Markov's inequality
In probability theory, Markov's inequality gives an upper bound on the probability that a non-negative random variable is greater than or equal to some positive constant. Markov's inequality is tight in the sense that for each chosen positive constant, there exists a random variable such that the inequality is in fact an equality.<ref name=":0">Template:Cite journal</ref>
It is named after the Russian mathematician Andrey Markov, although it appeared earlier in the work of Pafnuty Chebyshev (Markov's teacher), and many sources, especially in analysis, refer to it as Chebyshev's inequality (sometimes, calling it the first Chebyshev inequality, while referring to Chebyshev's inequality as the second Chebyshev inequality) or Bienaymé's inequality.
Markov's inequality (and other similar inequalities) relate probabilities to expectations, and provide (frequently loose but still useful) bounds for the cumulative distribution function of a random variable. Markov's inequality can also be used to upper bound the expectation of a non-negative random variable in terms of its distribution function.
StatementEdit
If Template:Mvar is a nonnegative random variable and Template:Math, then the probability that Template:Mvar is at least Template:Mvar is at most the expectation of Template:Mvar divided by Template:Mvar:<ref name=":0" />
- <math>\operatorname{P}(X \geq a) \leq \frac{\operatorname{E}(X)}{a}.</math>
When <math>\operatorname{E}(X) > 0</math>, we can take <math> a = \tilde{a} \cdot \operatorname{E}(X) </math> for <math> \tilde{a} > 0 </math> to rewrite the previous inequality as
- <math>\operatorname{P}(X \geq \tilde{a} \cdot \operatorname{E}(X)) \leq \frac{1}{\tilde{a}}.</math>
In the language of measure theory, Markov's inequality states that if Template:Math is a measure space, <math>f</math> is a measurable extended real-valued function, and Template:Math, then
- <math> \mu(\{x\in X:|f(x)|\geq \varepsilon \}) \leq \frac 1 \varepsilon \int_X |f|\,d\mu.</math>
This measure-theoretic definition is sometimes referred to as Chebyshev's inequality.<ref>Template:Citation.</ref>
Extended version for nondecreasing functionsEdit
If Template:Mvar is a nondecreasing nonnegative function, Template:Mvar is a (not necessarily nonnegative) random variable, and Template:Math, then<ref name=":1">Template:Cite book</ref>
- <math>\operatorname P (X \ge a) \le \frac{\operatorname E(\varphi(X))}{\varphi(a)}.</math>
An immediate corollary, using higher moments of Template:Mvar supported on values larger than 0, is
- <math>\operatorname P (|X| \ge a) \le \frac{\operatorname E(|X|^n)}{a^n}.</math>
The uniformly randomized Markov's inequalityEdit
If Template:Mvar is a nonnegative random variable and Template:Math, and Template:Mvar is a uniformly distributed random variable on <math>[0,1]</math> that is independent of Template:Mvar, then<ref>Template:Citation.</ref>
- <math>\operatorname{P}(X \geq Ua) \leq \frac{\operatorname{E}(X)}{a}.</math>
Since Template:Mvar is almost surely smaller than one, this bound is strictly stronger than Markov's inequality. Remarkably, Template:Mvar cannot be replaced by any constant smaller than one, meaning that deterministic improvements to Markov's inequality cannot exist in general. While Markov's inequality holds with equality for distributions supported on <math>\{0,a\}</math>, the above randomized variant holds with equality for any distribution that is bounded on <math>[0,a]</math>.
ProofsEdit
We separate the case in which the measure space is a probability space from the more general case because the probability case is more accessible for the general reader.
IntuitionEdit
<math>\operatorname{E}(X) = \operatorname{P}(X < a)\cdot \operatorname{E}(X|X<a) + \operatorname{P}(X \geq a)\cdot \operatorname{E}(X|X\geq a)</math> where <math>\operatorname{E}(X|X<a)</math> is larger than or equal to 0 as the random variable <math>X</math> is non-negative and <math>\operatorname{E}(X|X\geq a)</math> is larger than or equal to <math>a</math> because the conditional expectation only takes into account of values larger than or equal to <math>a</math> which r.v. <math>X</math> can take.
Property 1: <math>\operatorname{P}(X < a) \cdot \operatorname{E}(X \mid X < a) \geq 0</math>
Given a non-negative random variable <math>X</math>, the conditional expectation <math>\operatorname{E}(X \mid X < a) \geq 0</math> because <math>X \geq 0</math>. Also, probabilities are always non-negative, i.e., <math>\operatorname{P}(X < a) \geq 0</math>. Thus, the product:
<math>\operatorname{P}(X < a) \cdot \operatorname{E}(X \mid X < a) \geq 0</math>.
This is intuitive since conditioning on <math> X < a </math> still results in non-negative values, ensuring the product remains non-negative.
Property 2: <math>\operatorname{P}(X \geq a) \cdot \operatorname{E}(X \mid X \geq a) \geq a \cdot \operatorname{P}(X \geq a) </math>
For <math> X \geq a </math>, the expected value given <math> X \geq a</math> is at least <math> a. \operatorname{E}(X \mid X \geq a) \geq a </math>. Multiplying both sides by <math> \operatorname{P}(X \geq a) </math>, we get:
<math>\operatorname{P}(X \geq a) \cdot \operatorname{E}(X \mid X \geq a) \geq a \cdot \operatorname{P}(X \geq a)</math>.
This is intuitive since all values considered are at least <math>a</math>, making their average also greater than or equal to <math>a</math>.
Hence intuitively, <math>\operatorname{E}(X)\geq \operatorname{P}(X \geq a)\cdot \operatorname{E}(X|X\geq a)\geq a \cdot \operatorname{P}(X\geq a)</math>, which directly leads to <math>\operatorname{P}(X\geq a)\leq \frac{\operatorname{E}(X)}{a}</math>.
Probability-theoretic proofEdit
Method 1: From the definition of expectation:
- <math>\operatorname{E}(X)=\int_{-\infty}^{\infty} xf(x) \, dx</math>
However, X is a non-negative random variable thus,
- <math>\operatorname{E}(X)=\int_{-\infty}^\infty xf(x) \, dx = \int_0^\infty xf(x) \, dx </math>
From this we can derive,
- <math>\operatorname{E}(X)=\int_0^a xf(x) \, dx + \int_a^\infty xf(x) \, dx \ge \int_a^\infty xf(x) \, dx \ge\int_a^\infty af(x) \, dx = a\int_a^\infty f(x) \, dx= a \operatorname{Pr}(X \ge a)</math>
From here, dividing through by <math>a</math> allows us to see that
- <math>\Pr(X \ge a) \le \operatorname{E}(X)/a</math>
Method 2: For any event <math>E</math>, let <math>I_E</math> be the indicator random variable of <math> E </math>, that is, <math>I_E=1</math> if <math>E</math> occurs and <math>I_E=0</math> otherwise.
Using this notation, we have <math>I_{(X\geq a)}=1</math> if the event <math>X\geq a</math> occurs, and <math>I_{(X\geq a)}=0</math> if <math>X<a</math>. Then, given <math>a>0</math>,
- <math>aI_{(X \geq a)} \leq X</math>
which is clear if we consider the two possible values of <math>X\geq a</math>. If <math>X<a</math>, then <math>I_{(X\geq a)}=0</math>, and so <math>a I_{(X\geq a)}=0\leq X</math>. Otherwise, we have <math>X\geq a</math>, for which <math>I_{X\geq a}=1</math> and so <math>aI_{X\geq a}=a\leq X</math>.
Since <math>\operatorname{E}</math> is a monotonically increasing function, taking expectation of both sides of an inequality cannot reverse it. Therefore,
- <math>\operatorname{E}(aI_{(X \geq a)}) \leq \operatorname{E}(X).</math>
Now, using linearity of expectations, the left side of this inequality is the same as
- <math>a\operatorname{E}(I_{(X \geq a)}) = a(1\cdot\operatorname{P}(X \geq a) + 0\cdot\operatorname{P}(X < a)) = a\operatorname{P}(X \geq a).</math>
Thus we have
- <math>a\operatorname{P}(X \geq a) \leq \operatorname{E}(X)</math>
and since a > 0, we can divide both sides by a.
Measure-theoretic proofEdit
We may assume that the function <math>f</math> is non-negative, since only its absolute value enters in the equation. Now, consider the real-valued function s on X given by
- <math>
s(x) = \begin{cases}
\varepsilon, & \text{if } f(x) \geq \varepsilon \\ 0, & \text{if } f(x) < \varepsilon
\end{cases} </math>
Then <math>0\leq s(x)\leq f(x)</math>. By the definition of the Lebesgue integral
- <math>
\int_X f(x) \, d\mu \geq \int_X s(x) \, d \mu = \varepsilon \mu( \{ x\in X : \, f(x) \geq \varepsilon \} ) </math>
and since <math>\varepsilon >0 </math>, both sides can be divided by <math>\varepsilon</math>, obtaining
- <math>\mu(\{x\in X : \, f(x) \geq \varepsilon \}) \leq {1\over \varepsilon }\int_X f \,d\mu.</math>
Discrete caseEdit
We now provide a proof for the special case when <math>X</math> is a discrete random variable which only takes on non-negative integer values.
Let <math>a</math> be a positive integer. By definition <math>a\operatorname{Pr}(X > a)</math> <math>=a\operatorname{Pr}(X = a + 1) + a\operatorname{Pr}(X = a + 2) + a\operatorname{Pr}(X = a + 3) + ...</math> <math>\leq a\operatorname{Pr}(X = a) + (a+1)\operatorname{Pr}(X = a + 1) + (a+2)\operatorname{Pr}(X = a + 2) + ...</math> <math>\leq \operatorname{Pr}(X = 1) + 2\operatorname{Pr}(X = 2) + 3\operatorname{Pr}(X = 3) + ... </math> <math>+a\operatorname{Pr}(X = a ) + (a+1)\operatorname{Pr}(X = a + 1) + (a+2)\operatorname{Pr}(X = a + 2) + ...</math> <math>=\operatorname{E}(X)</math>
Dividing by <math>a</math> yields the desired result.
CorollariesEdit
Chebyshev's inequalityEdit
Chebyshev's inequality uses the variance to bound the probability that a random variable deviates far from the mean. Specifically,
- <math>\operatorname{P}(|X-\operatorname{E}(X)| \geq a) \leq \frac{\operatorname{Var}(X)}{a^2},</math>
for any Template:Math.<ref name=":1" /> Here Template:Math is the variance of X, defined as:
- <math> \operatorname{Var}(X) = \operatorname{E}[(X - \operatorname{E}(X) )^2]. </math>
Chebyshev's inequality follows from Markov's inequality by considering the random variable
- <math> (X - \operatorname{E}(X))^2 </math>
and the constant <math>a^2,</math> for which Markov's inequality reads
- <math> \operatorname{P}( (X - \operatorname{E}(X))^2 \ge a^2) \le \frac{\operatorname{Var}(X)}{a^2}.</math>
This argument can be summarized (where "MI" indicates use of Markov's inequality):
- <math>\operatorname{P}(|X-\operatorname{E}(X)| \geq a) =
\operatorname{P}\left((X-\operatorname{E}(X))^2 \geq a^2\right) \,\overset{\underset{\mathrm{MI}}{}}{\leq}\, \frac {\operatorname{E} \left( (X-\operatorname{E}(X))^2 \right)}{a^2} = \frac{\operatorname{Var}(X)}{a^2}.</math>
Other corollariesEdit
- The "monotonic" result can be demonstrated by:
- <math>\operatorname P (|X| \ge a) = \operatorname P \big(\varphi(|X|) \ge \varphi(a)\big) \,\overset{\underset{\mathrm{MI}}{}}{\leq}\,
\frac{\operatorname E(\varphi(|X|))}{\varphi(a)}</math>
- The result that, for a nonnegative random variable Template:Mvar, the quantile function of Template:Mvar satisfies:
- <math>Q_X(1-p) \leq \frac {\operatorname E(X)}{p},</math>
- the proof using
- <math>p \leq \operatorname P(X \geq Q_X(1-p)) \,\overset{\underset{\mathrm{MI}}{}}{\leq}\, \frac {\operatorname E(X)}{Q_X(1-p)}.</math>
- Let <math> M \succeq 0 </math> be a self-adjoint matrix-valued random variable and <math> A \succ 0 </math>. Then
- <math>
\operatorname{P}(M \npreceq A) \leq \operatorname{tr}(\operatorname E (X) A^{-1}) </math>
- which can be proved similarly.<ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation
|CitationClass=web }}</ref>
ExamplesEdit
Assuming no income is negative, Markov's inequality shows that no more than 10% (1/10) of the population can have more than 10 times the average income.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
Another simple example is as follows: Andrew makes 4 mistakes on average on his Statistics course tests. The best upper bound on the probability that Andrew will do at least 10 mistakes is 0.4 as <math>\operatorname{P}(X \geq 10) \leq \frac{\operatorname{E}(X)}{\alpha} = \frac{4}{10}.</math> Note that Andrew might do exactly 10 mistakes with probability 0.4 and make no mistakes with probability 0.6; the expectation is exactly 4 mistakes.
See alsoEdit
- Paley–Zygmund inequality – a corresponding lower bound
- Concentration inequality – a summary of tail-bounds on random variables.