Template:Short description Template:For
In the mathematical discipline of group theory, Cayley's theorem, named in honour of Arthur Cayley, states that every group Template:Mvar is isomorphic to a subgroup of a symmetric group.<ref>Template:Harvtxt</ref> More specifically, Template:Mvar is isomorphic to a subgroup of the symmetric group <math>\operatorname{Sym}(G)</math> whose elements are the permutations of the underlying set of Template:Mvar. Explicitly,
- for each <math>g \in G</math>, the left-multiplication-by-Template:Mvar map <math>\ell_g \colon G \to G</math> sending each element Template:Mvar to Template:Math is a permutation of Template:Mvar, and
- the map <math>G \to \operatorname{Sym}(G)</math> sending each element Template:Mvar to <math>\ell_g</math> is an injective homomorphism, so it defines an isomorphism from Template:Mvar onto a subgroup of <math>\operatorname{Sym}(G)</math>.
The homomorphism <math>G \to \operatorname{Sym}(G)</math> can also be understood as arising from the left translation action of Template:Mvar on the underlying set Template:Mvar.<ref>Template:Harvtxt</ref>
When Template:Mvar is finite, <math>\operatorname{Sym}(G)</math> is finite too. The proof of Cayley's theorem in this case shows that if Template:Mvar is a finite group of order Template:Mvar, then Template:Mvar is isomorphic to a subgroup of the standard symmetric group <math>S_n</math>. But Template:Mvar might also be isomorphic to a subgroup of a smaller symmetric group, <math>S_m</math> for some <math>m<n</math>; for instance, the order 6 group <math>G=S_3</math> is not only isomorphic to a subgroup of <math>S_6</math>, but also (trivially) isomorphic to a subgroup of <math>S_3</math>.<ref name="Cameron2008">Template:Cite book</ref> The problem of finding the minimal-order symmetric group into which a given group Template:Mvar embeds is rather difficult.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
Alperin and Bell note that "in general the fact that finite groups are imbedded in symmetric groups has not influenced the methods used to study finite groups".<ref name="AlperinBell1995">Template:Cite book</ref>
When Template:Mvar is infinite, <math>\operatorname{Sym}(G)</math> is infinite, but Cayley's theorem still applies.
HistoryEdit
When Cayley (1854) introduced what are now called groups, the modern definitions did not exist, and it was not immediately clear that this was equivalent to what were then called groups, which are now called permutation groups. Cayley's theorem unifies the two.
Although Burnside<ref>Template:Citation</ref> attributes the theorem to Jordan,<ref>Template:Citation</ref> Eric Nummela<ref>Template:Citation</ref> nonetheless argues that the standard name—"Cayley's Theorem"—is in fact appropriate. Cayley's original 1854 paper,<ref>Template:Citation</ref> showed that the correspondence in the theorem is one-to-one, but he did not explicitly show it was a homomorphism (and thus an embedding). However, Nummela notes that Cayley made this result known to the mathematical community at the time, thus predating Jordan by 16 years or so.
The theorem was later published by Walther Dyck in 1882<ref>Template:Citation. Template:In lang</ref> and is attributed to Dyck in the first edition of Burnside's book.<ref>Template:Citation</ref>
BackgroundEdit
A permutation of a set Template:Mvar is a bijective function from Template:Mvar to Template:Mvar. The set of all permutations of Template:Mvar forms a group under function composition, called the symmetric group on Template:Mvar, and written as <math>\operatorname{Sym}(A)</math>.<ref>Template:Harvtxt</ref> In particular, taking Template:Mvar to be the underlying set of a group Template:Mvar produces a symmetric group denoted <math>\operatorname{Sym}(G)</math>.
Proof of the theoremEdit
If g is any element of a group G with operation ∗, consider the function Template:Nowrap, defined by Template:Nowrap. By the existence of inverses, this function has also an inverse, <math>f_{g^{-1}}</math>. So multiplication by g acts as a bijective function. Thus, fg is a permutation of G, and so is a member of Sym(G).
The set Template:Nowrap is a subgroup of Sym(G) that is isomorphic to G. The fastest way to establish this is to consider the function Template:Nowrap with Template:Nowrap for every g in G. T is a group homomorphism because (using · to denote composition in Sym(G)):
- <math> (f_g \cdot f_h)(x) = f_g(f_h(x)) = f_g(h*x) = g*(h*x) = (g*h)*x = f_{g*h}(x) ,</math>
for all x in G, and hence:
- <math> T(g) \cdot T(h) = f_g \cdot f_h = f_{g*h} = T(g*h) .</math>
The homomorphism T is injective since Template:Nowrap (the identity element of Sym(G)) implies that Template:Nowrap for all x in G, and taking x to be the identity element e of G yields Template:Nowrap, i.e. the kernel is trivial. Alternatively, T is also injective since Template:Nowrap implies that Template:Nowrap (because every group is cancellative).
Thus G is isomorphic to the image of T, which is the subgroup K.
T is sometimes called the regular representation of G.
Alternative setting of proofEdit
An alternative setting uses the language of group actions. We consider the group <math>G</math> as acting on itself by left multiplication, i.e. <math>g \cdot x = gx</math>, which has a permutation representation, say <math>\phi : G \to \mathrm{Sym}(G)</math>.
The representation is faithful if <math>\phi</math> is injective, that is, if the kernel of <math>\phi</math> is trivial. Suppose <math>g\in\ker\phi</math>. Then, <math>g = ge = g\cdot e = e</math>. Thus, <math>\ker\phi</math> is trivial. The result follows by use of the first isomorphism theorem, from which we get <math>\mathrm{Im}\, \phi \cong G</math>.
Remarks on the regular group representationEdit
The identity element of the group corresponds to the identity permutation. All other group elements correspond to derangements: permutations that do not leave any element unchanged. Since this also applies for powers of a group element, lower than the order of that element, each element corresponds to a permutation that consists of cycles all of the same length: this length is the order of that element. The elements in each cycle form a right coset of the subgroup generated by the element.
Examples of the regular group representationEdit
<math> \mathbb Z_2 = \{0,1\} </math> with addition modulo 2; group element 0 corresponds to the identity permutation e, group element 1 to permutation (12) (see cycle notation). E.g. 0 +1 = 1 and 1+1 = 0, so <math display=inline>1\mapsto0</math> and <math display=inline>0\mapsto1,</math> as they would under a permutation.
<math> \mathbb Z_3 = \{0,1,2\} </math> with addition modulo 3; group element 0 corresponds to the identity permutation e, group element 1 to permutation (123), and group element 2 to permutation (132). E.g. 1 + 1 = 2 corresponds to (123)(123) = (132).
<math> \mathbb Z_4 = \{0,1,2,3\} </math> with addition modulo 4; the elements correspond to e, (1234), (13)(24), (1432).
The elements of Klein four-group {e, a, b, c} correspond to e, (12)(34), (13)(24), and (14)(23).
S3 (dihedral group of order 6) is the group of all permutations of 3 objects, but also a permutation group of the 6 group elements, and the latter is how it is realized by its regular representation.
* | e | a | b | c | d | f | permutation |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
e | e | a | b | c | d | f | e |
a | a | e | d | f | b | c | (12)(35)(46) |
b | b | f | e | d | c | a | (13)(26)(45) |
c | c | d | f | e | a | b | (14)(25)(36) |
d | d | c | a | b | f | e | (156)(243) |
f | f | b | c | a | e | d | (165)(234) |
More general statementEdit
Theorem: Let Template:Mvar be a group, and let Template:Mvar be a subgroup. Let <math>G/H</math> be the set of left cosets of Template:Mvar in Template:Mvar. Let Template:Mvar be the normal core of Template:Mvar in Template:Mvar, defined to be the intersection of the conjugates of Template:Mvar in Template:Mvar. Then the quotient group <math>G/N</math> is isomorphic to a subgroup of <math>\operatorname{Sym}(G/H)</math>.
The special case <math>H=1</math> is Cayley's original theorem.
See alsoEdit
- Wagner–Preston theorem is the analogue for inverse semigroups.
- Birkhoff's representation theorem, a similar result in order theory
- Frucht's theorem, every finite group is the automorphism group of a graph
- Yoneda lemma, a generalization of Cayley's theorem in category theory
- Representation theorem