponding open and half-open intervals are defined by removing the respective endpoints. This redefinition is useful in interval arithmetic when dividing by an interval containing 0.<ref name=":1" />

<math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> and the empty set are also intervals, as is <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> excluding any single point.Template:Efn</math> (where the interval on either side is defined), all intervals excluding <math>\varnothing</math> and <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> may be naturally represented using this notation, with <math>(a,a)</math> being interpreted as <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}\setminus \{ a \}</math>, and half-open intervals with equal endpoints, e.g. <math>(a,a]</math>, remaining undefined.}}

The open intervals as a base define a topology on <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>. Sufficient for a base are the bounded open intervals in <math>\mathbb{R}</math> and the intervals <math>(b, a) = \{x \mid x \in \mathbb{R}, b < x\} \cup \{\infty\} \cup \{x \mid x \in \mathbb{R}, x < a\}</math> for all <math>a, b \in \mathbb{R}</math> such that <math>a < b.</math>

As said, the topology is homeomorphic to a circle. Thus it is metrizable corresponding (for a given homeomorphism) to the ordinary metric on this circle (either measured straight or along the circle). There is no metric which is an extension of the ordinary metric on <math>\mathbb{R}.</math>

Interval arithmeticEdit

Interval arithmetic extends to <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> from <math>\mathbb{R}</math>. The result of an arithmetic operation on intervals is always an interval, except when the intervals with a binary operation contain incompatible values leading to an undefined result.Template:Efn In particular, we have, for every <math>a, b \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>:

<math>x \in [a, b] \iff \frac{1}{x} \in \left[ \frac{1}{b}, \frac{1}{a} \right] \!,</math>

irrespective of whether either interval includes Template:Math and Template:Math.

CalculusEdit

The tools of calculus can be used to analyze functions of <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>. The definitions are motivated by the topology of this space.

NeighbourhoodsEdit

Let <math>x \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> and <math>A \subseteq \widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>.

LimitsEdit

Basic definitions of limitsEdit

Let <math>f : \widehat{\mathbb{R}} \to \widehat{\mathbb{R}},</math> <math>p \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}},</math> and <math>L \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>.

The limit of fTemplate:Hairsp(x) as Template:Math approaches p is L, denoted

<math>\lim_{x \to p}{f(x)} = L</math>

if and only if for every neighbourhood A of L, there is a punctured neighbourhood B of p, such that <math>x \in B</math> implies <math>f(x) \in A</math>.

The one-sided limit of fTemplate:Hairsp(x) as x approaches p from the right (left) is L, denoted

<math>\lim_{x \to p^{+}}{f(x)} = L \qquad \left( \lim_{x \to p^{-}}{f(x)} = L \right),</math>

if and only if for every neighbourhood A of L, there is a right-sided (left-sided) punctured neighbourhood B of p, such that <math>x \in B</math> implies <math>f(x) \in A.</math>

It can be shown that <math>\lim_{x \to p}{f(x)} = L</math> if and only if both <math>\lim_{x \to p^+}{f(x)} = L</math> and <math>\lim_{x \to p^-}{f(x)} = L</math>.

Comparison with limits in <math>\mathbb{R}</math>Edit

The definitions given above can be compared with the usual definitions of limits of real functions. In the following statements, <math>p, L \in \mathbb{R},</math> the first limit is as defined above, and the second limit is in the usual sense:

  • <math>\lim_{x \to p}{f(x)} = L</math> is equivalent to <math>\lim_{x \to p}{f(x)} = L</math>
  • <math>\lim_{x \to \infty^{+}}{f(x)} = L</math> is equivalent to <math>\lim_{x \to -\infty}{f(x)} = L</math>
  • <math>\lim_{x \to \infty^{-}}{f(x)} = L</math> is equivalent to <math>\lim_{x \to +\infty}{f(x)} = L</math>
  • <math>\lim_{x \to p}{f(x)} = \infty</math> is equivalent to <math>\lim_{x \to p}{|f(x)|} = +\infty</math>
  • <math>\lim_{x \to \infty^{+}}{f(x)} = \infty</math> is equivalent to <math>\lim_{x \to -\infty}{|f(x)|} = +\infty</math>
  • <math>\lim_{x \to \infty^{-}}{f(x)} = \infty</math> is equivalent to <math>\lim_{x \to +\infty}{|f(x)|} = +\infty</math>

Extended definition of limitsEdit

Let <math>A \subseteq \widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>. Then p is a limit point of A if and only if every neighbourhood of p includes a point <math>y \in A</math> such that <math>y \neq p.</math>

Let <math>f : \widehat{\mathbb{R}} \to \widehat{\mathbb{R}}, A \subseteq \widehat{\mathbb{R}}, L \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}}, p \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>, p a limit point of A. The limit of fTemplate:Hairsp(x) as x approaches p through A is L, if and only if for every neighbourhood B of L, there is a punctured neighbourhood C of p, such that <math>x \in A \cap C</math> implies <math>f(x) \in B.</math>

This corresponds to the regular topological definition of continuity, applied to the subspace topology on <math>A\cup \lbrace p \rbrace,</math> and the restriction of f to <math>A \cup \lbrace p \rbrace.</math>

ContinuityEdit

The function

<math>f : \widehat{\mathbb{R}} \to \widehat{\mathbb{R}},\quad p \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}}.</math>

is continuous at Template:Math if and only if Template:Math is defined at Template:Math and

<math>\lim_{x \to p}{f(x)} = f(p).</math>

If <math>A \subseteq \widehat\mathbb R,</math> the function

<math>f : A \to \widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math>

is continuous in Template:Math if and only if, for every <math>p \in A</math>, Template:Math is defined at Template:Math and the limit of <math>f(x)</math> as Template:Math tends to Template:Math through Template:Math is <math>f(p).</math>

Every rational function Template:Math, where Template:Math and Template:Math are polynomials, can be prolongated, in a unique way, to a function from <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> to <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> that is continuous in <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}.</math> In particular, this is the case of polynomial functions, which take the value <math>\infty</math> at <math>\infty,</math> if they are not constant.

Also, if the tangent function <math>\tan</math> is extended so that

<math>\tan\left(\frac{\pi}{2} + n\pi\right) = \infty\text{ for }n \in \mathbb{Z},</math>

then <math>\tan</math> is continuous in <math>\mathbb{R},</math> but cannot be prolongated further to a function that is continuous in <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}.</math>

Many elementary functions that are continuous in <math>\mathbb R</math> cannot be prolongated to functions that are continuous in <math>\widehat\mathbb{R}.</math> This is the case, for example, of the exponential function and all trigonometric functions. For example, the sine function is continuous in <math>\mathbb{R},</math> but it cannot be made continuous at <math>\infty.</math> As seen above, the tangent function can be prolongated to a function that is continuous in <math>\mathbb{R},</math> but this function cannot be made continuous at <math>\infty.</math>

Many discontinuous functions that become continuous when the codomain is extended to <math>\widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> remain discontinuous if the codomain is extended to the affinely extended real number system <math>\overline{\mathbb{R}}.</math> This is the case of the function <math>x\mapsto \frac 1x.</math> On the other hand, some functions that are continuous in <math>\mathbb R</math> and discontinuous at <math>\infty \in \widehat{\mathbb{R}}</math> become continuous if the domain is extended to <math>\overline{\mathbb{R}}.</math> This is the case for the arctangent.

As a projective rangeEdit

{{#invoke:Labelled list hatnote|labelledList|Main article|Main articles|Main page|Main pages}} When the real projective line is considered in the context of the real projective plane, then the consequences of Desargues' theorem are implicit. In particular, the construction of the projective harmonic conjugate relation between points is part of the structure of the real projective line. For instance, given any pair of points, the point at infinity is the projective harmonic conjugate of their midpoint.

As projectivities preserve the harmonic relation, they form the automorphisms of the real projective line. The projectivities are described algebraically as homographies, since the real numbers form a ring, according to the general construction of a projective line over a ring. Collectively they form the group PGL(2, R).

The projectivities which are their own inverses are called involutions. A hyperbolic involution has two fixed points. Two of these correspond to elementary, arithmetic operations on the real projective line: negation and reciprocation. Indeed, 0 and ∞ are fixed under negation, while 1 and −1 are fixed under reciprocation.

See alsoEdit

NotesEdit

Template:Notelist

ReferencesEdit

Template:Reflist