Norman Malcolm
Template:Short description Template:For Template:For Template:Infobox philosopher Template:Wittgenstein Norman Adrian Malcolm (Template:IPAc-en; 11 June 1911 – 4 August 1990) was an American philosopher. Malcolm was primarily active in the fields of epistemology, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of psychology.
BiographyEdit
Malcolm was born in Selden, Kansas. He studied philosophy with O. K. Bouwsma at the University of Nebraska, then enrolled as a graduate student at Harvard University in 1933.
At Cambridge University in 1938–9, he met G. E. Moore and Ludwig Wittgenstein. Malcolm attended Wittgenstein's lectures on the philosophical foundations of mathematics throughout 1939 and remained one of Wittgenstein's closest friends. Malcolm's memoir of his time with Wittgenstein, published in 1958, is widely acclaimed as one of the most captivating and most accurate portraits of Wittgenstein's remarkable personality.
After serving in the United States Navy from 1942 to 1945, Malcolm, with his wife, Leonida, and their son, Raymond Charles Malcolm, resided in Cambridge again in 1946–47. He saw a good deal of Wittgenstein during that time, and they continued to correspond frequently thereafter. In 1947, Malcolm joined the faculty at Cornell University, where he taught until his retirement. In 1949, Wittgenstein was a guest of the Malcolms in Ithaca, New York. In that year Malcolm introduced O. K. Bouwsma to Wittgenstein. Bouwsma remained close to Wittgenstein until Wittgenstein's death in 1951.
Malcolm was a Fulbright research fellow at University of Helsinki during the academic year of 1960-1961.<ref>Template:Cite book</ref> From 1972-73 he was President of the Eastern Division of the American Philosophical Association and in 1975 joined the American Academy of Arts and Sciences.<ref name=blooms>Template:Cite book</ref> he died in London England in 1990
Philosophical workEdit
In 1959, his book Dreaming was published, in which he elaborated on Wittgenstein's question as to whether it really mattered if people who tell dreams "really had these images while they slept, or whether it merely seems so to them on waking". This work was also a response to Descartes' Meditations.<ref>Pastor, Rebecca. "Norman Malcolm's Critique of Descartes' Skepticism"</ref>
Other than that he is known for propagating the view that common sense philosophy and ordinary language philosophy are the same. He was generally supportive of Moore's theory of knowledge and certitude, though he found Moore's style and method of arguing to be ineffective.<ref>Norman Malcolm (1952), "Moore and Ordinary Language", The Philosophy of G. E. Moore</ref> His critique of Moore's articles on skepticism (and also on Moore's 'Here is a hand' argument) lay the foundation for the renewed interest in common sense philosophy and ordinary language philosophy.<ref>Scott Soames (2003) "Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century, Volume II: The Age of Meaning." Chapter 7</ref> He was among the most important and influential of the ordinary-language philosophers in the United States.<ref name=blooms/>
Malcolm was also a defender of a modal version of the ontological argument. In 1960 he argued that the argument originally presented by Anselm of Canterbury in the second chapter of his Proslogion was just an inferior version of the argument propounded in chapter three.<ref>Norman Malcolm (1960), "Anselm's Ontological Arguments," Philosophical Review, 69:41–62.</ref><ref>{{#invoke:citation/CS1|citation |CitationClass=web }}</ref> His argument is similar to those produced by Charles Hartshorne and Alvin Plantinga. Malcolm argued that a God cannot simply exist as a matter of contingency but rather must exist in necessity if at all. He argued that if God exists in contingency then his existence is subject to a series of conditions that would then be greater than God and this would be a contradiction (referring to Anselm's definition of God as That than which Nothing Greater can be Conceived).
PublicationsEdit
BooksEdit
- Ludwig Wittgenstein: A Memoir (with a biographical sketch by G. H. von Wright)<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- Wittgenstein: A Religious Point Of View? (edited by Peter Winch) <ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>{{#invoke:doi|main}} Template:ISBN
- Nothing Is Hidden: Wittgenstein's criticism of his early thought<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- Problems of Mind: Descartes to Wittgenstein Template:ISBN<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- Consciousness and Causality (with D. M. Armstrong)<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- Memory and Mind Template:ISBN<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- Wittgenstein: The Relation of Language to Instinctive Behaviour (J.R.Jones Memorial Lecture) Publisher: University of Wales, Swansea (Dec 1981) Template:ISBN<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- Thought and Knowledge: Essay by Norman Malcolm {{#invoke:doi|main}} Template:ISBN
- Wittgensteinian themes: essays, 1978-1989 (edited by G. H. von Wright)<ref>Template:Cite book</ref>
- Dreaming.<ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref><ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
- Knowledge and Certainty: Essays and Lectures <ref>Template:Cite journal</ref>
EssaysEdit
Template:Col-begin Template:Col-2
- Are Necessary Propositions Really Verbal? (1940) in Mind, Vol. 49, No. 194 (Apr., 1940), pp. 189-203 .
- Certainty and Empirical Statements (1942) in Mind, Vol. 51, No. 201 (Jan., 1942), pp. 18-46.
- The Nature of Entailment (1940) in Mind, Vol. 49, No. 195 (Jul., 1940), pp. 333-347.
- Defending Common Sense (1949) in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 58, No. 3 (May, 1949), pp. 201-220.
- Russell's Human Knowledge (1950), in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 59, No. 1 (Jan., 1950), pp. 94-106.
- Philosophy for Philosophers (1951) in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 60, No. 3 (Jul., 1951), pp. 329-340.
- Knowledge and Belief (1952), in Mind, New Series, Vol. 61, No. 242 (Apr., 1952), pp. 178-189.
- Moore's Use of "Know" (1953), in Mind, Vol. 62, No. 246 (Apr., 1953), pp. 241-247.
- Direct Perception (1953), in The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 3, No. 13 (Oct., 1953), pp. 301-316.
- On Knowledge and Belief (1954) in Analysis, Vol. 14, No. 4 (Mar., 1954), pp. 94-98.
- Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations (1954) in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 63, No. 4 (Oct., 1954), pp. 530-559.
- Dreaming and Skepticism (1956), in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 65, No. 1 (Jan., 1956), pp. 14-37.
- Knowledge of Other Minds (1958) in The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 55, No. 23, pp. 969-978.
- Anselm's Ontological Arguments (1960) in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 69, No. 1 (Jan., 1960), pp. 41-62.
- Professor Ayer on Dreaming (1961) in The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 58, No. 11 (May 25, 1961), pp. 294-297.
- Scientific Materialism and the Identity Theory: Comments in The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 60, No. 22, American Philosophical Association, Eastern Division, Sixtieth Annual Meeting (Oct. 24, 1963), pp. 662-663.
- Memory and the Past (1963) in The Monist, Vol. 47, No. 2, Metaphysics Today (Winter, 1963), pp. 247-266.
- Moore and Ordinary Language (1964) in V.C. Chappell (ed.) Ordinary Language: Essays in Philosophical Method.
- Is it a Religious Belief that ‘God Exists’? (1964) in John Hick (ed.) Faith and the Philosophers.
- Descartes's Proof that his Essence is Thinking in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 74, No. 3 (Jul., 1965), pp. 315-338
- Explaining Behaviour (1967), in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 76, No. 1 (Jan., 1967), pp. 97-104.
- Wittgenstein's Philosophische Bermerkungen (1967) in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 76, No. 2 (Apr., 1967), pp. 220-229.
- The Conceivability of the Mechanism (1968), in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 77, No. 1 (Jan., 1968), pp. 45-72.
- Memory and Representation (1970) in Noûs, Vol. 4, No. 1 (Feb., 1970), pp. 59-70.
- Thoughtless Brutes (1972) in Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, Vol. 46 (1972 - 1973), pp. 5-20.
- The Groundlessness of Belief (1975) in Stuart Brown (ed.) Reason and Religion.
- 'Functionalism' in Philosophy of Psychology (1980), Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 80 (1979 - 1980), pp. 211-229.
- Subjectivity (1988) in Philosophy, Vol. 63, No. 244 (Apr., 1988), pp. 147-160.
- Wittgenstein on Language and Rules (1989) in Philosophy, Vol. 64, No. 247 (Jan., 1989), pp. 5-28.
ReviewsEdit
- The Rise of Scientific Philosophy by Hans Reichenbach (1951), in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 60, No. 4 (Oct., 1951), pp. 582-586.
- English Philosophy Since 1900 by G. J. Warnock (1959), in The Philosophical Review, Vol. 68, No. 2 (Apr., 1959), pp. 256-258.
- Meaning and Saying by Frank B. Ebersole; Language and Perception by Frank B. Ebersole (1980) in Philosophy, Vol. 55, No. 214 (ct., 1980), pp. 555-557.
- "Wittgenstein and the Simple Object". London Review of Books. Vol.2, no. 3., 21 February 1980
- "Wittgenstein's Bag of Raisins". London Review of Books. Vol.3, No.3, 19 February 1981
- "Wittgenstein's Confessions". London Review of Books. Vol.. 3, No. 21, 19 November 1981
ReferencesEdit
Further readingEdit
- Template:Cite journal
- Ginet, C. (2001). "Norman Malcolm (1911–1990)" in A Companion to Analytic Philosophy (eds A.P. Martinich and D. Sosa).
External linksEdit
- McDonough, Richard (2017). "Norman Malcolm" Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.