Material conditional
Template:Short description Template:Redirect Template:Distinguish Template:Infobox logical connective Template:Logical connectives sidebar The material conditional (also known as material implication) is a binary operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol <math>\to</math> is interpreted as material implication, a formula <math> P \to Q</math> is true unless <math>P</math> is true and <math>Q</math> is false.
Material implication is used in all the basic systems of classical logic as well as some nonclassical logics. It is assumed as a model of correct conditional reasoning within mathematics and serves as the basis for commands in many programming languages. However, many logics replace material implication with other operators such as the strict conditional and the variably strict conditional. Due to the paradoxes of material implication and related problems, material implication is not generally considered a viable analysis of conditional sentences in natural language.
NotationEdit
In logic and related fields, the material conditional is customarily notated with an infix operator <math>\to</math>.Template:Sfn The material conditional is also notated using the infixes <math>\supset</math> and <math>\Rightarrow</math>.Template:Sfn In the prefixed Polish notation, conditionals are notated as <math>Cpq</math>. In a conditional formula <math>p\to q</math>, the subformula <math>p</math> is referred to as the antecedent and <math>q</math> is termed the consequent of the conditional. Conditional statements may be nested such that the antecedent or the consequent may themselves be conditional statements, as in the formula <math>(p\to q)\to(r\to s)</math>.
HistoryEdit
In Arithmetices Principia: Nova Methodo Exposita (1889), Peano expressed the proposition "If <math>A</math>, then <math>B</math>" as <math>A</math> Ɔ <math>B</math> with the symbol Ɔ, which is the opposite of C.Template:Sfn He also expressed the proposition <math>A\supset B</math> as <math>A</math> Ɔ <math>B</math>.<ref>Note that the horseshoe symbol Ɔ has been flipped to become a subset symbol ⊂.</ref>Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Hilbert expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as <math>A\to B</math> in 1918.Template:Sfn Russell followed Peano in his Principia Mathematica (1910–1913), in which he expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as <math>A\supset B</math>. Following Russell, Gentzen expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as <math>A\supset B</math>. Heyting expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as <math>A\supset B</math> at first but later came to express it as <math>A\to B</math> with a right-pointing arrow. Bourbaki expressed the proposition "If A, then B" as <math>A \to B</math> in 1954.Template:Sfn
SemanticsEdit
Truth tableEdit
From a classical semantic perspective, material implication is the binary truth functional operator which returns "true" unless its first argument is true and its second argument is false. This semantics can be shown graphically in the following truth table: Template:2-ary truth table One can also consider the equivalence <math>A \to B \equiv \neg (A \land \neg B) \equiv \neg A \lor B</math>.
The conditionals <math>(A \to B)</math> where the antecedent <math>A</math> is false, are called "vacuous truths". Examples are ...
- ... with <math>B</math> false: "If Marie Curie is a sister of Galileo Galilei, then Galileo Galilei is a brother of Marie Curie."
- ... with <math>B</math> true: "If Marie Curie is a sister of Galileo Galilei, then Marie Curie has a sibling."
Analytic tableauxEdit
Template:Further Formulas over the set of connectives <math>\{\to, \bot\}</math><ref>The well-formed formulas are:
- Each propositional variable is a formula.
- "<math>\bot</math>" is a formula.
- If <math>A</math> and <math>B</math> are formulas, so is <math>(A \to B)</math>.
- Nothing else is a formula.</ref> are called f-implicational.Template:Sfn In classical logic the other connectives, such as <math>\neg</math> (negation), <math>\land</math> (conjunction), <math>\lor</math> (disjunction) and <math>\leftrightarrow</math> (equivalence), can be defined in terms of <math>\to</math> and <math>\bot</math> (falsity):<ref name="connective_needed">f-implicational formulas cannot express all valid formulas in minimal (MPC) or intuitionistic (IPC) propositional logic — in particular, <math>\lor</math> (disjunction) cannot be defined within it. In contrast, <math>\{\to, \lor, \bot \}</math> is a complete basis for MPC / IPC: from these, all other connectives (e.g., <math>\land, \neg, \leftrightarrow, \bot</math>) can be defined.</ref>
<math display="block"> \begin{align} \neg A & \quad \overset{\text{def}}{=} \quad A \to \bot \\ A \land B & \quad \overset{\text{def}}{=} \quad (A \to (B \to \bot)) \to \bot \\ A \lor B & \quad \overset{\text{def}}{=} \quad (A \to \bot) \to B \\ A \leftrightarrow B & \quad \overset{\text{def}}{=} \quad \{(A \to B) \to [(B \to A) \to \bot]\} \to \bot \\ \end{align} </math>
The validity of f-implicational formulas can be semantically established by the method of analytic tableaux. The logical rules are
<math>\frac{\boldsymbol{\mathsf{T}}(A \to B)}{\boldsymbol{\mathsf{F}}(A) \quad \mid \quad \boldsymbol{\mathsf{T}}(B)}</math> || valign="top" | <math>\frac{\boldsymbol{\mathsf{F}}(A \to B)}{\begin{array}{c} \boldsymbol{\mathsf{T}}(A) \\ \boldsymbol{\mathsf{F}}(B)\end{array}}</math>
<math>\boldsymbol{\mathsf{T}}(\bot)</math> : Close the branch (contradiction)
<math>\boldsymbol{\mathsf{F}}(\bot)</math> : Do nothing (since it just asserts no contradiction)
F[p → ((p → ⊥) → ⊥)] | T[p] F[(p → ⊥) → ⊥] | T[p → ⊥] F[⊥] ┌────────┴────────┐ F[p] T[⊥] | | CONTRADICTION CONTRADICTION (T[p], F[p]) (⊥ is true)
F[((p → ⊥) → ⊥) → p] | T[(p → ⊥) → ⊥] F[p] ┌────────┴────────┐ F[p → ⊥] T[⊥] | | T[p] CONTRADICTION (⊥ is true) F[⊥] | CONTRADICTION (T[p], F[p])
Hilbert-style proofs can be found here or here. Template:Collapse bottom
1. F[(p → q) → ((q → r) → (p → r))] | // from 1 2. T[p → q] 3. F[(q → r) → (p → r)] | // from 3 4. T[q → r] 5. F[p → r] | // from 5 6. T[p] 7. F[r] ┌────────┴────────┐ // from 2 8a. F[p] 8b. T[q] X ┌────────┴────────┐ // from 4 9a. F[q] 9b. T[r] X X
A Hilbert-style proof can be found here. Template:Collapse bottom
Syntactical propertiesEdit
Template:Further The semantic definition by truth tables does not permit the examination of structurally identical propositional forms in various logical systems, where different properties may be demonstrated. The language considered here is restricted to f-implicational formulas.
Consider the following (candidate) natural deduction rules.
Implication Introduction (<math>\to</math>I)
If assuming <math>A</math> one can derive <math>B</math>, then one can conclude <math>A \to B</math>. <math> \frac{\begin{array}{c} [A] \\ \vdots \\ B \end{array}}{A \to B}</math> (<math>\to</math>I) <math>[A]</math> is an assumption that is discharged when applying the rule. |
Implication Elimination (<math>\to</math>E)
This rule corresponds to modus ponens. <math>\frac{A \to B \quad A}{B}</math> (<math>\to</math>E)
|
Double Negation Elimination (<math>\neg\neg</math>E)
|
Falsum Elimination (<math>\bot</math>E)
From falsum (<math>\bot</math>) one can derive any formula. <math>\frac{\bot}{A}</math> (<math>\bot</math>E) |
- Minimal logic: By limiting the natural deduction rules to Implication Introduction (<math>\to</math>I) and Implication Elimination (<math>\to</math>E), one obtains (the implicational fragment of)<ref name="connective_needed"/> minimal logic (as defined by Johansson).Template:Sfn
1.Template:Spaces | [ P ] | Template:Spaces// Assume |
2.Template:Spaces | [ P → ⊥ ] | Template:Spaces// Assume |
3.Template:Spaces | ⊥ | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>E (1, 2) |
4.Template:Spaces | (P → ⊥) → ⊥) | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>I (2, 3), discharging 2 |
5.Template:Spaces | P → ((P → ⊥) → ⊥) | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>I (1, 4), discharging 1 |
- Intuitionistic logic: By adding Falsum Elimination (<math>\bot</math>E) as a rule, one obtains (the implicational fragment of)<ref name="connective_needed"/> intuitionistic logic.
- The statement <math>P \to \neg \neg P</math> is valid (already in minimal logic), unlike the reverse implication which would entail the law of excluded middle.
- Classical logic: If Double Negation Elimination (<math>\neg\neg</math>E) is also permitted,Template:Refn{A}</math> (RAA)}} the system defines (full!) classical logic.Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn
A selection of theorems (classical logic)Edit
In classical logic material implication validates the following:
1.Template:Spaces | [ (Q → ⊥) → (P → ⊥) ] | Template:Spaces// Assume (to discharge at 9) |
2.Template:Spaces | [ P ] | Template:Spaces// Assume (to discharge at 8) |
3.Template:Spaces | [ Q → ⊥ ] | Template:Spaces// Assume (to discharge at 6)) |
4.Template:Spaces | P → ⊥ | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>E (1, 3) |
5.Template:Spaces | ⊥ | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>E (2, 4) |
6.Template:Spaces | (Q → ⊥) → ⊥ | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>I (3, 5) (discharging 3) |
7.Template:Spaces | Q | Template:Spaces// <math>\neg\neg</math>E (6) |
8.Template:Spaces | P → Q | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>I (2, 7) (discharging 2) |
9.Template:Spaces | ((Q → ⊥) → (P → ⊥)) → (P → Q) | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>I (1, 8) (discharging 1) |
1.Template:Spaces | [ (P → Q) → P ] | Template:Spaces// Assume (to discharge at 11) |
2.Template:Spaces | [ P → ⊥ ] | Template:Spaces// Assume (to discharge at 9) |
3.Template:Spaces | [ P ] | Template:Spaces// Assume (to discharge at 6) |
4.Template:Spaces | ⊥ | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>E (2, 3) |
5.Template:Spaces | Q | Template:Spaces// <math>\bot</math>E (4) |
6.Template:Spaces | P → Q | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>I (3, 5) (discharging 3) |
7.Template:Spaces | P | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>E (1, 6) |
8.Template:Spaces | ⊥ | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>E (2, 7) |
9.Template:Spaces | (P → ⊥) → ⊥ | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>I (2, 8) (discharging 2) |
10.Template:Spaces | P | Template:Spaces// <math>\neg \neg</math>E (9) |
11.Template:Spaces | ((P → Q) → P) → P | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>I (1, 10) (discharging 1) |
1.Template:Spaces | <math>[ P \to \bot ]</math> | Template:Spaces// Assume |
2.Template:Spaces | <math>[ P ]</math> | Template:Spaces// Assume |
3.Template:Spaces | <math>\bot</math> | Template:Spaces// <math>\to</math>E (1, 2) |
4.Template:Spaces | <math>Q</math> | Template:Spaces// <math>\bot</math>E (3) |
5.Template:Spaces | <math>P \to Q</math> | Template:Spaces// <math>\to </math>I (2, 4) (discharging 2) |
6.Template:Spaces | <math>( P \to \bot ) \to ( P \to Q )</math> | Template:Spaces// <math>\to </math>I (1, 5) (discharging 1) |
- Import-export: <math>P \to (Q \to R) \equiv (P \land Q) \to R</math>
- Negated conditionals: <math>\neg(P \to Q) \equiv P \land \neg Q</math>
- Or-and-if: <math>P \to Q \equiv \neg P \lor Q</math>
- Commutativity of antecedents: <math>\big(P \to (Q \to R)\big) \equiv \big(Q \to (P \to R)\big)</math>
- Left distributivity: <math>\big(R \to (P \to Q)\big) \equiv \big((R \to P) \to (R \to Q)\big)</math>
Similarly, on classical interpretations of the other connectives, material implication validates the following entailments:
- Antecedent strengthening: <math>P \to Q \models (P \land R) \to Q</math>
- Transitivity: <math>(P \to Q) \land (Q \to R) \models P \to R</math>
- Simplification of disjunctive antecedents: <math>(P \lor Q) \to R \models (P \to R) \land (Q \to R)</math>
Tautologies involving material implication include:
- Reflexivity: <math>\models P \to P</math>
- Totality: <math>\models (P \to Q) \lor (Q \to P)</math>
- Conditional excluded middle: <math>\models (P \to Q) \lor (P \to \neg Q)</math>
Discrepancies with natural languageEdit
Material implication does not closely match the usage of conditional sentences in natural language. For example, even though material conditionals with false antecedents are vacuously true, the natural language statement "If 8 is odd, then 3 is prime" is typically judged false. Similarly, any material conditional with a true consequent is itself true, but speakers typically reject sentences such as "If I have a penny in my pocket, then Paris is in France". These classic problems have been called the paradoxes of material implication.Template:Sfn In addition to the paradoxes, a variety of other arguments have been given against a material implication analysis. For instance, counterfactual conditionals would all be vacuously true on such an account, when in fact some are false.Template:Refn
In the mid-20th century, a number of researchers including H. P. Grice and Frank Jackson proposed that pragmatic principles could explain the discrepancies between natural language conditionals and the material conditional. On their accounts, conditionals denote material implication but end up conveying additional information when they interact with conversational norms such as Grice's maxims.Template:SfnTemplate:Sfn Recent work in formal semantics and philosophy of language has generally eschewed material implication as an analysis for natural-language conditionals.Template:Sfn In particular, such work has often rejected the assumption that natural-language conditionals are truth functional in the sense that the truth value of "If P, then Q" is determined solely by the truth values of P and Q.Template:Sfn Thus semantic analyses of conditionals typically propose alternative interpretations built on foundations such as modal logic, relevance logic, probability theory, and causal models.Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn
Similar discrepancies have been observed by psychologists studying conditional reasoning, for instance, by the notorious Wason selection task study, where less than 10% of participants reasoned according to the material conditional. Some researchers have interpreted this result as a failure of the participants to conform to normative laws of reasoning, while others interpret the participants as reasoning normatively according to nonclassical laws.Template:SfnTemplate:SfnTemplate:Sfn
See alsoEdit
- Boolean domain
- Boolean function
- Boolean logic
- Conditional quantifier
- Implicational propositional calculus
- Laws of Form
- Logical graph
- Logical equivalence
- Material implication (rule of inference)
- Peirce's law
- Propositional calculus
- Sole sufficient operator
ConditionalsEdit
NotesEdit
BibliographyEdit
- {{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation
|CitationClass=web }}
- {{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation
|CitationClass=web }}
Further readingEdit
- Brown, Frank Markham (2003), Boolean Reasoning: The Logic of Boolean Equations, 1st edition, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Norwell, MA. 2nd edition, Dover Publications, Mineola, NY, 2003.
- Edgington, Dorothy (2001), "Conditionals", in Lou Goble (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic, Blackwell.
- Quine, W.V. (1982), Methods of Logic, (1st ed. 1950), (2nd ed. 1959), (3rd ed. 1972), 4th edition, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
- Stalnaker, Robert, "Indicative Conditionals", Philosophia, 5 (1975): 269–286.
External linksEdit
Template:Logical connectives Template:Common logical symbols Template:Mathematical logic