Template:Short description In boolean logic, a disjunctive normal form (DNF) is a canonical normal form of a logical formula consisting of a disjunction of conjunctions; it can also be described as an OR of ANDs, a sum of products, or Template:Mdash in philosophical logic Template:Mdash a cluster concept.Template:Sfn As a normal form, it is useful in automated theorem proving.

DefinitionEdit

A logical formula is considered to be in DNF if it is a disjunction of one or more conjunctions of one or more literals.Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn A DNF formula is in full disjunctive normal form if each of its variables appears exactly once in every conjunction and each conjunction appears at most once (up to the order of variables). As in conjunctive normal form (CNF), the only propositional operators in DNF are and (<math>\wedge</math>), or (<math>\vee</math>), and not (<math>\neg</math>). The not operator can only be used as part of a literal, which means that it can only precede a propositional variable.

The following is a context-free grammar for DNF:

DNF <math>\, \to \,</math> Conjunct <math>\, \mid \, </math> Conjunct <math>\, \lor \,</math> DNF
Conjunct <math>\, \to \,</math> Literal <math>\, \mid\, </math> Literal <math>\, \land \,</math> Conjunct
Literal <math>\, \to \,</math> Variable <math>\, \mid \,</math> <math>\, \neg \,</math> Variable

Where Variable is any variable.

For example, all of the following formulas are in DNF:

  • <math>(A \land \neg B \land \neg C) \lor (\neg D \land E \land F \land D \land F)</math>
  • <math>(A \land B) \lor (C)</math>
  • <math>(A \land B)</math>
  • <math>(A)</math>

The formula <math>A \lor B</math> is in DNF, but not in full DNF; an equivalent full-DNF version is <math>(A \land B) \lor (A \land \lnot B) \lor (\lnot A \land B)</math>.

The following formulas are not in DNF:

  • <math>\neg(A \lor B)</math>, since an OR is nested within a NOT
  • <math>\neg(A \land B) \lor C</math>, since an AND is nested within a NOT
  • <math>A \lor (B \land (C \lor D))</math>, since an OR is nested within an AND<ref>However, this one is in negation normal form.</ref>

Conversion to DNFEdit

In classical logic each propositional formula can be converted to DNFTemplate:Sfn ...

File:Karnaugh map KV 4mal4 18.svg
Karnaugh map of the disjunctive normal form Template:Ifsubst style="color:#800000">(¬A∧¬B∧¬D) ∨ Template:Ifsubst style="color:#000080">(¬ABC) ∨ Template:Ifsubst style="color:#008000">(ABD) ∨ Template:Ifsubst style="color:#800080">(A∧¬B∧¬C)
File:Karnaugh map KV 4mal4 19.svg
Karnaugh map of the disjunctive normal form Template:Ifsubst style="color:#800080">(¬AC∧¬D) ∨ Template:Ifsubst style="color:#008000">(BCD) ∨ Template:Ifsubst style="color:#000080">(A∧¬CD) ∨ Template:Ifsubst style="color:#800000">(¬B∧¬C∧¬D). Despite the different grouping, the same fields contain a "1" as in the previous map.

... by syntactic meansEdit

The conversion involves using logical equivalences, such as double negation elimination, De Morgan's laws, and the distributive law. Formulas built from the primitive connectives <math>\{\land,\lor,\lnot\}</math><ref>Formulas with other connectives can be brought into negation normal form first.</ref> can be converted to DNF by the following canonical term rewriting system:Template:Sfn

<math>\begin{array}{rcl}

(\lnot \lnot x) & \rightsquigarrow & x \\ (\lnot (x \lor y)) & \rightsquigarrow & ((\lnot x) \land (\lnot y)) \\ (\lnot (x \land y)) & \rightsquigarrow & ((\lnot x) \lor (\lnot y)) \\ (x \land (y \lor z)) & \rightsquigarrow & ((x \land y) \lor (x \land z)) \\ ((x \lor y) \land z) & \rightsquigarrow & ((x \land z) \lor (y \land z)) \\ \end{array}</math>

... by semantic meansEdit

The full DNF of a formula can be read off its truth table.<ref>Template:Harvnb: "Make a truth-table for the formula. Each line of the table which comes out "T" will yield one of the basic conjunctions of the disjunctive normal form."</ref>Template:Sfn For example, consider the formula

<math>\phi = ((\lnot (p \land q)) \leftrightarrow (\lnot r \uparrow (p \oplus q)))</math>.<ref><math>\phi</math> = ((NOT (p AND q)) IFF ((NOT r) NAND (p XOR q)))</ref>

The corresponding truth table is

<math>p</math> <math>q</math> <math>r</math> <math>(</math> <math>\lnot</math> <math>(p \land q)</math> <math>)</math> <math>\leftrightarrow</math> <math>(</math> <math>\lnot r</math> <math>\uparrow</math> <math>(p \oplus q)</math> <math>)</math>
T T T F T F F T F
T T F F T F T T F
T F T T F T F T T
T F F T F F T F T
F T T T F T F T T
F T F T F F T F T
F F T T F T F T F
F F F T F T T T F
  • The full DNF equivalent of <math>\phi</math> is
<math>

( p \land \lnot q \land r) \lor (\lnot p \land q \land r) \lor (\lnot p \land \lnot q \land r) \lor (\lnot p \land \lnot q \land \lnot r) </math>

  • The full DNF equivalent of <math>\lnot \phi</math> is
<math>

( p \land q \land r) \lor ( p \land q \land \lnot r) \lor ( p \land \lnot q \land \lnot r) \lor (\lnot p \land q \land \lnot r) </math>

RemarkEdit

A propositional formula can be represented by one and only one full DNF.Template:Refn In contrast, several plain DNFs may be possible. For example, by applying the rule <math>((a \land b) \lor (\lnot a \land b)) \rightsquigarrow b</math> three times, the full DNF of the above <math>\phi</math> can be simplified to <math>(\lnot p \land \lnot q) \lor (\lnot p \land r) \lor (\lnot q \land r)</math>. However, there are also equivalent DNF formulas that cannot be transformed one into another by this rule, see the pictures for an example.

Disjunctive Normal Form TheoremEdit

It is a theorem that all consistent formulas in propositional logic can be converted to disjunctive normal form.<ref name=":0">Template:Cite book</ref><ref name=":13" /><ref name=":1">Template:Cite book</ref><ref name=":2">Template:Cite book</ref> This is called the Disjunctive Normal Form Theorem.<ref name=":0" /><ref name=":13" /><ref name=":1" /><ref name=":2" /> The formal statement is as follows:

Disjunctive Normal Form Theorem: Suppose <math>X</math> is a sentence in a propositional language <math>\mathcal{L}</math> with <math>n</math> sentence letters, which we shall denote by <math>A_1,...,A_n</math>. If <math>X</math> is not a contradiction, then it is truth-functionally equivalent to a disjunction of conjunctions of the form <math>\pm A_1 \land ... \land \pm A_n</math>, where <math>+A_i=A_i</math>, and <math>-A_i= \neg A_i</math>.<ref name=":13">Template:Cite book</ref>

The proof follows from the procedure given above for generating DNFs from truth tables. Formally, the proof is as follows:

Suppose <math>X</math> is a sentence in a propositional language whose sentence letters are <math>A, B, C, \ldots</math>. For each row of <math>X</math>'s truth table, write out a corresponding conjunction <math>\pm A \land \pm B \land \pm C \land \ldots</math>, where <math>\pm A</math> is defined to be <math>A</math> if <math>A</math> takes the value <math>T</math> at that row, and is <math>\neg A</math> if <math>A</math> takes the value <math>F</math> at that row; similarly for <math>\pm B</math>, <math>\pm C</math>, etc. (the alphabetical ordering of <math>A, B, C, \ldots</math> in the conjunctions is quite arbitrary; any other could be chosen instead). Now form the disjunction of all these conjunctions which correspond to <math>T</math> rows of <math>X</math>'s truth table. This disjunction is a sentence in <math>\mathcal{L}[A, B, C, \ldots; \land, \lor, \neg]</math>,<ref>That is, the language with the propositional variables <math>A, B, C, \ldots</math> and the connectives <math>\{\land, \lor, \neg\}</math>.</ref> which by the reasoning above is truth-functionally equivalent to <math>X</math>. This construction obviously presupposes that <math>X</math> takes the value <math>T</math> on at least one row of its truth table; if <math>X</math> doesn’t, i.e., if <math>X</math> is a contradiction, then <math>X</math> is equivalent to <math>A \land \neg A</math>, which is, of course, also a sentence in <math>\mathcal{L}[A, B, C, \ldots; \land, \lor, \neg]</math>.<ref name=":13" />

This theorem is a convenient way to derive many useful metalogical results in propositional logic, such as, trivially, the result that the set of connectives <math>\{\land, \lor, \neg\}</math> is functionally complete.<ref name=":13" />

Maximum number of conjunctionsEdit

Any propositional formula is built from <math>n</math> variables, where <math>n \ge 1</math>.

There are <math>2n</math> possible literals: <math>L = \{ p_1, \lnot p_1, p_2, \lnot p_2, \ldots, p_n, \lnot p_n\}</math>.

<math>L</math> has <math>(2^{2n} -1)</math> non-empty subsets.<ref><math>\left|\mathcal{P}(L)\right| = 2^{2n}</math></ref>

This is the maximum number of conjunctions a DNF can have.<ref name="noreps" />

A full DNF can have up to <math>2^{n}</math> conjunctions, one for each row of the truth table.

Example 1

Consider a formula with two variables <math>p</math> and <math>q</math>.

The longest possible DNF has <math>2^{(2 \times 2)} -1 = 15</math> conjunctions:<ref name= "noreps" />

<math>

\begin{array}{lcl} (\lnot p) \lor (p) \lor (\lnot q) \lor (q) \lor \\ (\lnot p \land p) \lor \underline{(\lnot p \land \lnot q)} \lor \underline{(\lnot p \land q)} \lor \underline{( p \land \lnot q)} \lor \underline{( p \land q)} \lor (\lnot q \land q) \lor \\ (\lnot p \land p \land \lnot q) \lor (\lnot p \land p \land q) \lor (\lnot p \land \lnot q \land q) \lor ( p \land \lnot q \land q) \lor \\ (\lnot p \land p \land \lnot q \land q) \end{array}</math>

The longest possible full DNF has 4 conjunctions: they are underlined.

This formula is a tautology. It can be simplified to <math>(\neg p \lor p)</math> or to <math>(\neg q \lor q)</math>, which are also tautologies, as well as valid DNFs.

Example 2

Each DNF of the e.g. formula <math>(X_1 \lor Y_1) \land (X_2 \lor Y_2) \land \dots \land (X_n \lor Y_n)</math> has <math>2^n</math> conjunctions.

Computational complexityEdit

The Boolean satisfiability problem on conjunctive normal form formulas is NP-complete. By the duality principle, so is the falsifiability problem on DNF formulas. Therefore, it is co-NP-hard to decide if a DNF formula is a tautology.

Conversely, a DNF formula is satisfiable if, and only if, one of its conjunctions is satisfiable. This can be decided in polynomial time simply by checking that at least one conjunction does not contain conflicting literals.

VariantsEdit

An important variation used in the study of computational complexity is k-DNF. A formula is in k-DNF if it is in DNF and each conjunction contains at most k literals.Template:Sfn

See alsoEdit

NotesEdit

Template:Reflist

ReferencesEdit

Template:Sfn whitelist

Template:Normal forms in logic