Cardinality of the continuum
Template:Short description In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers <math>\mathbb R</math>, sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by <math>\bold\mathfrak c</math> (lowercase Fraktur "c") or <math>\bold|\bold\mathbb R\bold|.</math><ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref>
The real numbers <math>\mathbb R</math> are more numerous than the natural numbers <math>\mathbb N</math>. Moreover, <math>\mathbb R</math> has the same number of elements as the power set of <math>\mathbb N</math>. Symbolically, if the cardinality of <math>\mathbb N</math> is denoted as <math>\aleph_0</math>, the cardinality of the continuum is Template:Block indent This was proven by Georg Cantor in his uncountability proof of 1874, part of his groundbreaking study of different infinities. The inequality was later stated more simply in his diagonal argument in 1891. Cantor defined cardinality in terms of bijective functions: two sets have the same cardinality if, and only if, there exists a bijective function between them.
Between any two real numbers a < b, no matter how close they are to each other, there are always infinitely many other real numbers, and Cantor showed that they are as many as those contained in the whole set of real numbers. In other words, the open interval (a,b) is equinumerous with <math>\mathbb R</math>, as well as with several other infinite sets, such as any n-dimensional Euclidean space <math>\mathbb R^n</math> (see space filling curve). That is, Template:Block indent
The smallest infinite cardinal number is <math>\aleph_0</math> (aleph-null). The second smallest is <math>\aleph_1</math> (aleph-one). The continuum hypothesis, which asserts that there are no sets whose cardinality is strictly between <math>\aleph_0</math> and Template:Nowrap, means that <math>\mathfrak c = \aleph_1</math>.<ref name=":0">{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref> The truth or falsity of this hypothesis is undecidable and cannot be proven within the widely used Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with axiom of choice (ZFC).
PropertiesEdit
UncountabilityEdit
Georg Cantor introduced the concept of cardinality to compare the sizes of infinite sets. He famously showed that the set of real numbers is uncountably infinite. That is, <math>{\mathfrak c}</math> is strictly greater than the cardinality of the natural numbers, <math>\aleph_0</math>: Template:Block indent In practice, this means that there are strictly more real numbers than there are integers. Cantor proved this statement in several different ways. For more information on this topic, see Cantor's first uncountability proof and Cantor's diagonal argument.
Cardinal equalitiesEdit
A variation of Cantor's diagonal argument can be used to prove Cantor's theorem, which states that the cardinality of any set is strictly less than that of its power set. That is, <math>|A| < 2^{|A|}</math> (and so that the power set <math>\wp(\mathbb N)</math> of the natural numbers <math>\mathbb N</math> is uncountable).<ref>Template:SpringerEOM</ref> In fact, the cardinality of <math>\wp(\mathbb N)</math>, by definition <math>2^{\aleph_0}</math>, is equal to <math>{\mathfrak c}</math>. This can be shown by providing one-to-one mappings in both directions between subsets of a countably infinite set and real numbers, and applying the Cantor–Bernstein–Schroeder theorem according to which two sets with one-to-one mappings in both directions have the same cardinality.<ref name=stillwell>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref name=johnson>Template:Cite book</ref> In one direction, reals can be equated with Dedekind cuts, sets of rational numbers,<ref name=stillwell/> or with their binary expansions.<ref name=johnson/> In the other direction, the binary expansions of numbers in the half-open interval <math>[0,1)</math>, viewed as sets of positions where the expansion is one, almost give a one-to-one mapping from subsets of a countable set (the set of positions in the expansions) to real numbers, but it fails to be one-to-one for numbers with terminating binary expansions, which can also be represented by a non-terminating expansion that ends in a repeating sequence of 1s. This can be made into a one-to-one mapping by that adds one to the non-terminating repeating-1 expansions, mapping them into <math>[1,2)</math>.<ref name=johnson/> Thus, we conclude that<ref name=stillwell/><ref name=johnson/> Template:Block indent
The cardinal equality <math>\mathfrak{c}^2 = \mathfrak{c}</math> can be demonstrated using cardinal arithmetic: Template:Block indent = 2^{\aleph_0} = \mathfrak{c}.</math>}}
By using the rules of cardinal arithmetic, one can also show that
where n is any finite cardinal ≥ 2 and
where <math>2 ^{\mathfrak c}</math> is the cardinality of the power set of R, and <math>2 ^{\mathfrak c} > \mathfrak c </math>.
Alternative explanation for Template:Not a typoEdit
Every real number has at least one infinite decimal expansion. For example, Template:Block indent Template:Block indent Template:Block indent (This is true even in the case the expansion repeats, as in the first two examples.)
In any given case, the number of decimal places is countable since they can be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the set of natural numbers <math>\mathbb{N}</math>. This makes it sensible to talk about, say, the first, the one-hundredth, or the millionth decimal place of π. Since the natural numbers have cardinality <math>\aleph_0,</math> each real number has <math>\aleph_0</math> digits in its expansion.
Since each real number can be broken into an integer part and a decimal fraction, we get: Template:Block indent
where we used the fact that
On the other hand, if we map <math>2 = \{0, 1\}</math> to <math>\{3, 7\}</math> and consider that decimal fractions containing only 3 or 7 are only a part of the real numbers, then we get
and thus Template:Block indent
Beth numbersEdit
{{#invoke:Labelled list hatnote|labelledList|Main article|Main articles|Main page|Main pages}} The sequence of beth numbers is defined by setting <math>\beth_0 = \aleph_0</math> and <math>\beth_{k+1} = 2^{\beth_k}</math>. So <math>{\mathfrak c}</math> is the second beth number, beth-one: Template:Block indent The third beth number, beth-two, is the cardinality of the power set of <math>\mathbb{R}</math> (i.e. the set of all subsets of the real line): Template:Block indent
The continuum hypothesisEdit
{{#invoke:Labelled list hatnote|labelledList|Main article|Main articles|Main page|Main pages}}
The continuum hypothesis asserts that <math>{\mathfrak c}</math> is also the second aleph number, <math>\aleph_1</math>.<ref name=":0" /> In other words, the continuum hypothesis states that there is no set <math>A</math> whose cardinality lies strictly between <math>\aleph_0</math> and <math>{\mathfrak c}</math> Template:Block indent This statement is now known to be independent of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), as shown by Kurt Gödel and Paul Cohen.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref> That is, both the hypothesis and its negation are consistent with these axioms. In fact, for every nonzero natural number n, the equality <math>{\mathfrak c}</math> = <math>\aleph_n</math> is independent of ZFC (case <math>n=1</math> being the continuum hypothesis). The same is true for most other alephs, although in some cases, equality can be ruled out by König's theorem on the grounds of cofinality (e.g. <math>\mathfrak{c}\neq\aleph_\omega</math>). In particular, <math>\mathfrak{c}</math> could be either <math>\aleph_1</math> or <math>\aleph_{\omega_1}</math>, where <math>\omega_1</math> is the first uncountable ordinal, so it could be either a successor cardinal or a limit cardinal, and either a regular cardinal or a singular cardinal.
Sets with cardinality of the continuumEdit
A great many sets studied in mathematics have cardinality equal to <math>{\mathfrak c}</math>. Some common examples are the following:
Sets with greater cardinalityEdit
Sets with cardinality greater than <math>{\mathfrak c}</math> include:
- the set of all subsets of <math>\mathbb{R}</math> (i.e., power set <math>\mathcal{P}(\mathbb{R})</math>)
- the set 2R of indicator functions defined on subsets of the reals (the set <math>2^{\mathbb{R}}</math> is isomorphic to <math>\mathcal{P}(\mathbb{R})</math> – the indicator function chooses elements of each subset to include)
- the set <math>\mathbb{R}^\mathbb{R}</math> of all functions from <math>\mathbb{R}</math> to <math>\mathbb{R}</math>
- the Lebesgue σ-algebra of <math>\mathbb{R}</math>, i.e., the set of all Lebesgue measurable sets in <math>\mathbb{R}</math>.
- the set of all Lebesgue-integrable functions from <math>\mathbb{R}</math> to <math>\mathbb{R}</math>
- the set of all Lebesgue-measurable functions from <math>\mathbb{R}</math> to <math>\mathbb{R}</math>
- the Stone–Čech compactifications of <math>\mathbb{N}</math>, <math>\mathbb{Q}</math>, and <math>\mathbb{R}</math>
- the set of all automorphisms of the (discrete) field of complex numbers.
These all have cardinality <math>2^\mathfrak c = \beth_2</math> (beth two)
See alsoEdit
ReferencesEdit
<references/>
BibliographyEdit
- Paul Halmos, Naive set theory. Princeton, NJ: D. Van Nostrand Company, 1960. Reprinted by Springer-Verlag, New York, 1974. Template:ISBN (Springer-Verlag edition).
- Jech, Thomas, 2003. Set Theory: The Third Millennium Edition, Revised and Expanded. Springer. Template:ISBN.
- Kunen, Kenneth, 1980. Set Theory: An Introduction to Independence Proofs. Elsevier. Template:ISBN.
{{#if: | This article incorporates material from the following PlanetMath articles, which are licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License: {{#if: CardinalityOfTheContinuum | cardinality of the continuum | {{#if: | cardinality of the continuum | [{{{sourceurl}}} cardinality of the continuum] }} }}, {{#if: | {{{title2}}} | {{#if: | {{{title2}}} | [{{{sourceurl2}}} {{{title2}}}] }} }}{{#if: | , {{#if: | {{{title3}}} | {{#if: | {{{title3}}} | [{{{sourceurl3}}} {{{title3}}}] }} }} }}{{#if: | , {{#if: | {{{title4}}} | {{#if: | {{{title4}}} | [{{{sourceurl4}}} {{{title4}}}] }} }} }}{{#if: | , {{#if: | {{{title5}}} | {{#if: | {{{title5}}} | [{{{sourceurl5}}} {{{title5}}}] }} }} }}{{#if: | , {{#if: | {{{title6}}} | {{#if: | {{{title6}}} | [{{{sourceurl6}}} {{{title6}}}] }} }} }}{{#if: | , {{#if: | {{{title7}}} | {{#if: | {{{title7}}} | [{{{sourceurl7}}} {{{title7}}}] }} }} }}{{#if: | , {{#if: | {{{title8}}} | {{#if: | {{{title8}}} | [{{{sourceurl8}}} {{{title8}}}] }} }} }}{{#if: | , {{#if: | {{{title9}}} | {{#if: | {{{title9}}} | [{{{sourceurl9}}} {{{title9}}}] }} }} }}. | This article incorporates material from {{#if: CardinalityOfTheContinuum | cardinality of the continuum | cardinality of the continuum}} on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License. }}