Eleatics
The Eleatics were a group of pre-Socratic philosophers and school of thought in the 5th century BC centered around the ancient Greek colony of Elea (Template:Langx), located around 80 miles south-east of Naples in southern Italy, then known as Magna Graecia.
The primary philosophers who are associated with the Eleatic doctrines are Parmenides, Zeno of Elea, and Melissus of Samos, although other Italian philosophers such as Xenophanes of Colophon and Empedocles have also sometimes been classified as members of this movement. The Eleatics have traditionally been seen as advocating a strict metaphysical view of monism in response to the materialist monism advocated by their predecessors, the Ionian school.
HistoryEdit
Patricia Curd states that the chronology of pre-Socratic philosophers is one of the most contentious issues of pre-Socratic philosophy.Template:Sfn Many of the historical details mentioned by Plato, Diogenes Laertius, or Apollodorus are generally considered by modern scholarship to be of little value,Template:Sfn and there are generally few exact dates that can be verified, so most estimates of dates and relative chronology must rely on interpretations of the internal evidence within the surviving fragments.Template:Sfn
There is generally a consensus that Parmenides lived in the early 5th century BC,Template:Sfn based on the date and setting of the fictionalized events in Plato's Parmenides where Parmenides and Zeno travel to Athens and have a debate with a young Socrates.Template:Sfn This would place Parmenides well after other philosophers such as Xenophanes, Heraclitus, and Pythagoras.Template:Sfn Although many philosophers throughout history have interpreted the doctrines of the Eleatics as responses to Xenophanes, Heraclitus, or Pythagoras, there is no broad agreement or direct evidence of any influence or direct response, although many theories have been put forth interpreting the Eleatics in terms of these philosophers.Template:Sfn For philosophers after Parmenides however, the relative chronology and potential directions of influence become even more difficult to determine.Template:Sfn
For Zeno, it is not clear whether or not Anaxagoras or Empedocles influenced or were influenced by any of his ideas, although they appear to have lived at approximately the same time.Template:Sfn For Melissus, who lived one generation later, the problem of influence is further complicated by additional potential influences of Leucippus, Democritus, and Diogenes of Apollonia.Template:Sfn For example, some interpreters see Melissus as responding to Leucippus' atomism, which is then responded to by Democritus - but others see Melissus responding to Democritus.Template:Sfn
PhilosophyEdit
The OneEdit
The Eleatics believed in the oneness of the universe, and that "All is One". To justify this view, Parmenides argued that everything either "is" or "is not". Since "is not" doesn't truly exist, this means only "what is" can actually exist, and must everything falls under this one category. In his poem On Nature, Parmenides wrote:
<templatestyles src="Template:Blockquote/styles.css" />
Come now, I will tell thee—and do thou hearken to my saying and carry it away—the only two ways of search that can be thought of. The first, namely, that It is, and that it is impossible for it not to be, is the way of belief, for truth is its companion. The other, namely, that It is not, and that it must needs not be,—that, I tell thee, is a path that none can learn of at all. For thou canst not know what is not —that is impossible—nor utter it; for it is the same thing that can be thought and that can be.{{#if:|{{#if:|}}
— {{#if:|, in }}Template:Comma separated entries}}
{{#invoke:Check for unknown parameters|check|unknown=Template:Main other|preview=Page using Template:Blockquote with unknown parameter "_VALUE_"|ignoreblank=y| 1 | 2 | 3 | 4 | 5 | author | by | char | character | cite | class | content | multiline | personquoted | publication | quote | quotesource | quotetext | sign | source | style | text | title | ts }}
This concept was further expanded upon by Melissus of Samos, who was one of the first philosophers to champion the principle that nothing can come from nothing<ref>"οὐδαμὰ ἂν γένοιτο οὐδὲν ἐκ μηδενός (... in no wise could anything have arisen out of nothing)".</ref>, and that a first cause was necessary for the universe to exist. He believed that this first cause (called "The One") had to be both eternal and infinite, and that because it is infinite it also cannot be divided into parts, as that would require those parts having to establish finite boundaries in relation to each other. Since The One is already whole it can't change in any way, shape or form.<ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref>
MotionEdit
Because the Eleatics thought that The One doesn't undergo any changes, they rejected the possibility of motion existing. They believed that any perceived motion was due to illusions of the senses, which are incapable of understanding the universal unity.Template:Sfn They thus rejected empirical evidence in favour of strict adherence to reason.
CreationEdit
The Eleatics argued that there can be no creation, for being cannot come from non-being, because a thing cannot arise from that which is different from it. They argued that errors on this point commonly arise from the ambiguous use of the verb to be, which may imply actual physical existence or be merely the linguistic copula which connects subject and predicate.Template:Sfn
Zeno's paradoxesEdit
Zeno of Elea employed various reductio ad absurdum paradoxes in order to disprove the concept of motion, attempting to destroy the arguments of others by showing that their premises led to contradictions (see: Zeno's paradoxes).
LegacyEdit
One of the characters in Plato's Sophist is "an Eleatic stranger";<ref>Plato, Sophist: Persons of the Dialogue, the Project Gutenberg EBook of Sophist, translated by Benjamin Jowett, accessed on 4 January 2025</ref> Plato also acknowledged the Eleatics in the Parmenides and the Statesman. Some authors suggest that Meno's paradox, in Plato's dialogue Meno, can be linked to the Eleatic distinction between "knowing" and "not-knowing".<ref>Calvert, B., Meno's Paradox Reconsidered, Journal of the History of Philosophy, Volume 12, Number 2, April 1974, accessed on 4 January 2025</ref>
ReferencesEdit
SourcesEdit
|{{#ifeq: Eleatic School | |{{#ifeq: | |public domain: }}{{#invoke:template wrapper|{{#if:|list|wrap}}|_template=cite EB1911 |_exclude=footnote, inline, noicon, no-icon, noprescript, no-prescript, _debug| }} | }} }}{{#ifeq: | |{{#ifeq: | |This article |One or more of the preceding sentences }} incorporates text from a publication now in the
| noicon=1 }}{{#ifeq: ||}}
Further readingEdit
- Template:Cite EB9
- Template:Cite SEP
- Template:Cite SEP
- Template:Cite SEP
- Template:Cite SEP
- Template:Cite SEP
External linksEdit
Template:Greek schools of philosophy Template:Authority control